Cicero’s Tusculan Disputations, On the Nature of the Gods, On the Commonwealth
Project Gutenberg's Cicero's Tusculan Disputations, by Marcus Tullius Cicero
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net
Title: Cicero's Tusculan Disputations
Also, Treatises On The Nature Of The Gods, And On The Commonwealth
Author: Marcus Tullius Cicero
Release Date: February 9, 2005 [EBook #14988]
Language: English and Latin
Character set encoding: ISO-8859-1
*** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK CICERO'S TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS ***
Produced by Ted Garvin, Hagen von Eitzen and the PG Online Distributed
Proofreading Team.
CICERO’S
TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS;
В
ALSO, TREATISES ON
THE NATURE OF THE GODS,
AND ON
THE COMMONWEALTH.
В
LITERALLY TRANSLATED, CHIEFLY BY
C. D. YONGE.
NEW YORK:
HARPER & BROTHERS, PUBLISHERS,
FRANKLIN SQUARE.
1877.
2HARPER’S
NEW CLASSICAL LIBRARY.
COMPRISING LITERAL TRANSLATIONS OF
CÆSAR.
VIRGIL.
SALLUST.
HORACE.
CICERO’S ORATIONS.
CICERO’S OFFICES &c.
CICERO ON ORATORY AND ORATORS.
CICERO’S TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS, the Republic, and the Nature of the Gods.
TERENCE.
TACITUS.
LIVY. 2 Vols.
JUVENAL.
XENOPHON.
HOMER’S ILIAD.
HOMER’S ODYSSEY.
HERODOTUS.
DEMOSTHENES. 2 Vols.
THUCIDIDES.
Г†SCHYLUS.
SOPHOCLES.
EURIPIDES. 2 Vols.
PLATO. [Select Dialogues.]
12mo, Cloth, $1.50 per Volume.
Harper & Brothers will send either of the above works by mail, postage
prepaid, to any part of the United States, on receipt of the price.
3NOTE.
The greater portion of the Republic was previously translated by Francis
Barham, Esq., and published in 1841. Although ably performed, it was not
sufficiently close for the purpose of the “
Classical Library,” and was
therefore placed in the hands of the present editor for revision, as
well as for collation with recent texts. This has occasioned material
alterations and additions.
The treatise “On the Nature of the Gods” is a revision of that usually
ascribed to the celebrated Benjamin Franklin.
5CONTENTS.
Tusculan Disputations
On the Nature of the Gods
On the Commonwealth
7THE TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS.
INTRODUCTION.
In the year
a.u.c. 708, and the sixty-second year of Cicero’s age, his
daughter, Tullia, died in childbed; and her loss afflicted Cicero to
such a degree that he abandoned all public business, and, leaving the
city, retired to Asterra, which was a country house that he had near
Antium; where, after a while, he devoted himself to philosophical
studies, and, besides other works, he published his Treatise de Finibus,
and also this treatise called the Tusculan Disputations, of which
Middleton gives this concise description:
“The first book teaches us how to contemn the terrors of death, and to
look upon it as a blessing rather than an evil;
“The second, to support pain and affliction with a manly fortitude;
“The third, to appease all our complaints and uneasinesses under the
accidents of life;
“The fourth, to moderate all our other passions;
“And the fifth explains the sufficiency of virtue to make men happy.”
It was his custom in the opportunities of his leisure to take some
friends with him into the country, where, instead of amusing themselves
with idle sports or feasts, their diversions were wholly speculative,
tending to improve the mind and enlarge the understanding. In this
manner he now spent five days at his Tusculan villa in discussing with
his friends the several questions just mentioned. For, after employing
the mornings in declaiming and rhetorical exercises, they used to retire
in the afternoon
8into a gallery, called the Academy, which he had built
for the purpose of philosophical conferences, where, after the manner of
the Greeks, he held a school, as they called it, and invited the company
to call for any subject that they desired to hear explained, which being
proposed accordingly by some of the audience became immediately the
argument of that day’s debate. These five conferences, or dialogues, he
collected afterward into writing in the very words and manner in which
they really passed; and published them under the title of his Tusculan
Disputations, from the name of the villa in which they were held.
BOOK I.
ON THE CONTEMPT OF DEATH.
I.
At a time when I had entirely, or to a great degree, released myself
from my labors as an advocate, and from my duties as a senator, I had
recourse again, Brutus, principally by your advice, to those studies
which never had been out of my mind, although neglected at times, and
which after a long interval I resumed; and now, since the principles and
rules of all arts which relate to living well depend on the study of
wisdom, which is called philosophy, I have thought it an employment
worthy of me to illustrate them in the Latin tongue, not because
philosophy could not be understood in the Greek language, or by the
teaching of Greek masters; but it has always been my opinion that our
countrymen have, in some instances, made wiser discoveries than the
Greeks, with reference to those subjects which they have considered
worthy of devoting their attention to, and in others have improved upon
their discoveries, so that in one way or other we surpass them on every
point; for, with regard to the manners and habits of private life, and
family and domestic affairs, we certainly manage them with more
elegance, and better than they did; and as to our republic, that our
ancestors have, beyond all dispute, formed on better customs and laws.
What shall I say of our military affairs; in which our ancestors have
been most eminent in valor, and still more so
9in discipline? As to
those things which are attained not by study, but nature, neither
Greece, nor any nation, is comparable to us; for what people has
displayed such gravity, such steadiness, such greatness of soul,
probity, faith—such distinguished virtue of every kind, as to be equal
to our ancestors. In learning, indeed, and all kinds of literature,
Greece did excel us, and it was easy to do so where there was no
competition; for while among the Greeks the poets were the most ancient
species of learned men—since Homer and Hesiod lived before the
foundation of Rome, and Archilochus
1 was a contemporary of Romulus—we
received poetry much later. For it was about five hundred and ten years
after the building of Rome before Livius
2 published a play in the
consulship of C. Claudius, the son of Cæcus, and M. Tuditanus, a year
before the birth of Ennius, who was older than Plautus and Nævius.
II. It was, therefore, late before poets were either known or received
among us; though we find in Cato de Originibus that the guests used, at
their entertainments, to sing the praises of famous men to the sound of
the flute; but a speech of Cato’s shows this kind of poetry to have been
in no great esteem, as he censures Marcus Nobilior for carrying poets
with him into his province; for that consul, as we know, carried Ennius
with him into Г†tolia. Therefore the less esteem poets were in, the less
were
10those studies pursued; though even then those who did display the
greatest abilities that way were not very inferior to the Greeks. Do we
imagine that if it had been considered commendable in Fabius,
3 a man
of the highest rank, to paint, we should not have had many Polycleti and
Parrhasii? Honor nourishes art, and glory is the spur with all to
studies; while those studies are always neglected in every nation which
are looked upon disparagingly. The Greeks held skill in vocal and
instrumental music as a very important accomplishment, and therefore it
is recorded of Epaminondas, who, in my opinion, was the greatest man
among the Greeks, that he played excellently on the flute; and
Themistocles, some years before, was deemed ignorant because at an
entertainment he declined the lyre when it was offered to him. For this
reason musicians flourished in Greece; music was a general study; and
whoever was unacquainted with it was not considered as fully instructed
in learning. Geometry was in high esteem with them, therefore none were
more honorable than mathematicians. But we have confined this art to
bare measuring and calculating.
III. But, on the contrary, we early entertained an esteem for the
orator; though he was not at first a man of learning, but only quick at
speaking: in subsequent times he became learned; for it is reported that
Galba, Africanus, and Lælius were men of learning; and that even Cato,
who preceded them in point of time, was a studious man: then succeeded
the Lepidi, Carbo, and Gracchi, and so many great orators after them,
down to our own times, that we were very little, if at all, inferior to
the Greeks. Philosophy has been at a low ebb even to this present time,
and has had no assistance from our own language, and so now I have
undertaken to raise and illustrate it, in order that, as I have been of
service to my countrymen, when employed on public affairs, I may, if
possible, be so likewise in my retirement; and in this I must take the
more pains, because there are already many books in the
11Latin language
which are said to be written inaccurately, having been composed by
excellent men, only not of sufficient learning; for, indeed, it is
possible that a man may think well, and yet not be able to express his
thoughts elegantly; but for any one to publish thoughts which he can
neither arrange skilfully nor illustrate so as to entertain his reader,
is an unpardonable abuse of letters and retirement: they, therefore,
read their books to one another, and no one ever takes them up but those
who wish to have the same license for careless writing allowed to
themselves. Wherefore, if oratory has acquired any reputation from my
industry, I shall take the more pains to open the fountains of
philosophy, from which all my eloquence has taken its rise.
IV. But, as Aristotle,
4 a man of the greatest genius, and of the most
various knowledge, being excited by the glory of the rhetorician
Isocrates,
5 commenced teaching young men to speak, and joined
philosophy with eloquence: so it is my design not to lay aside my former
study of oratory, and yet to employ myself at the same time in this
greater and more fruitful art; for I have always thought that to be able
to speak copiously and elegantly on the most important questions was the
most perfect philosophy. And I have so diligently applied myself to this
pursuit, that I have already ventured to have a school like the Greeks.
And lately when you left us, having many of my friends about me, I
attempted at my Tusculan villa what I could do in that way; for as I
formerly used to practise declaiming, which nobody continued longer than
myself, so this is now to be the declamation of my old age. I desired
any one to propose a question which he wished to have discussed, and
then I argued that point either sitting or walking; and so I have
compiled the scholæ, as the Greeks call them, of five days, in as many
books. We proceeded in this manner: when he who had proposed the subject
for discussion had said what he thought proper, I
12spoke against him;
for this is, you know, the old and Socratic method of arguing against
another’s opinion; for Socrates thought that thus the truth would more
easily be arrived at. But to give you a better notion of our
disputations, I will not barely send you an account of them, but
represent them to you as they were carried on; therefore let the
introduction be thus:
V.
A. To me death seems to be an evil.
M. What, to those who are already dead? or to those who must die?
A. To both.
M. It is a misery, then, because an evil?
A. Certainly.
M. Then those who have already died, and those who have still got to
die, are both miserable?
A. So it appears to me.
M. Then all are miserable?
A. Every one.
M. And, indeed, if you wish to be consistent, all that are already
born, or ever shall be, are not only miserable, but always will be so;
for should you maintain those only to be miserable, you would not except
any one living, for all must die; but there should be an end of misery
in death. But seeing that the dead are miserable, we are born to eternal
misery, for they must of consequence be miserable who died a hundred
thousand years ago; or rather, all that have ever been born.
A. So, indeed, I think.
M. Tell me, I beseech you, are you afraid of the three-headed Cerberus
in the shades below, and the roaring waves of Cocytus, and the passage
over Acheron, and Tantalus expiring with thirst, while the water touches
his chin; and Sisyphus,
Who sweats with arduous toil in vain
The steepy summit of the mount to gain?
Perhaps, too, you dread the inexorable judges, Minos and Rhadamanthus;
before whom neither L. Crassus nor M. Antonius can defend you; and
where, since the cause lies before Grecian judges, you will not even be
able to employ Demosthenes; but you must plead for yourself before a
13very great assembly. These things perhaps you dread, and therefore look
on death as an eternal evil.
VI. A. Do you take me to be so imbecile as to give credit to such
things?
M. What, do you not believe them?
A. Not in the least.
M. I am sorry to hear that.
A. Why, I beg?
M. Because I could have been very eloquent in speaking against them.
A. And who could not on such a subject? or what trouble is it to
refute these monstrous inventions of the poets and painters?6
M. And yet you have books of philosophers full of arguments against
these.
A. A great waste of time, truly! for who is so weak as to be concerned
about them?
M. If, then, there is no one miserable in the infernal regions, there
can be no one there at all.
A. I am altogether of that opinion.
M. Where, then, are those you call miserable? or what place do they
inhabit? For, if they exist at all, they must be somewhere.
A. I, indeed, am of opinion that they are nowhere.
M. Then they have no existence at all.
A. Even so, and yet they are miserable for this very reason, that they
have no existence.
M. I had rather now have you afraid of Cerberus than speak thus
inaccurately.
A. In what respect?
M. Because you admit him to exist whose existence you deny with the
same breath. Where now is your sagacity? When you say any one is
miserable, you say that he who does not exist, does exist.
A. I am not so absurd as to say that.
14M. What is it that you do say, then?
A. I say, for instance, that Marcus Crassus is miserable in being
deprived of such great riches as his by death; that Cn. Pompey is
miserable in being taken from such glory and honor; and, in short, that
all are miserable who are deprived of this light of life.
M. You have returned to the same point, for to be miserable implies an
existence; but you just now denied that the dead had any existence: if,
then, they have not, they can be nothing; and if so, they are not even
miserable.
A. Perhaps I do not express what I mean, for I look upon this very
circumstance, not to exist after having existed, to be very miserable.
M. What, more so than not to have existed at all? Therefore, those who
are not yet born are miserable because they are not; and we ourselves,
if we are to be miserable after death, were miserable before we were
born: but I do not remember that I was miserable before I was born; and
I should be glad to know, if your memory is better, what you recollect
of yourself before you were born.
VII. A. You are pleasant: as if I had said that those men are
miserable who are not born, and not that they are so who are dead.
M. You say, then, that they are so?
A. Yes; I say that because they no longer exist after having existed
they are miserable.
M. You do not perceive that you are asserting contradictions; for what
is a greater contradiction, than that that should be not only miserable,
but should have any existence at all, which does not exist? When you go
out at the Capene gate and see the tombs of the Calatini, the Scipios,
Servilii, and Metelli, do you look on them as miserable?
A. Because you press me with a word, henceforward I will not say they
are miserable absolutely, but miserable on this account, because they
have no existence.
M. You do not say, then, “M. Crassus is miserable,” but only
“Miserable M. Crassus.”
A. Exactly so.
M. As if it did not follow that whatever you speak of 15in that manner
either is or is not. Are you not acquainted with the first principles of
logic? For this is the first thing they lay down, Whatever is asserted
(for that is the best way that occurs to me, at the moment, of rendering
the Greek term бјЂОѕбЅ·П‰ОјО±; if I can think of a more accurate expression
hereafter, I will use it), is asserted as being either true or false.
When, therefore, you say, “Miserable M. Crassus,” you either say this,
“M. Crassus is miserable,” so that some judgment may be made whether it
is true or false, or you say nothing at all.
A. Well, then, I now own that the dead are not miserable, since you
have drawn from me a concession that they who do not exist at all can
not be miserable. What then? We that are alive, are we not wretched,
seeing we must die? for what is there agreeable in life, when we must
night and day reflect that, at some time or other, we must die?
VIII. M. Do you not, then, perceive how great is the evil from which
you have delivered human nature?
A. By what means?
M. Because, if to die were miserable to the dead, to live would be a
kind of infinite and eternal misery. Now, however, I see a goal, and
when I have reached it, there is nothing more to be feared; but you seem
to me to follow the opinion of Epicharmus,7 a man of some discernment,
and sharp enough for a Sicilian.
A. What opinion? for I do not recollect it.
M. I will tell you if I can in Latin; for you know I am no more used
to bring in Latin sentences in a Greek discourse than Greek in a Latin
one.
A. And that is right enough. But what is that opinion of Epicharmus?
M.
I would not die, but yet
Am not concerned that I shall be dead.
A. I now recollect the Greek; but since you have
16obliged me to grant
that the dead are not miserable, proceed to convince me that it is not
miserable to be under a necessity of dying.
M. That is easy enough; but I have greater things in hand.
A. How comes that to be so easy? And what are those things of more
consequence?
M. Thus: because, if there is no evil after death, then even death
itself can be none; for that which immediately succeeds that is a state
where you grant that there is no evil: so that even to be obliged to die
can be no evil, for that is only the being obliged to arrive at a place
where we allow that no evil is.
A. I beg you will be more explicit on this point, for these subtle
arguments force me sooner to admissions than to conviction. But what are
those more important things about which you say that you are occupied?
M. To teach you, if I can, that death is not only no evil, but a good.
A. I do not insist on that, but should be glad to hear you argue it,
for even though you should not prove your point, yet you will prove that
death is no evil. But I will not interrupt you; I would rather hear a
continued discourse.
M. What, if I should ask you a question, would you not answer?
A. That would look like pride; but I would rather you should not ask
but where necessity requires.
IX.
M. I will comply with your wishes, and explain as well as I can
what you require; but not with any idea that, like the Pythian Apollo,
what I say must needs be certain and indisputable, but as a mere man,
endeavoring to arrive at probabilities by conjecture, for I have no
ground to proceed further on than probability. Those men may call their
statements indisputable who assert that what they say can be perceived
by the senses, and who proclaim themselves philosophers by profession.
A. Do as you please: We are ready to hear you.
M. The first thing, then, is to inquire what death, which seems to be
so well understood, really is; for some imagine death to be the
departure of the soul from the body;
17others think that there is no such
departure, but that soul and body perish together, and that the soul is
extinguished with the body. Of those who think that the soul does depart
from the body, some believe in its immediate dissolution; others fancy
that it continues to exist for a time; and others believe that it lasts
forever. There is great dispute even what the soul is, where it is, and
whence it is derived: with some, the heart itself (
cor) seems to be
the soul, hence the expressions,
excordes,
vecordes,
concordes; and that
prudent Nasica, who was twice consul, was called Corculus,
i.e.,
wise-heart; and Г†lius Sextus is described as
Egregie cordatus
homo,
catus Æliu’ Sextus—that great
wise-hearted man, sage Г†lius.
Empedocles imagines the blood, which is suffused over the heart, to be
the soul; to others, a certain part of the brain seems to be the throne
of the soul; others neither allow the heart itself, nor any portion of
the brain, to be the soul, but think either that the heart is the seat
and abode of the soul, or else that the brain is so. Some would have the
soul, or spirit, to be the
anima, as our schools generally agree; and
indeed the name signifies as much, for we use the expressions
animam
agere, to live;
animam efflare, to expire;
animosi, men of spirit;
bene animati, men of right feeling;
exanimi sententia, according to
our real opinion; and the very word
animus is derived from
anima.
Again, the soul seems to Zeno the Stoic to be fire.
X. But what I have said as to the heart, the blood, the brain, air, or
fire being the soul, are common opinions: the others are only
entertained by individuals; and, indeed, there were many among the
ancients who held singular opinions on this subject, of whom the latest
was Aristoxenus, a man who was both a musician and a philosopher. He
maintained a certain straining of the body, like what is called harmony
in music, to be the soul, and believed that, from the figure and nature
of the whole body, various motions are excited, as sounds are from an
instrument. He adhered steadily to his system, and yet he said
something, the nature of which, whatever it was, had been detailed and
explained a great while before by Plato. Xenocrates denied that the soul
had any figure, or anything like a body; but said it was a number, the
power of which, as
18Pythagoras had fancied, some ages before, was the
greatest in nature: his master, Plato, imagined a threefold soul, a
dominant portion of which—that is to say, reason—he had lodged in the
head, as in a tower; and the other two parts—namely, anger and
desire—he made subservient to this one, and allotted them distinct
abodes, placing anger in the breast, and desire under the præcordia. But
Dicæarchus, in that discourse of some learned disputants, held at
Corinth, which he details to us in three books—in the first book
introduces many speakers; and in the other two he introduces a certain
Pherecrates, an old man of Phthia, who, as he said, was descended from
Deucalion; asserting, that there is in fact no such thing at all as a
soul, but that it is a name without a meaning; and that it is idle to
use the expression “animals,” or “animated beings;” that neither men nor
beasts have minds or souls, but that all that power by which we act or
perceive is equally infused into every living creature, and is
inseparable from the body, for if it were not, it would be nothing; nor
is there anything whatever really existing except body, which is a
single and simple thing, so fashioned as to live and have its sensations
in consequence of the regulations of nature. Aristotle, a man superior
to all others, both in genius and industry (I always except Plato),
after having embraced these four known sorts of principles, from which
all things deduce their origin, imagines that there is a certain fifth
nature, from whence comes the soul; for to think, to foresee, to learn,
to teach, to invent anything, and many other attributes of the same
kind, such as to remember, to love, to hate, to desire, to fear, to be
pleased or displeased—these, and others like them, exist, he thinks, in
none of those first four kinds: on such account he adds a fifth kind,
which has no name, and so by a new name he calls the soul
бјђОЅОґОµО»бЅіП‡ОµО№О±, as
if it were a certain continued and perpetual motion.
XI. If I have not forgotten anything unintentionally, these are the
principal opinions concerning the soul. I have omitted Democritus, a
very great man indeed, but one who deduces the soul from the fortuitous
concourse of small, light, and round substances; for, if you believe men
of his school, there is nothing which a crowd of atoms
19cannot effect.
Which of these opinions is true, some God must determine. It is an
important question for us, Which has the most appearance of truth? Shall
we, then, prefer determining between them, or shall we return to our
subject?
A. I could wish both, if possible; but it is difficult to mix them:
therefore, if without a discussion of them we can get rid of the fears
of death, let us proceed to do so; but if this is not to be done without
explaining the question about souls, let us have that now, and the other
at another time.
M. I take that plan to be the best, which I perceive you are inclined
to; for reason will demonstrate that, whichever of the opinions which I
have stated is true, it must follow, then, that death cannot be an evil;
or that it must rather be something desirable; for if either the heart,
or the blood, or the brain, is the soul, then certainly the soul, being
corporeal, must perish with the rest of the body; if it is air, it will
perhaps be dissolved; if it is fire, it will be extinguished; if it is
Aristoxenus’s harmony, it will be put out of tune. What shall I say of
Dicæarchus, who denies that there is any soul? In all these opinions,
there is nothing to affect any one after death; for all feeling is lost
with life, and where there is no sensation, nothing can interfere to
affect us. The opinions of others do indeed bring us hope; if it is any
pleasure to you to think that souls, after they leave the body, may go
to heaven as to a permanent home.
A. I have great pleasure in that thought, and it is what I most
desire; and even if it should not be so, I should still be very willing
to believe it.
M. What occasion have you, then, for my assistance? Am I superior to
Plato in eloquence? Turn over carefully his book that treats of the
soul; you will have there all that you can want.
A. I have, indeed, done that, and often; but, I know not how it comes
to pass, I agree with it while I am reading it; but when I have laid
down the book, and begin to reflect with myself on the immortality of
the soul, all that agreement vanishes.
M. How comes that? Do you admit this—that souls
20either exist after
death, or else that they also perish at the moment of death?
A. I agree to that. And if they do exist, I admit that they are happy;
but if they perish, I cannot suppose them to be unhappy, because, in
fact, they have no existence at all. You drove me to that concession but
just now.
M. How, then, can you, or why do you, assert that you think that death
is an evil, when it either makes us happy, in the case of the soul
continuing to exist, or, at all events, not unhappy, in the case of our
becoming destitute of all sensation?
XII.
A. Explain, therefore, if it is not troublesome to you, first, if
you can, that souls do exist after death; secondly, should you fail in
that (and it is a very difficult thing to establish), that death is free
from all evil; for I am not without my fears that this itself is an
evil: I do not mean the immediate deprivation of sense, but the fact
that we shall hereafter suffer deprivation.
M. I have the best authority in support of the opinion you desire to
have established, which ought, and generally has, great weight in all
cases. And, first, I have all antiquity on that side, which the more
near it is to its origin and divine descent, the more clearly, perhaps,
on that account, did it discern the truth in these matters. This very
doctrine, then, was adopted by all those ancients whom Ennius calls in
the Sabine tongue Casci; namely, that in death there was a sensation,
and that, when men departed this life, they were not so entirely
destroyed as to perish absolutely. And this may appear from many other
circumstances, and especially from the pontifical rites and funeral
obsequies, which men of the greatest genius would not have been so
solicitous about, and would not have guarded from any injury by such
severe laws, but from a firm persuasion that death was not so entire a
destruction as wholly to abolish and destroy everything, but rather a
kind of transmigration, as it were, and change of life, which was, in
the case of illustrious men and women, usually a guide to heaven, while
in that of others it was still confined to the earth, but in such a
manner as still to exist. From this, and the sentiments of the Romans,
In heaven Romulus with Gods now lives,
21as Ennius saith, agreeing with the common belief; hence, too, Hercules
is considered so great and propitious a God among the Greeks, and from
them he was introduced among us, and his worship has extended even to
the very ocean itself. This is how it was that Bacchus was deified, the
offspring of Semele; and from the same illustrious fame we receive
Castor and Pollux as Gods, who are reported not only to have helped the
Romans to victory in their battles, but to have been the messengers of
their success. What shall we say of Ino, the daughter of Cadmus? Is she
not called Leucothea by the Greeks, and Matuta by us? Nay, more; is not
the whole of heaven (not to dwell on particulars) almost filled with the
offspring of men?
Should I attempt to search into antiquity, and produce from thence what
the Greek writers have asserted, it would appear that even those who are
called their principal Gods were taken from among men up into heaven.
XIII. Examine the sepulchres of those which are shown in Greece;
recollect, for you have been initiated, what lessons are taught in the
mysteries; then will you perceive how extensive this doctrine is. But
they who were not acquainted with natural philosophy (for it did not
begin to be in vogue till many years later) had no higher belief than
what natural reason could give them; they were not acquainted with the
principles and causes of things; they were often induced by certain
visions, and those generally in the night, to think that those men who
had departed from this life were still alive. And this may further be
brought as an irrefragable argument for us to believe that there are
Gods—that there never was any nation so barbarous, nor any people in
the world so savage, as to be without some notion of Gods. Many have
wrong notions of the Gods, for that is the nature and ordinary
consequence of bad customs, yet all allow that there is a certain divine
nature and energy. Nor does this proceed from the conversation of men,
or the agreement of philosophers; it is not an opinion established by
institutions or by laws; but, no doubt, in every case the consent of all
nations is to be looked on as a law of nature. Who is there, then, that
does not lament the loss of his friends, principally from 22imagining
them deprived of the conveniences of life? Take away this opinion, and
you remove with it all grief; for no one is afflicted merely on account
of a loss sustained by himself. Perhaps we may be sorry, and grieve a
little; but that bitter lamentation and those mournful tears have their
origin in our apprehensions that he whom we loved is deprived of all the
advantages of life, and is sensible of his loss. And we are led to this
opinion by nature, without any arguments or any instruction.
XIV. But the greatest proof of all is, that nature herself gives a
silent judgment in favor of the immortality of the soul, inasmuch as all
are anxious, and that to a great degree, about the things which concern
futurity:
One plants what future ages shall enjoy,
as Statius saith in his Synephebi. What is his object in doing so,
except that he is interested in posterity? Shall the industrious
husbandman, then, plant trees the fruit of which he shall never see? And
shall not the great man found laws, institutions, and a republic? What
does the procreation of children imply, and our care to continue our
names, and our adoptions, and our scrupulous exactness in drawing up
wills, and the inscriptions on monuments, and panegyrics, but that our
thoughts run on futurity? There is no doubt but a judgment may be formed
of nature in general, from looking at each nature in its most perfect
specimens; and what is a more perfect specimen of a man than those are
who look on themselves as born for the assistance, the protection, and
the preservation of others? Hercules has gone to heaven; he never would
have gone thither had he not, while among men, made that road for
himself. These things are of old date, and have, besides, the sanction
of universal religion.
XV. What will you say? What do you imagine that so many and such great
men of our republic, who have sacrificed their lives for its good,
expected? Do you believe that they thought that their names should not
continue beyond their lives? None ever encountered death for their
country but under a firm persuasion of immortality! Themistocles might
have lived at his ease; so might Epaminondas; and, not to look abroad
and among the ancients 23for instances, so might I myself. But, somehow
or other there clings to our minds a certain presage of future ages; and
this both exists most firmly, and appears most clearly, in men of the
loftiest genius and greatest souls. Take away this, and who would be so
mad as to spend his life amidst toils and dangers? I speak of those in
power. What are the poet’s views but to be ennobled after death? What
else is the object of these lines,
Behold old Ennius here, who erst
Thy fathers’ great exploits rehearsed?
He is challenging the reward of glory from those men whose ancestors he
himself had ennobled by his poetry. And in the same spirit he says, in
another passage,
Let none with tears my funeral grace, for I
Claim from my works an immortality.
Why do I mention poets? The very mechanics are desirous of fame after
death. Why did Phidias include a likeness of himself in the shield of
Minerva, when he was not allowed to inscribe his name on it? What do our
philosophers think on the subject? Do not they put their names to those
very books which they write on the contempt of glory? If, then,
universal consent is the voice of nature, and if it is the general
opinion everywhere that those who have quitted this life are still
interested in something, we also must subscribe to that opinion. And if
we think that men of the greatest abilities and virtues see most clearly
into the power of nature, because they themselves are her most perfect
work, it is very probable that, as every great man is especially anxious
to benefit posterity, there is something of which he himself will be
sensible after death.
XVI. But as we are led by nature to think there are Gods, and as we
discover, by reason, of what description they are, so, by the consent of
all nations, we are induced to believe that our souls survive; but where
their habitation is, and of what character they eventually are, must be
learned from reason. The want of any certain reason on which to argue
has given rise to the idea of the shades below, and to those fears which
you seem, not without 24reason, to despise; for as our bodies fall to the
ground, and are covered with earth (humus), from whence we derive the
expression to be interred (humari), that has occasioned men to imagine
that the dead continue, during the remainder of their existence, under
ground; which opinion has drawn after it many errors, which the poets
have increased; for the theatre, being frequented by a large crowd,
among which are women and children, is wont to be greatly affected on
hearing such pompous verses as these,
Lo! here I am, who scarce could gain this place,
Through stony mountains and a dreary waste;
Through cliffs, whose sharpen’d stones tremendous hung,
Where dreadful darkness spread itself around.
And the error prevailed so much, though indeed at present it seems to me
to be removed, that although men knew that the bodies of the dead had
been burned, yet they conceived such things to be done in the infernal
regions as could not be executed or imagined without a body; for they
could not conceive how disembodied souls could exist; and, therefore,
they looked out for some shape or figure. This was the origin of all
that account of the dead in Homer. This was the idea that caused my
friend Appius to frame his Necromancy; and this is how there got about
that idea of the lake of Avernus, in my neighborhood,
From whence the souls of undistinguish’d shape,
Clad in thick shade, rush from the open gate
Of Acheron, vain phantoms of the dead.
And they must needs have these appearances speak, which is not possible
without a tongue, and a palate, and jaws, and without the help of lungs
and sides, and without some shape or figure; for they could see nothing
by their mind alone—they referred all to their eyes. To withdraw the
mind from sensual objects, and abstract our thoughts from what we are
accustomed to, is an attribute of great genius. I am persuaded, indeed,
that there were many such men in former ages; but Pherecydes8 the
Syrian is the 25first on record who said that the souls of men were
immortal, and he was a philosopher of great antiquity, in the reign of
my namesake Tullius. His disciple Pythagoras greatly confirmed this
opinion, who came into Italy in the reign of Tarquin the Proud; and all
that country which is called Great Greece was occupied by his school,
and he himself was held in high honor, and had the greatest authority;
and the Pythagorean sect was for many ages after in such great credit,
that all learning was believed to be confined to that name.
XVII. But I return to the ancients. They scarcely ever gave any reason
for their opinion but what could be explained by numbers or definitions.
It is reported of Plato that he came into Italy to make himself
acquainted with the Pythagoreans; and that when there, among others, he
made an acquaintance with Archytas9 and Timæus,10 and learned from
them all the tenets of the Pythagoreans; and that he not only was of the
same opinion with Pythagoras concerning the immortality of the soul, but
that he also brought reasons in support of it; which, if you have
nothing to say against it, I will pass over, and say no more at present
about all this hope of immortality.
A. What, will you leave me when you have raised my expectations so
high? I had rather, so help me Hercules! be mistaken with Plato, whom I
know how much you esteem, and whom I admire myself, from what you say of
him, than be in the right with those others.
26M. I commend you; for, indeed, I could myself willingly be mistaken
in his company. Do we, then, doubt, as we do in other cases (though I
think here is very little room for doubt in this case, for the
mathematicians prove the facts to us), that the earth is placed in the
midst of the world, being, as it were, a sort of point, which they call
a ОєбЅіОЅП„ПЃОїОЅ, surrounded by the whole heavens; and that such is the nature
of the four principles which are the generating causes of all things,
that they have equally divided among them the constituents of all
bodies; moreover, that earthy and humid bodies are carried at equal
angles by their own weight and ponderosity into the earth and sea; that
the other two parts consist, one of fire, and the other of air? As the
two former are carried by their gravity and weight into the middle
region of the world, so these, on the other hand, ascend by right lines
into the celestial regions, either because, owing to their intrinsic
nature, they are always endeavoring to reach the highest place, or else
because lighter bodies are naturally repelled by heavier; and as this is
notoriously the case, it must evidently follow that souls, when once
they have departed from the body, whether they are animal (by which term
I mean capable of breathing) or of the nature of fire, must mount
upward. But if the soul is some number, as some people assert, speaking
with more subtlety than clearness, or if it is that fifth nature, for
which it would be more correct to say that we have not given a name to
than that we do not correctly understand it—still it is too pure and
perfect not to go to a great distance from the earth. Something of this
sort, then, we must believe the soul to be, that we may not commit the
folly of thinking that so active a principle lies immerged in the heart
or brain; or, as Empedocles would have it, in the blood.
XVIII. We will pass over Dicæarchus,11 with his contemporary and
fellow-disciple Aristoxenus,12 both indeed 27men of learning. One of
them seems never even to have been affected with grief, as he could not
perceive that he had a soul; while the other is so pleased with his
musical compositions that he endeavors to show an analogy betwixt them
and souls. Now, we may understand harmony to arise from the intervals of
sounds, whose various compositions occasion many harmonies; but I do not
see how a disposition of members, and the figure of a body without a
soul, can occasion harmony. He had better, learned as he is, leave these
speculations to his master Aristotle, and follow his own trade as a
musician. Good advice is given him in that Greek proverb,
Apply your talents where you best are skill’d.
I will have nothing at all to do with that fortuitous concourse of
individual light and round bodies, notwithstanding Democritus insists on
their being warm and having breath, that is to say, life. But this soul,
which is compounded of either of the four principles from which we
assert that all things are derived, is of inflamed air, as seems
particularly to have been the opinion of Panætius, and must necessarily
mount upward; for air and fire have no tendency downward, but always
ascend; so should they be dissipated that must be at some distance from
the earth; but should they remain, and preserve their original state, it
is clearer still that they must be carried heavenward, and this gross
and concrete air, which is nearest the earth, must be divided and broken
by them; for the soul is warmer, or rather hotter, than that air, which
I just now called gross and concrete: and this may be made evident from
this consideration—that our bodies, being compounded of the earthy
class of principles, grow warm by the heat of the soul.
XIX. We may add, that the soul can the more easily escape from this air,
which I have often named, and break 28through it, because nothing is
swifter than the soul; no swiftness is comparable to the swiftness of
the soul, which, should it remain uncorrupt and without alteration, must
necessarily be carried on with such velocity as to penetrate and divide
all this atmosphere, where clouds, and rain, and winds are formed,
which, in consequence of the exhalations from the earth, is moist and
dark: but, when the soul has once got above this region, and falls in
with, and recognizes, a nature like its own, it then rests upon fires
composed of a combination of thin air and a moderate solar heat, and
does not aim at any higher flight; for then, after it has attained a
lightness and heat resembling its own, it moves no more, but remains
steady, being balanced, as it were, between two equal weights. That,
then, is its natural seat where it has penetrated to something like
itself, and where, wanting nothing further, it may be supported and
maintained by the same aliment which nourishes and maintains the stars.
Now, as we are usually incited to all sorts of desires by the stimulus
of the body, and the more so as we endeavor to rival those who are in
possession of what we long for, we shall certainly be happy when, being
emancipated from that body, we at the same time get rid of these desires
and this rivalry. And that which we do at present, when, dismissing all
other cares, we curiously examine and look into anything, we shall then
do with greater freedom; and we shall employ ourselves entirely in the
contemplation and examination of things; because there is naturally in
our minds a certain insatiable desire to know the truth, and the very
region itself where we shall arrive, as it gives us a more intuitive and
easy knowledge of celestial things, will raise our desires after
knowledge. For it was this beauty of the heavens, as seen even here upon
earth, which gave birth to that national and hereditary philosophy (as
Theophrastus calls it), which was thus excited to a desire of knowledge.
But those persons will in a most especial degree enjoy this philosophy,
who, while they were only inhabitants of this world and enveloped in
darkness, were still desirous of looking into these things with the eye
of their mind.
XX. For if those men now think that they have attained 29something who
have seen the mouth of the Pontus, and those straits which were passed
by the ship called Argo, because,
From Argos she did chosen men convey,
Bound to fetch back the Golden Fleece, their prey;
or those who have seen the straits of the ocean,
Where the swift waves divide the neighboring shores
Of Europe, and of Afric;
what kind of sight do you imagine that will be when the whole earth is
laid open to our view? and that, too, not only in its position, form,
and boundaries, nor those parts of it only which are habitable, but
those also that lie uncultivated, through the extremities of heat and
cold to which they are exposed; for not even now is it with our eyes
that we view what we see, for the body itself has no senses; but (as the
naturalists, ay, and even the physicians assure us, who have opened our
bodies, and examined them) there are certain perforated channels from
the seat of the soul to the eyes, ears, and nose; so that frequently,
when either prevented by meditation, or the force of some bodily
disorder, we neither hear nor see, though our eyes and ears are open and
in good condition; so that we may easily apprehend that it is the soul
itself which sees and hears, and not those parts which are, as it were,
but windows to the soul, by means of which, however, she can perceive
nothing, unless she is on the spot, and exerts herself. How shall we
account for the fact that by the same power of thinking we comprehend
the most different things—as color, taste, heat, smell, and
sound—which the soul could never know by her five messengers, unless
every thing were referred to her, and she were the sole judge of all?
And we shall certainly discover these things in a more clear and perfect
degree when the soul is disengaged from the body, and has arrived at
that goal to which nature leads her; for at present, notwithstanding
nature has contrived, with the greatest skill, those channels which lead
from the body to the soul, yet are they, in some way or other, stopped
up with earthy and concrete bodies; but when we shall be nothing but
soul, then nothing will interfere 30to prevent our seeing everything in
its real substance and in its true character.
XXI. It is true, I might expatiate, did the subject require it, on the
many and various objects with which the soul will be entertained in
those heavenly regions; when I reflect on which, I am apt to wonder at
the boldness of some philosophers, who are so struck with admiration at
the knowledge of nature as to thank, in an exulting manner, the first
inventor and teacher of natural philosophy, and to reverence him as a
God; for they declare that they have been delivered by his means from
the greatest tyrants, a perpetual terror, and a fear that molested them
by night and day. What is this dread—this fear? What old woman is there
so weak as to fear these things, which you, forsooth, had you not been
acquainted with natural philosophy, would stand in awe of?
The hallow’d roofs of Acheron, the dread
Of Orcus, the pale regions of the dead.
And does it become a philosopher to boast that he is not afraid of these
things, and that he has discovered them to be false? And from this we
may perceive how acute these men were by nature, who, if they had been
left without any instruction, would have believed in these things. But
now they have certainly made a very fine acquisition in learning that
when the day of their death arrives, they will perish entirely. And if
that really is the case—for I say nothing either way—what is there
agreeable or glorious in it? Not that I see any reason why the opinion
of Pythagoras and Plato may not be true; but even although Plato were to
have assigned no reason for his opinion (observe how much I esteem the
man), the weight of his authority would have borne me down; but he has
brought so many reasons, that he appears to me to have endeavored to
convince others, and certainly to have convinced himself.
XXII. But there are many who labor on the other side of the question,
and condemn souls to death, as if they were criminals capitally
convicted; nor have they any other reason to allege why the immortality
of the soul appears to them to be incredible, except that they are not
31able to conceive what sort of thing the soul can be when disentangled
from the body; just as if they could really form a correct idea as to
what sort of thing it is, even when it is in the body; what its form,
and size, and abode are; so that were they able to have a full view of
all that is now hidden from them in a living body, they have no idea
whether the soul would be discernible by them, or whether it is of so
fine a texture that it would escape their sight. Let those consider
this, who say that they are unable to form any idea of the soul without
the body, and then they will see whether they can form any adequate idea
of what it is when it is in the body. For my own part, when I reflect on
the nature of the soul, it appears to me a far more perplexing and
obscure question to determine what is its character while it is in the
body—a place which, as it were, does not belong to it—than to imagine
what it is when it leaves it, and has arrived at the free Г¦ther, which
is, if I may so say, its proper, its own habitation. For unless we are
to say that we cannot apprehend the character or nature of anything
which we have never seen, we certainly may be able to form some notion
of God, and of the divine soul when released from the body. Dicæarchus,
indeed, and Aristoxenus, because it was hard to understand the existence
and substance and nature of the soul, asserted that there was no such
thing as a soul at all. It is, indeed, the most difficult thing
imaginable to discern the soul by the soul. And this, doubtless, is the
meaning of the precept of Apollo, which advises every one to know
himself. For I do not apprehend the meaning of the God to have been that
we should understand our members, our stature, and form; for we are not
merely bodies; nor, when I say these things to you, am I addressing
myself to your body: when, therefore, he says, “Know yourself,” he says
this, “Inform yourself of the nature of your soul;” for the body is but
a kind of vessel, or receptacle of the soul, and whatever your soul does
is your own act. To know the soul, then, unless it had been divine,
would not have been a precept of such excellent wisdom as to be
attributed to a God; but even though the soul should not know of what
nature itself is, will you say that it does not even perceive that 32it
exists at all, or that it has motion? On which is founded that reason
of Plato’s, which is explained by Socrates in the Phædrus, and inserted
by me, in my sixth book of the Republic.
XXIII. “That which is always moved is eternal; but that which gives
motion to something else, and is moved itself by some external cause,
when that motion ceases, must necessarily cease to exist. That,
therefore, alone, which is self-moved, because it is never forsaken by
itself, can never cease to be moved. Besides, it is the beginning and
principle of motion to everything else; but whatever is a principle has
no beginning, for all things arise from that principle, and it cannot
itself owe its rise to anything else; for then it would not be a
principle did it proceed from anything else. But if it has no beginning,
it never will have any end; for a principle which is once extinguished
cannot itself be restored by anything else, nor can it produce anything
else from itself; inasmuch as all things must necessarily arise from
some first cause. And thus it comes about that the first principle of
motion must arise from that thing which is itself moved by itself; and
that can neither have a beginning nor an end of its existence, for
otherwise the whole heaven and earth would be overset, and all nature
would stand still, and not be able to acquire any force by the impulse
of which it might be first set in motion. Seeing, then, that it is clear
that whatever moves itself is eternal, can there be any doubt that the
soul is so? For everything is inanimate which is moved by an external
force; but everything which is animate is moved by an interior force,
which also belongs to itself. For this is the peculiar nature and power
of the soul; and if the soul be the only thing in the whole world which
has the power of self-motion, then certainly it never had a beginning,
and therefore it is eternal.”
Now, should all the lower order of philosophers (for so I think they may
be called who dissent from Plato and Socrates and that school) unite
their force, they never would be able to explain anything so elegantly
as this, nor even to understand how ingeniously this conclusion is
drawn. The soul, then, perceives itself to have motion, 33and at the same
time that it gets that perception, it is sensible that it derives that
motion from its own power, and not from the agency of another; and it is
impossible that it should ever forsake itself. And these premises compel
you to allow its eternity, unless you have something to say against
them.
A. I should myself be very well pleased not to have even a thought
arise in my mind against them, so much am I inclined to that opinion.
XXIV. M. Well, then, I appeal to you, if the arguments which prove
that there is something divine in the souls of men are not equally
strong? But if I could account for the origin of these divine
properties, then I might also be able to explain how they might cease to
exist; for I think I can account for the manner in which the blood, and
bile, and phlegm, and bones, and nerves, and veins, and all the limbs,
and the shape of the whole body, were put together and made; ay, and
even as to the soul itself, were there nothing more in it than a
principle of life, then the life of a man might be put upon the same
footing as that of a vine or any other tree, and accounted for as caused
by nature; for these things, as we say, live. Besides, if desires and
aversions were all that belonged to the soul, it would have them only in
common with the beasts; but it has, in the first place, memory, and
that, too, so infinite as to recollect an absolute countless number of
circumstances, which Plato will have to be a recollection of a former
life; for in that book which is inscribed Menon, Socrates asks a child
some questions in geometry, with reference to measuring a square; his
answers are such as a child would make, and yet the questions are so
easy, that while answering them, one by one, he comes to the same point
as if he had learned geometry. From whence Socrates would infer that
learning is nothing more than recollection; and this topic he explains
more accurately in the discourse which he held the very day he died; for
he there asserts that, any one, who seeming to be entirely illiterate,
is yet able to answer a question well that is proposed to him, does in
so doing manifestly show that he is not learning it then, but
recollecting it by his memory. Nor is it to be accounted for in any
other way, how children 34come to have notions of so many and such
important things as are implanted, and, as it were, sealed up, in their
minds (which the Greeks call бј”ОЅОЅОїО№О±О№), unless the soul, before it
entered the body, had been well stored with knowledge. And as it had no
existence at all (for this is the invariable doctrine of Plato, who will
not admit anything to have a real existence which has a beginning and an
end, and who thinks that that alone does really exist which is of such a
character as what he calls ОµбјґОґОµО±, and we species), therefore, being shut
up in the body, it could not while in the body discover what it knows;
but it knew it before, and brought the knowledge with it, so that we are
no longer surprised at its extensive and multifarious knowledge. Nor
does the soul clearly discover its ideas at its first resort to this
abode to which it is so unaccustomed, and which is in so disturbed a
state; but after having refreshed and recollected itself, it then by its
memory recovers them; and, therefore, to learn implies nothing more than
to recollect. But I am in a particular manner surprised at memory. For
what is that faculty by which we remember? what is its force? what its
nature? I am not inquiring how great a memory Simonides13 may be said
to have had, or Theodectes,14 or that Cineas15 who was sent to Rome
as ambassador from Pyrrhus; or, in more modern times, Charmadas;16 or,
very lately, Metrodorus17 35the Scepsian, or our own contemporary
Hortensius18: I am speaking of ordinary memory, and especially of
those men who are employed in any important study or art, the great
capacity of whose minds it is hard to estimate, such numbers of things
do they remember.
XXV. Should you ask what this leads to, I think we may understand what
that power is, and whence we have it. It certainly proceeds neither from
the heart, nor from the blood, nor from the brain, nor from atoms;
whether it be air or fire, I know not, nor am I, as those men are,
ashamed, in cases where I am ignorant, to own that I am so. If in any
other obscure matter I were able to assert anything positively, then I
would swear that the soul, be it air or fire, is divine. Just think, I
beseech you: can you imagine this wonderful power of memory to be sown
in or to be a part of the composition of the earth, or of this dark and
gloomy atmosphere? Though you cannot apprehend what it is, yet you see
what kind of thing it is, or if you do not quite see that, yet you
certainly see how great it is. What, then? Shall we imagine that there
is a kind of measure in the soul, into which, as into a vessel, all that
we remember is poured? That indeed is absurd; for how shall we form any
idea of the bottom, or of the shape or fashion of such a soul as that?
And, again, how are we to conceive how much it is able to contain? Shall
we imagine the soul to receive impressions like wax, and memory to be
marks of the impressions made on the soul? What are the characters of
the words, what of the facts themselves? and what, again, is that
prodigious greatness which can give rise to impressions of so many
things? What, lastly, is that power which investigates secret things,
and is called invention and contrivance? Does that man seem to be
compounded of this earthly, mortal, and perishing nature who first
invented names for everything; 36which, if you will believe Pythagoras,
is the highest pitch of wisdom? or he who collected the dispersed
inhabitants of the world, and united them in the bonds of social life?
or he who confined the sounds of the voice, which used to seem infinite,
to the marks of a few letters? or he who first observed the courses of
the planets, their progressive motions, their laws? These were all great
men. But they were greater still who invented food, and raiment, and
houses; who introduced civilization among us, and armed us against the
wild beasts; by whom we were made sociable and polished, and so
proceeded from the necessaries of life to its embellishments. For we
have provided great entertainments for the ears by inventing and
modulating the variety and nature of sounds; we have learned to survey
the stars, not only those that are fixed, but also those which are
improperly called wandering; and the man who has acquainted himself with
all their revolutions and motions is fairly considered to have a soul
resembling the soul of that Being who has created those stars in the
heavens: for when Archimedes described in a sphere the motions of the
moon, sun, and five planets, he did the very same thing as Plato’s God,
in his Timæus, who made the world, causing one revolution to adjust
motions differing as much as possible in their slowness and velocity.
Now, allowing that what we see in the world could not be effected
without a God, Archimedes could not have imitated the same motions in
his sphere without a divine soul.
XXVI. To me, indeed, it appears that even those studies which are more
common and in greater esteem are not without some divine energy: so that
I do not consider that a poet can produce a serious and sublime poem
without some divine impulse working on his mind; nor do I think that
eloquence, abounding with sonorous words and fruitful sentences, can
flow thus without something beyond mere human power. But as to
philosophy, that is the parent of all the arts: what can we call that
but, as Plato says, a gift, or, as I express it, an invention, of the
Gods? This it was which first taught us the worship of the Gods; and
then led us on to justice, which arises from the human race being formed
into society; and after that 37it imbued us with modesty and elevation of
soul. This it was which dispersed darkness from our souls, as it is
dispelled from our eyes, enabling us to see all things that are above or
below, the beginning, end, and middle of everything. I am convinced
entirely that that which could effect so many and such great things must
be a divine power. For what is memory of words and circumstances? What,
too, is invention? Surely they are things than which nothing greater can
be conceived in a God! For I do not imagine the Gods to be delighted
with nectar and ambrosia, or with Juventas presenting them with a cup;
nor do I put any faith in Homer, who says that Ganymede was carried away
by the Gods on account of his beauty, in order to give Jupiter his wine.
Too weak reasons for doing Laomedon such injury! These were mere
inventions of Homer, who gave his Gods the imperfections of men. I would
rather that he had given men the perfections of the Gods! those
perfections, I mean, of uninterrupted health, wisdom, invention, memory.
Therefore the soul (which is, as I say, divine) is, as Euripides more
boldly expresses it, a God. And thus, if the divinity be air or fire,
the soul of man is the same; for as that celestial nature has nothing
earthly or humid about it, in like manner the soul of man is also free
from both these qualities: but if it is of that fifth kind of nature,
first introduced by Aristotle, then both Gods and souls are of the same.
XXVII. As this is my opinion, I have explained it in these very words,
in my book on Consolation.19 The origin of the soul of man is not to
be found upon earth, for there is nothing in the soul of a mixed or
concrete nature, or that has any appearance of being formed or made out
of the earth; nothing even humid, or airy, or fiery. For what is there
in natures of that kind which has the power of memory, understanding, or
thought? which can recollect the past, foresee the future, and
comprehend the present? for these capabilities are confined to divine
beings; nor can we discover any source from which men could derive them,
but from God. There is therefore a peculiar 38nature and power in the
soul, distinct from those natures which are more known and familiar to
us. Whatever, then, that is which thinks, and which has understanding,
and volition, and a principle of life, is heavenly and divine, and on
that account must necessarily be eternal; nor can God himself, who is
known to us, be conceived to be anything else except a soul free and
unembarrassed, distinct from all mortal concretion, acquainted with
everything, and giving motion to everything, and itself endued with
perpetual motion.
XXVIII. Of this kind and nature is the intellect of man. Where, then, is
this intellect seated, and of what character is it? where is your own,
and what is its character? Are you able to tell? If I have not faculties
for knowing all that I could desire to know, will you not even allow me
to make use of those which I have? The soul has not sufficient capacity
to comprehend itself; yet, the soul, like the eye, though it has no
distinct view of itself, sees other things: it does not see (which is of
least consequence) its own shape; perhaps not, though it possibly may;
but we will pass that by: but it certainly sees that it has vigor,
sagacity, memory, motion, and velocity; these are all great, divine,
eternal properties. What its appearance is, or where it dwells, it is
not necessary even to inquire. As when we behold, first of all, the
beauty and brilliant appearance of the heavens; secondly, the vast
velocity of its revolutions, beyond power of our imagination to
conceive; then the vicissitudes of nights and days, the fourfold
division of the seasons, so well adapted to the ripening of the fruits
of the earth, and the temperature of our bodies: and after that we look
up to the sun, the moderator and governor of all these things; and view
the moon, by the increase and decrease of its light, marking, as it
were, and appointing our holy days; and see the five planets, borne on
in the same circle, divided into twelve parts, preserving the same
course with the greatest regularity, but with utterly dissimilar motions
among themselves; and the nightly appearance of the heaven, adorned on
all sides with stars; then, the globe of the earth, raised above the
sea, and placed in the centre of the universe, inhabited and cultivated
in its two opposite extremities, one of which, the 39place of our
habitation, is situated towards the north pole, under the seven stars:
Where the cold northern blasts, with horrid sound,
Harden to ice the snowy cover’d ground;
the other, towards the south pole, is unknown to us, but is called by
the Greeks бјЂОЅП„бЅ·П‡ОёОїОЅО±: the other parts are uncultivated, because they are
either frozen with cold, or burned up with heat; but where we dwell, it
never fails, in its season,
To yield a placid sky, to bid the trees
Assume the lively verdure of their leaves:
The vine to bud, and, joyful, in its shoots,
Foretell the approaching vintage of its fruits:
The ripen’d corn to sing, while all around
Full riv’lets glide; and flowers deck the ground:
then the multitude of cattle, fit part for food, part for tilling the
ground, others for carrying us, or for clothing us; and man himself,
made, as it were, on purpose to contemplate the heavens and the Gods,
and to pay adoration to them: lastly, the whole earth, and wide
extending seas, given to man’s use. When we view these and numberless
other things, can we doubt that they have some being who presides over
them, or has made them (if, indeed, they have been made, as is the
opinion of Plato, or if, as Aristotle thinks, they are eternal), or who
at all events is the regulator of so immense a fabric and so great a
blessing to men? Thus, though you see not the soul of man, as you see
not the Deity, yet, as by the contemplation of his works you are led to
acknowledge a God, so you must own the divine power of the soul, from
its remembering things, from its invention, from the quickness of its
motion, and from all the beauty of virtue. Where, then, is it seated,
you will say?
XXIX. In my opinion, it is seated in the head, and I can bring you
reasons for my adopting that opinion. At present, let the soul reside
where it will, you certainly have one in you. Should you ask what its
nature is? It has one peculiarly its own; but admitting it to consist of
fire, or air, it does not affect the present question. Only observe
this, that as you are convinced there is a God, though 40you are ignorant
where he resides, and what shape he is of; in like manner you ought to
feel assured that you have a soul, though you cannot satisfy yourself of
the place of its residence, nor its form. In our knowledge of the soul,
unless we are grossly ignorant of natural philosophy, we cannot but be
satisfied that it has nothing but what is simple, unmixed, uncompounded,
and single; and if this is admitted, then it cannot be separated, nor
divided, nor dispersed, nor parted, and therefore it cannot perish; for
to perish implies a parting-asunder, a division, a disunion, of those
parts which, while it subsisted, were held together by some band. And it
was because he was influenced by these and similar reasons that Socrates
neither looked out for anybody to plead for him when he was accused, nor
begged any favor from his judges, but maintained a manly freedom, which
was the effect not of pride, but of the true greatness of his soul; and
on the last day of his life he held a long discourse on this subject;
and a few days before, when he might have been easily freed from his
confinement, he refused to be so; and when he had almost actually hold
of that deadly cup, he spoke with the air of a man not forced to die,
but ascending into heaven.
XXX. For so indeed he thought himself, and thus he spoke: “That there
were two ways, and that the souls of men, at their departure from the
body, took different roads; for those which were polluted with vices
that are common to men, and which had given themselves up entirely to
unclean desires, and had become so blinded by them as to have habituated
themselves to all manner of debauchery and profligacy, or to have laid
detestable schemes for the ruin of their country, took a road wide of
that which led to the assembly of the Gods; but they who had preserved
themselves upright and chaste, and free from the slightest contagion of
the body, and had always kept themselves as far as possible at a
distance from it, and while on earth had proposed to themselves as a
model the life of the Gods, found the return to those beings from whom
they had come an easy one.” Therefore, he argues, that all good and wise
men should take example from the swans, who are considered sacred to
Apollo, not without reason, but particularly because they seem to have
received 41the gift of divination from him, by which, foreseeing how
happy it is to die, they leave this world with singing and joy. Nor can
any one doubt of this, unless it happens to us who think with care and
anxiety about the soul (as is often the case with those who look
earnestly at the setting sun), to lose the sight of it entirely; and so
the mind’s eye, viewing itself, sometimes grows dull, and for that
reason we become remiss in our contemplation. Thus our reasoning is
borne about, harassed with doubts and anxieties, not knowing how to
proceed, but measuring back again those dangerous tracts which it has
passed, like a boat tossed about on the boundless ocean. But these
reflections are of long standing, and borrowed from the Greeks. But Cato
left this world in such a manner as if he were delighted that he had
found an opportunity of dying; for that God who presides in us forbids
our departure hence without his leave. But when God himself has given us
a just cause, as formerly he did to Socrates, and lately to Cato, and
often to many others—in such a case, certainly every man of sense would
gladly exchange this darkness for that light: not that he would forcibly
break from the chains that held him, for that would be against the law;
but, like a man released from prison by a magistrate or some lawful
authority, so he too would walk away, being released and discharged by
God. For the whole life of a philosopher is, as the same philosopher
says, a meditation on death.
XXXI. For what else is it that we do, when we call off our minds from
pleasure, that is to say, from our attention to the body, from the
managing our domestic estate, which is a sort of handmaid and servant of
the body, or from duties of a public nature, or from all other serious
business whatever? What else is it, I say, that we do, but invite the
soul to reflect on itself? oblige it to converse with itself, and, as
far as possible, break off its acquaintance with the body? Now, to
separate the soul from the body, is to learn to die, and nothing else
whatever. Wherefore take my advice; and let us meditate on this, and
separate ourselves as far as possible from the body, that is to say, let
us accustom ourselves to die. This will be enjoying a life like that of
heaven even while we remain on earth; and 42when we are carried thither
and released from these bonds, our souls will make their progress with
more rapidity; for the spirit which has always been fettered by the
bonds of the body, even when it is disengaged, advances more slowly,
just as those do who have worn actual fetters for many years: but when
we have arrived at this emancipation from the bonds of the body, then
indeed we shall begin to live, for this present life is really death,
which I could say a good deal in lamentation for if I chose.
A. You have lamented it sufficiently in your book on Consolation; and
when I read that, there is nothing which I desire more than to leave
these things; but that desire is increased a great deal by what I have
just heard.
M. The time will come, and that soon, and with equal certainty,
whether you hang back or press forward; for time flies. But death is so
far from being an evil, as it lately appeared to you, that I am inclined
to suspect, not that there is no other thing which is an evil to man,
but rather that there is nothing else which is a real good to him; if,
at least, it is true that we become thereby either Gods ourselves, or
companions of the Gods. However, this is not of so much consequence, as
there are some of us here who will not allow this. But I will not leave
off discussing this point till I have convinced you that death can, upon
no consideration whatever, be an evil.
A. How can it, after what I now know?
M. Do you ask how it can? There are crowds of arguers who contradict
this; and those not only Epicureans, whom I regard very little, but,
somehow or other, almost every man of letters; and, above all, my
favorite Dicæarchus is very strenuous in opposing the immortality of the
soul: for he has written three books, which are entitled Lesbiacs,
because the discourse was held at Mitylene, in which he seeks to prove
that souls are mortal. The Stoics, on the other hand, allow us as long a
time for enjoyment as the life of a raven; they allow the soul to exist
a great while, but are against its eternity.
XXXII. Are you willing to hear then why, even allowing this, death
cannot be an evil.
A. As you please; but no one shall drive me from my belief in
mortality.
43M. I commend you, indeed, for that; though we should not be too
confident in our belief of anything; for we are frequently disturbed by
some subtle conclusion. We give way and change our opinions even in
things that are more evident than this; for in this there certainly is
some obscurity. Therefore, should anything of this kind happen, it is
well to be on our guard.
A. You are right in that; but I will provide against any accident.
M. Have you any objection to our dismissing our friends the
Stoics—those, I mean, who allow that the souls exist after they have
left the body, but yet deny that they exist forever?
A. We certainly may dismiss the consideration of those men who admit
that which is the most difficult point in the whole question, namely,
that a soul can exist independently of the body, and yet refuse to grant
that which is not only very easy to believe, but which is even the
natural consequence of the concession which they have made—that if they
can exist for a length of time; they most likely do so forever.
M. You take it right; that is the very thing. Shall we give,
therefore, any credit to Pauæstius, when he dissents from his master,
Plato? whom he everywhere calls divine, the wisest, the holiest of men,
the Homer of philosophers, and whom he opposes in nothing except this
single opinion of the soul’s immortality: for he maintains what nobody
denies, that everything which has been generated will perish, and that
even souls are generated, which he thinks appears from their resemblance
to those of the men who begot them; for that likeness is as apparent in
the turn of their minds as in their bodies. But he brings another
reason—that there is nothing which is sensible of pain which is not
also liable to disease; but whatever is liable to disease must be liable
to death. The soul is sensible of pain, therefore it is liable to
perish.
XXXIII. These arguments may be refuted; for they proceed from his not
knowing that, while discussing the subject of the immortality of the
soul, he is speaking of the intellect, which is free from all turbid
motion; but not of those parts of the mind in which those disorders,
44anger and lust, have their seat, and which he whom he is opposing, when
he argues thus, imagines to be distinct and separate from the mind. Now
this resemblance is more remarkable in beasts, whose souls are void of
reason. But the likeness in men consists more in the configuration of
the bodies: and it is of no little consequence in what bodies the soul
is lodged; for there are many things which depend on the body that give
an edge to the soul, many which blunt it. Aristotle, indeed, says that
all men of great genius are melancholy; so that I should not have been
displeased to have been somewhat duller than I am. He instances many,
and, as if it were matter of fact, brings his reasons for it. But if the
power of those things that proceed from the body be so great as to
influence the mind (for they are the things, whatever they are, that
occasion this likeness), still that does not necessarily prove why a
similitude of souls should be generated. I say nothing about cases of
unlikeness. I wish Panætius could be here: he lived with Africanus. I
would inquire of him which of his family the nephew of Africanus’s
brother was like? Possibly he may in person have resembled his father;
but in his manners he was so like every profligate, abandoned man, that
it was impossible to be more so. Whom did the grandson of P. Crassus,
that wise and eloquent and most distinguished man, resemble? Or the
relations and sons of many other excellent men, whose names there is no
occasion to mention? But what are we doing? Have we forgotten that our
purpose was, when we had sufficiently spoken on the subject of the
immortality of the soul, to prove that, even if the soul did perish,
there would be, even then, no evil in death?
A. I remembered it very well; but I had no dislike to your digressing
a little from your original design, while you were talking of the soul’s
immortality.
M. I perceive you have sublime thoughts, and are eager to mount up to
heaven.
XXXIV. I am not without hopes myself that such may be our fate. But
admit what they assert—that the soul does not continue to exist after
death.
A. Should it be so, I see that we are then deprived of the hopes of a
happier life.
45M. But what is there of evil in that opinion? For let the soul perish
as the body: is there any pain, or indeed any feeling at all, in the
body after death? No one, indeed asserts that; though Epicurus charges
Democritus with saying so; but the disciples of Democritus deny it. No
sense, therefore, remains in the soul; for the soul is nowhere. Where,
then, is the evil? for there is nothing but these two things. Is it
because the mere separation of the soul and body cannot be effected
without pain? But even should that be granted, how small a pain must
that be! Yet I think that it is false, and that it is very often
unaccompanied by any sensation at all, and sometimes even attended with
pleasure; but certainly the whole must be very trifling, whatever it is,
for it is instantaneous. What makes us uneasy, or rather gives us pain,
is the leaving all the good things of life. But just consider if I might
not more properly say, leaving the evils of life; only there is no
reason for my now occupying myself in bewailing the life of man, and yet
I might, with very good reason. But what occasion is there, when what I
am laboring to prove is that no one is miserable after death, to make
life more miserable by lamenting over it? I have done that in the book
which I wrote, in order to comfort myself as well as I could. If, then,
our inquiry is after truth, death withdraws us from evil, not from good.
This subject is indeed so copiously handled by Hegesias, the Cyrenaic
philosopher, that he is said to have been forbidden by Ptolemy from
delivering his lectures in the schools, because some who heard him made
away with themselves. There is, too, an epigram of Callimachus20 on
Cleombrotus of Ambracia, who, without any misfortune having befallen
him, as he says, threw himself from a wall into the sea, after he had
read a book of Plato’s. The book I mentioned of that Hegesias is called
Ἀποκαρτερτερῶν, or “A Man who
46starves himself,” in which a man is represented as killing
himself by starvation, till he is prevented by his friends,
in reply to whom he reckons up all the miseries of human
life. I might do the same, though not so fully as he, who
thinks it not worth any man’s while to live. I pass over
others. Was it even worth my while to live, for, had I
died before I was deprived of the comforts of my own
family, and of the honors which I received for my public
services, would not death have taken me from the evils of
life rather than from its blessings?
XXXV. Mention, therefore, some one, who never knew
distress; who never received any blow from fortune.
The great Metellus had four distinguished sons; but
Priam had fifty, seventeen of whom were born to him by
his lawful wife. Fortune had the same power over both,
though she exercised it but on one; for Metellus was laid
on his funeral pile by a great company of sons and daughters,
grandsons, and granddaughters; but Priam fell by
the hand of an enemy, after having fled to the altar, and
having seen himself deprived of all his numerous progeny.
Had he died before the death of his sons and the ruin of
his kingdom,
With all his mighty wealth elate,
Under rich canopies of state;
would he then have been taken from good or from evil?
It would indeed, at that time, have appeared that he was
being taken away from good; yet surely it would have
turned out advantageous for him; nor should we have
had these mournful verses,
Lo! these all perish’d in one flaming pile;
The foe old Priam did of life beguile,
And with his blood, thy altar, Jove, defile.
As if anything better could have happened to him at that
time than to lose his life in that manner; but yet, if it had
befallen him sooner, it would have prevented all those consequences;
but even as it was, it released him from any
further sense of them. The case of our friend Pompey21
47was something better: once, when he had been very ill
at Naples, the Neapolitans, on his recovery, put crowns
on their heads, as did those of Puteoli; the people flocked
from the country to congratulate him—it is a Grecian
custom, and a foolish one; still it is a sign of good fortune.
But the question is, had he died, would he have
been taken from good, or from evil? Certainly from
evil. He would not have been engaged in a war with his
father-in-law;22 he would not have taken up arms before
he was prepared; he would not have left his own house,
nor fled from Italy; he would not, after the loss of his
army, have fallen unarmed into the hands of slaves, and
been put to death by them; his children would not have
been destroyed; nor would his whole fortune have come
into the possession of the conquerors. Did not he, then,
who, if he had died at that time, would have died in all
his glory, owe all the great and terrible misfortunes into
which he subsequently fell to the prolongation of his life
at that time?
XXXVI. These calamities are avoided by death, for
even though they should never happen, there is a possibility
that they may; but it never occurs to a man that such
a disaster may befall him himself. Every one hopes to
be as happy as Metellus: as if the number of the happy
exceeded that of the miserable; or as if there were any
certainty in human affairs; or, again, as if there were
more rational foundation for hope than fear. But should
we grant them even this, that men are by death deprived
of good things; would it follow that the dead are therefore
in need of the good things of life, and are miserable
on that account? Certainly they must necessarily say so.
Can he who does not exist be in need of anything? To
be in need of has a melancholy sound, because it in effect
amounts to this—he had, but he has not; he regrets, he
looks back upon, he wants. Such are, I suppose, the distresses
48of one who is in need of. Is he deprived
of eyes? to be blind is misery. Is he destitute of children? not to have
them is misery. These considerations apply to the living, but the dead
are neither in need of the blessings of life, nor of life itself. But
when I am speaking of the dead, I am speaking of those who have no
existence. But would any one say of us, who do exist, that we want horns
or wings? Certainly not. Should it be asked, why not? the answer would
be, that not to have what neither custom nor nature has fitted you for
would not imply a want of them, even though you were sensible that you
had them not. This argument should be pressed over and over again, after
that point has once been established, which, if souls are mortal, there
can be no dispute about—I mean, that the destruction of them by death
is so entire as to remove even the least suspicion of any sense
remaining. When, therefore, this point is once well grounded and
established, we must correctly define what the term to want means; that
there may be no mistake in the word. To want, then, signifies this: to
be without that which you would be glad to have; for inclination for a
thing is implied in the word want, excepting when we use the word in an
entirely different sense, as we do when we say that a fever is wanting
to any one. For it admits of a different interpretation, when you are
without a certain thing, and are sensible that you are without it, but
yet can easily dispense with having it. “To want,” then, is an
expression which you cannot apply to the dead; nor is the mere fact of
wanting something necessarily lamentable. The proper expression ought to
be, “that they want a good,” and that is an evil.
But a living man does not want a good, unless he is distressed without
it; and yet, we can easily understand how any man alive can be without a
kingdom. But this cannot be predicated of you with any accuracy: it
might have been asserted of Tarquin, when he was driven from his
kingdom. But when such an expression is used respecting the dead, it is
absolutely unintelligible. For to want implies to be sensible; but the
dead are insensible: therefore, the dead can be in no want.
XXXVII. But what occasion is there to philosophize 49here in a matter
with which we see that philosophy is but little concerned? How often
have not only our generals but whole armies, rushed on certain death!
But if it had been a thing to be feared, L. Brutus would never have
fallen in fight, to prevent the return of that tyrant whom he had
expelled; nor would Decius the father have been slain in fighting with
the Latins; nor would his son, when engaged with the Etruscans, nor his
grandson with Pyrrhus have exposed themselves to the enemy’s darts.
Spain would never have seen, in one campaign, the Scipios fall fighting
for their country; nor would the plains of Cannæ have witnessed the
death of Paulus and Geminus, or Venusia that of Marcellus; nor would the
Latins have beheld the death of Albinus, nor the Leucanians that of
Gracchus. But are any of these miserable now? Nay, they were not so even
at the first moment after they had breathed their last; nor can any one
be miserable after he has lost all sensation. Oh, but the mere
circumstance of being without sensation is miserable. It might be so if
being without sensation were the same thing as wanting it; but as it is
evident there can be nothing of any kind in that which has no existence,
what can there be afflicting to that which can neither feel want nor be
sensible of anything? We might be said to have repeated this over too
often, only that here lies all that the soul shudders at from the fear
of death. For whoever can clearly apprehend that which is as manifest as
the light—that when both soul and body are consumed, and there is a
total destruction, then that which was an animal becomes nothing—will
clearly see that there is no difference between a Hippocentaur, which
never had existence, and King Agamemnon, and that M. Camillus is no more
concerned about this present civil war than I was at the sacking of
Rome, when he was living.
XXXVIII. Why, then, should Camillus be affected with the thoughts of
these things happening three hundred and fifty years after his time? And
why should I be uneasy it I were to expect that some nation might
possess itself of this city ten thousand years hence? Because so great
is our regard for our country, as not to be measured by our own feeling,
but by its own actual safety.
50Death, then, which threatens us daily from a thousand accidents, and
which, by reason of the shortness of life, can never be far off, does
not deter a wise man from making such provision for his country and his
family as he hopes may last forever; and from regarding posterity, of
which he can never have any real perception, as belonging to himself.
Wherefore a man may act for eternity, even though he be persuaded that
his soul is mortal; not, indeed, from a desire of glory, which he will
be insensible of, but from a principle of virtue, which glory will
inevitably attend, though that is not his object. The process, indeed,
of nature is this: that just in the same manner as our birth was the
beginning of things with us, so death will be the end; and as we were
noways concerned with anything before we were born, so neither shall we
be after we are dead. And in this state of things where can the evil be,
since death has no connection with either the living or the dead? The
one have no existence at all, the other are not yet affected by it. They
who make the least of death consider it as having a great resemblance to
sleep; as if any one would choose to live ninety years on condition
that, at the expiration of sixty, he should sleep out the remainder. The
very swine would not accept of life on those terms, much less I.
Endymion, indeed, if you listen to fables, slept once on a time on
Latmus, a mountain of Caria, and for such a length of time that I
imagine he is not as yet awake. Do you think that he is concerned at the
Moon’s being in difficulties, though it was by her that he was thrown
into that sleep, in order that she might kiss him while sleeping. For
what should he be concerned for who has not even any sensation? You look
on sleep as an image of death, and you take that on you daily; and have
you, then, any doubt that there is no sensation in death, when you see
there is none in sleep, which is its near resemblance?
XXXIX. Away, then, with those follies, which are little better than the
old women’s dreams, such as that it is miserable to die before our time.
What time do you mean? That of nature? But she has only lent you life,
as she might lend you money, without fixing any certain time for its
repayment. Have you any grounds of complaint, 51then, that she recalls it
at her pleasure? for you received it on these terms. They that complain
thus allow that if a young child dies, the survivors ought to bear his
loss with equanimity; that if an infant in the cradle dies, they ought
not even to utter a complaint; and yet nature has been more severe with
them in demanding back what she gave. They answer by saying that such
have not tasted the sweets of life; while the other had begun to
conceive hopes of great happiness, and, indeed, had begun to realize
them. Men judge better in other things, and allow a part to be
preferable to none. Why do they not admit the same estimate in life?
Though Callimachus does not speak amiss in saying that more tears had
flowed from Priam than his son; yet they are thought happier who die
after they have reached old age. It would be hard to say why; for I do
not apprehend that any one, if a longer life were granted to him, would
find it happier. There is nothing more agreeable to a man than prudence,
which old age most certainly bestows on a man, though it may strip him
of everything else. But what age is long, or what is there at all long
to a man? Does not
Old age, though unregarded, still attend
On childhood’s pastimes, as the cares of men?
But because there is nothing beyond old age, we call that long: all
these things are said to be long or short, according to the proportion
of time they were given us for. Artistotle saith there is a kind of
insect near the river Hypanis, which runs from a certain part of Europe
into the Pontus, whose life consists but of one day; those that die at
the eighth hour die in full age; those who die when the sun sets are
very old, especially when the days are at the longest. Compare our
longest life with eternity, and we shall be found almost as short-lived
as those little animals.
XL. Let us, then, despise all these follies—for what softer name can I
give to such levities?—and let us lay the foundation of our happiness
in the strength and greatness of our minds, in a contempt and disregard
of all earthly things, and in the practice of every virtue. For at
present we are enervated by the softness of our imaginations, 52so that,
should we leave this world before the promises of our fortune-tellers
are made good to us, we should think ourselves deprived of some great
advantages, and seem disappointed and forlorn. But if, through life, we
are in continual suspense, still expecting, still desiring, and are in
continual pain and torture, good Gods! how pleasant must that journey be
which ends in security and ease! How pleased am I with Theramenes! Of
how exalted a soul does he appear! For, although we never read of him
without tears, yet that illustrious man is not to be lamented in his
death, who, when he had been imprisoned by the command of the thirty
tyrants, drank off, at one draught, as if he had been thirsty, the
poisoned cup, and threw the remainder out of it with such force that it
sounded as it fell; and then, on hearing the sound of the drops, he
said, with a smile, “I drink this to the most excellent Critias,” who
had been his most bitter enemy; for it is customary among the Greeks, at
their banquets, to name the person to whom they intend to deliver the
cup. This celebrated man was pleasant to the last, even when he had
received the poison into his bowels, and truly foretold the death of
that man whom he named when he drank the poison, and that death soon
followed. Who that thinks death an evil could approve of the evenness of
temper in this great man at the instant of dying? Socrates came, a few
years after, to the same prison and the same cup by as great iniquity on
the part of his judges as the tyrants displayed when they executed
Theramenes. What a speech is that which Plato makes him deliver before
his judges, after they had condemned him to death!
XLI. “I am not without hopes, O judges, that it is a favorable
circumstance for me that I am condemned to die; for one of these two
things must necessarily happen—either that death will deprive me
entirely of all sense, or else that, by dying, I shall go from hence
into some other place; wherefore, if all sense is utterly extinguished,
and if death is like that sleep which sometimes is so undisturbed as to
be even without the visions of dreams—in that case, O ye good Gods!
what gain is it to die? or what length of days can be imagined which
would be preferable to such a night? And if the constant course of
future time 53is to resemble that night, who is happier than I am? But if
on the other hand, what is said be true, namely, that death is but a
removal to those regions where the souls of the departed dwell, then
that state must be more happy still to have escaped from those who call
themselves judges, and to appear before such as are truly so—Minos,
Rhadamanthus, Æacus, Triptolemus—and to meet with those who have lived
with justice and probity!23 Can this change of abode appear otherwise
than great to you? What bounds can you set to the value of conversing
with Orpheus, and Musæus, and Homer, and Hesiod? I would even, were it
possible, willingly die often, in order to prove the certainty of what I
speak of. What delight must it be to meet with Palamedes, and Ajax, and
others, who have been betrayed by the iniquity of their judges! Then,
also, should I experience the wisdom of even that king of kings, who led
his vast troops to Troy, and the prudence of Ulysses and Sisyphus: nor
should I then be condemned for prosecuting my inquiries on such subjects
in the same way in which I have done here on earth. And even you, my
judges, you, I mean, who have voted for my acquittal, do not you fear
death, for nothing bad can befall a good man, whether he be alive or
dead; nor are his concerns ever overlooked by the Gods; nor in my case
either has this befallen me by chance; and I have nothing to charge
those men with who accused or condemned me but the fact that they
believed that they were doing me harm.” In this manner he proceeded.
There is no part of his speech which I admire more than his last words:
“But it is time,” says he, “for me now to go hence, that I may die; and
for you, that you may continue to live. Which condition of the two is
the best, the immortal Gods know; but I do not believe that any mortal
man does.”
54XLII. Surely I would rather have had this man’s soul than all the
fortunes of those who sat in judgment on him; although that very thing
which he says no one except the Gods know, namely, whether life or death
is most preferable, he knows himself, for he had previously stated his
opinion on it; but he maintained to the last that favorite maxim of his,
of affirming nothing. And let us, too, adhere to this rule of not
thinking anything an evil which is a general provision of nature; and
let us assure ourselves, that if death is an evil, it is an eternal
evil, for death seems to be the end of a miserable life; but if death is
a misery, there can be no end of that. But why do I mention Socrates, or
Theramenes, men distinguished by the glory of virtue and wisdom? when a
certain Lacedæmomian, whose name is not so much as known, held death in
such contempt, that, when led to it by the ephori, he bore a cheerful
and pleasant countenance; and, when he was asked by one of his enemies
whether he despised the laws of Lycurgus, “On the contrary,” answered
he, “I am greatly obliged to him, for he has amerced me in a fine which
I can pay without borrowing, or taking up money at interest.” This was a
man worthy of Sparta. And I am almost persuaded of his innocence because
of the greatness of his soul. Our own city has produced many such. But
why should I name generals, and other men of high rank, when Cato could
write that legions have marched with alacrity to that place from whence
they never expected to return? With no less greatness of soul fell the
Lacedæmonians at Thermopylæ, on whom Simonides wrote the following
epitaph:
Go, stranger, tell the Spartans, here we lie,
Who to support their laws durst boldly die.
24
What was it that Leonidas, their general, said to them? “March on with
courage, my Lacedæmonians. To-night, perhaps, we shall sup in the
regions below.” This was a brave nation while the laws of Lycurgus were
in force. One of them, when a Persian had said to him in conversation,
55“We shall hide the sun from your sight by the number of our arrows and
darts,” replied, “We shall fight, then in the shade.” Do I talk of their
men? How great was that Lacedæmonian woman, who had sent her son to
battle, and when she heard that he was slain, said, “I bore him for that
purpose, that you might have a man who durst die for his country!”
However, it is a matter of notoriety that the Spartans were bold and
hardy, for the discipline of a republic has great influence.
XLIII. What, then, have we not reason to admire Theodorus the Cyrenean,
a philosopher of no small distinction, who, when Lysimachus threatened
to crucify him, bade him keep those menaces for his courtiers? “To
Theodorus it makes no difference whether he rot in the air or
underground.” By which saying of the philosopher I am reminded to say
something of the custom of funerals and sepulture, and of funeral
ceremonies, which is, indeed, not a difficult subject, especially if we
recollect what has been before said about insensibility. The opinion of
Socrates respecting this matter is clearly stated in the book which
treats of his death, of which we have already said so much; for when he
had discussed the immortality of the soul, and when the time of his
dying was approaching rapidly, being asked by Criton how he would be
buried, “I have taken a great deal of pains,” saith he, “my friends, to
no purpose, for I have not convinced our Criton that I shall fly from
hence, and leave no part of me behind. Notwithstanding, Criton, if you
can overtake me, wheresoever you get hold of me, bury me as you please:
but believe me, none of you will be able to catch me when I have flown
away from hence.” That was excellently said, inasmuch as he allows his
friend to do as he pleased, and yet shows his indifference about
anything of this kind. Diogenes was rougher, though of the same opinion;
but in his character of a Cynic he expressed himself in a somewhat
harsher manner; he ordered himself to be thrown anywhere without being
buried. And when his friends replied, “What! to the birds and beasts?”
“By no means,” saith he; “place my staff near me, that I may drive them
away.” “How can you do that,” they answer, “for you will not perceive
them?” “How am I then 56injured by being torn by those animals, if I have
no sensation?” Anaxagoras, when he was at the point of death at
Lampsacus, and was asked by his friends, whether, if anything should
happen to him, he would not choose to be carried to Clazomenæ, his
country, made this excellent answer, “There is,” says he, “no occasion
for that, for all places are at an equal distance from the infernal
regions.” There is one thing to be observed with respect to the whole
subject of burial, that it relates to the body, whether the soul live or
die. Now, with regard to the body, it is clear that, whether the soul
live or die, that has no sensation.
XLIV. But all things are full of errors. Achilles drags Hector, tied to
his chariot; he thinks, I suppose, he tears his flesh, and that Hector
feels the pain of it; therefore, he avenges himself on him, as he
imagines. But Hecuba bewails this as a sore misfortune:
I saw (a dreadful sight) great Hector slain,
Dragg’d at Achilles’ car along the plain.
What Hector? or how long will he be Hector? Accius is better in this,
and Achilles, too, is sometimes reasonable:
I Hector’s body to his sire convey’d,
Hector I sent to the infernal shade.
It was not Hector that you dragged along, but a body that had been
Hector’s. Here another starts from underground, and will not suffer his
mother to sleep:
To thee I call, my once-loved parent, hear,
Nor longer with thy sleep relieve thy care;
Thine eye which pities not is closed—arise;
Ling’ring I wait the unpaid obsequies.
When these verses are sung with a slow and melancholy tune, so as to
affect the whole theatre with sadness, one can scarce help thinking
those unhappy that are unburied:
Ere the devouring dogs and hungry vultures...
He is afraid he shall not have the use of his limbs so well if they are
torn to pieces, but is under no such apprehensions if they are burned:
57
Nor leave my naked bones, my poor remains,
To shameful violence and bloody stains.
I do not understand what he could fear who could pour forth such
excellent verses to the sound of the flute. We must, therefore, adhere
to this, that nothing is to be regarded after we are dead, though many
people revenge themselves on their dead enemies. Thyestes pours forth
several curses in some good lines of Ennius, praying, first of all, that
Atreus may perish by a shipwreck, which is certainly a very terrible
thing, for such a death is not free from very grievous sensations. Then
follow these unmeaning expressions:
May
On the sharp rock his mangled carcass lie,
His entrails torn, to hungry birds a prey!
May he convulsive writhe his bleeding side,
And with his clotted gore the stones be dyed!
The rocks themselves were not more destitute of feeling than he who was
hanging to them by his side; though Thyestes imagines he is wishing him
the greatest torture. It would be torture, indeed, if he were sensible;
but as he is not, it can be none; then how very unmeaning is this:
Let him, still hovering o’er the Stygian wave,
Ne’er reach the body’s peaceful port, the grave!
You see under what mistaken notions all this is said. He imagines the
body has its haven, and that the dead are at rest in their graves.
Pelops was greatly to blame in not having informed and taught his son
what regard was due to everything.
XLV. But what occasion is there to animadvert on the opinions of
individuals, when we may observe whole nations to fall into all sorts of
errors? The Egyptians embalm their dead, and keep them in their houses;
the Persians dress them over with wax, and then bury them, that they may
preserve their bodies as long as possible. It is customary with the Magi
to bury none of their order, unless they have been first torn by wild
beasts. In Hyrcania, the people maintain dogs for the public use; the
nobles have their own—and we know that they have a good breed of dogs;
but every one, according to his ability, 58provides himself with some, in
order to be torn by them; and they hold that to be the best kind of
interment. Chrysippus, who is curious in all kinds of historical facts,
has collected many other things of this kind; but some of them are so
offensive as not to admit of being related. All that has been said of
burying is not worth our regard with respect to ourselves, though it is
not to be neglected as to our friends, provided we are thoroughly aware
that the dead are insensible. But the living, indeed, should consider
what is due to custom and opinion; only they should at the same time
consider that the dead are noways interested in it. But death truly is
then met with the greatest tranquillity when the dying man can comfort
himself with his own praise. No one dies too soon who has finished the
course of perfect virtue. I myself have known many occasions when I have
seemed in danger of immediate death; oh! how I wish it had come to me!
for I have gained nothing by the delay. I had gone over and over again
the duties of life; nothing remained but to contend with fortune. If
reason, then, cannot sufficiently fortify us to enable us to feel a
contempt for death, at all events let our past life prove that we have
lived long enough, and even longer than was necessary; for
notwithstanding the deprivation of sense, the dead are not without that
good which peculiarly belongs to them, namely, the praise and glory
which they have acquired, even though they are not sensible of it. For
although there be nothing in glory to make it desirable, yet it follows
virtue as its shadow; and the genuine judgment of the multitude on good
men, if ever they form any, is more to their own praise than of any real
advantage to the dead. Yet I cannot say, however it may be received,
that Lycurgus and Solon have no glory from their laws, and from the
political constitution which they established in their country; or that
Themistocles and Epaminondas have not glory from their martial virtue.
XLVI. For Neptune shall sooner bury Salamis itself with his waters than
the memory of the trophies gained there; and the BЕ“otian Leuctra shall
perish sooner than the glory of that great battle. And longer still
shall fame be before it deserts Curius, and Fabricius, and Calatinus,
59and the two Scipios, and the two Africani, and Maximus, and Marcellus,
and Paulus, and Cato, and Lælius, and numberless other heroes; and
whoever has caught any resemblance of them, not estimating it by common
fame, but by the real applause of good men, may with confidence, when
the occasion requires, approach death, on which we are sure that even if
the chief good is not continued, at least no evil is. Such a man would
even wish to die while in prosperity; for all the favors that could be
heaped on him would not be so agreeable to him as the loss of them would
be painful. That speech of the Lacedæmonian seems to have the same
meaning, who, when Diagoras the Rhodian, who had himself been a
conqueror at the Olympic games, saw two of his own sons conquerors there
on the same day, approached the old man, and, congratulating him, said,
“You should die now, Diagoras, for no greater happiness can possibly
await you.” The Greeks look on these as great things; perhaps they think
too highly of them, or, rather, they did so then. And so he who said
this to Diagoras, looking on it as something very glorious, that three
men out of one family should have been conquerors there, thought it
could answer no purpose to him to continue any longer in life, where he
could only be exposed to a reverse of fortune.
I might have given you a sufficient answer, as it seems to me, on this
point, in a few words, as you had allowed the dead were not exposed to
any positive evil; but I have spoken at greater length on the subject
for this reason, because this is our greatest consolation in the losing
and bewailing of our friends. For we ought to bear with moderation any
grief which arises from ourselves, or is endured on our own account,
lest we should seem to be too much influenced by self-love. But should
we suspect our departed friends to be under those evils, which they are
generally imagined to be, and to be sensible of them, then such a
suspicion would give us intolerable pain; and accordingly I wished, for
my own sake, to pluck up this opinion by the roots, and on that account
I have been perhaps somewhat more prolix than was necessary.
XLVII. A. More prolix than was necessary? Certainty not, in my
opinion. For I was induced, by the former 60part of your speech, to wish
to die; but, by the latter, sometimes not to be unwilling, and at others
to be wholly indifferent about it. But the effect of your whole argument
is, that I am convinced that death ought not to be classed among the
evils.
M. Do you, then, expect that I am to give you a regular peroration,
like the rhetoricians, or shall I forego that art?
A. I would not have you give over an art which you have set off to
such advantage; and you were in the right to do so, for, to speak the
truth, it also has set you off. But what is that peroration? For I
should be glad to hear it, whatever it is.
M. It is customary, in the schools, to produce the opinions of the
immortal Gods on death; nor are these opinions the fruits of the
imagination alone of the lecturers, but they have the authority of
Herodotus and many others. Cleobis and Biton are the first they mention,
sons of the Argive priestess; the story is a well-known one. As it was
necessary that she should be drawn in a chariot to a certain annual
sacrifice, which was solemnized at a temple some considerable distance
from the town, and the cattle that were to draw the chariot had not
arrived, those two young men whom I have just mentioned, pulling off
their garments, and anointing their bodies with oil, harnessed
themselves to the yoke. And in this manner the priestess was conveyed to
the temple; and when the chariot had arrived at the proper place, she is
said to have entreated the Goddess to bestow on them, as a reward for
their piety, the greatest gift that a God could confer on man. And the
young men, after having feasted with their mother, fell asleep; and in
the morning they were found dead. Trophonius and Agamedes are said to
have put up the same petition, for they, having built a temple to Apollo
at Delphi, offered supplications to the God, and desired of him some
extraordinary reward for their care and labor, particularizing nothing,
but asking for whatever was best for men. Accordingly, Apollo signified
to them that he would bestow it on them in three days, and on the third
day at daybreak they were found dead. And so they say that this was a
formal decision pronounced by that God to 61whom the rest of the deities
have assigned the province of divining with an accuracy superior to that
of all the rest.
XLVIII. There is also a story told of Silenus, who, when taken prisoner
by Midas, is said to have made him this present for his ransom—namely,
that he informed him25 that never to have been born was by far the
greatest blessing that could happen to man; and that the next best thing
was to die very soon; which very opinion Euripides makes use of in his
Cresphontes, saying,
When man is born, �tis fit, with solemn show,
We speak our sense of his approaching woe;
With other gestures and a different eye,
Proclaim our pleasure when he’s bid to die.
26
There is something like this in Crantor’s Consolation; for he says that
Terinæsus of Elysia, when he was bitterly lamenting the loss of his son,
came to a place of divination to be informed why he was visited with so
great affliction, and received in his tablet these three verses:
Thou fool, to murmur at Euthynous’ death!
The blooming youth to fate resigns his breath:
The fate, whereon your happiness depends,
At once the parent and the son befriends.
27
On these and similar authorities they affirm that the question has been
determined by the Gods. Nay, more; Alcidamas, an ancient rhetorician of
the very highest reputation, wrote even in praise of death, which he
endeavored to establish by an enumeration of the evils of life; and his
Dissertation has a great deal of eloquence in it; but 62he was
unacquainted with the more refined arguments of the philosophers. By the
orators, indeed, to die for our country is always considered not only as
glorious, but even as happy: they go back as far as Erechtheus,28
whose very daughters underwent death, for the safety of their
fellow-citizens: they instance Codrus, who threw himself into the midst
of his enemies, dressed like a common man, that his royal robes might
not betray him, because the oracle had declared the Athenians
conquerors, if their king was slain. MenЕ“ceus29 is not overlooked by
them, who, in compliance with the injunctions of an oracle, freely shed
his blood for his country. Iphigenia ordered herself to be conveyed to
Aulis, to be sacrificed, that her blood might be the cause of spilling
that of her enemies.
XLIX. From hence they proceed to instances of a fresher date. Harmodius
and Aristogiton are in everybody’s mouth; the memory of Leonidas the
Lacedæmonian and Epaminondas the Theban is as fresh as ever. Those
philosophers were not acquainted with the many instances in our
country—to give a list of whom would take up too much time—who, we
see, considered death desirable as long as it was accompanied with
honor. But, notwithstanding this is the correct view of the case, we
must use much persuasion, speak as if we were endued with some higher
authority, in order to bring men to begin to wish to die, or cease to be
afraid of death. For if that last day does not occasion an entire
extinction, but a change of abode only, what can be more desirable? And
if it, on the other hand, destroys, and absolutely puts an end to us,
what can be preferable to the having a deep sleep fall on us, in the
midst of the fatigues of life, and being thus overtaken, to sleep to
eternity? And, should this really 63be the case, then Ennius’s language
is more consistent with wisdom than Solon’s; for our Ennius says,
Let none bestow upon my passing bier
One needless sigh or unavailing tear.
But the wise Solon says,
Let me not unlamented die, but o’er my bier
Burst forth the tender sigh, the friendly tear.
30
But let us, if indeed it should be our fate to know the time which is
appointed by the Gods for us to die, prepare ourselves for it with a
cheerful and grateful mind, thinking ourselves like men who are
delivered from a jail, and released from their fetters, for the purpose
of going back to our eternal habitation, which may be more emphatically
called our own; or else to be divested of all sense and trouble. If, on
the other hand, we should have no notice given us of this decree, yet
let us cultivate such a disposition as to look on that formidable hour
of death as happy for us, though shocking to our friends; and let us
never imagine anything to be an evil which is an appointment of the
immortal Gods, or of nature, the common parent of all. For it is not by
hazard or without design that we have been born and situated as we have.
On the contrary, beyond all doubt there is a certain power which
consults the happiness of human nature; and this would neither have
produced nor provided for a being which, after having gone through the
labors of life, was to fall into eternal misery by death. Let us rather
infer that we have a retreat and haven prepared for us, which I wish we
could crowd all sail and arrive at; but though the winds should not
serve, and we should be driven back, yet we shall to a certainty arrive
at that point eventually, though somewhat later. But how can that be
miserable for one which all must of necessity undergo? I have given you
a peroration, that you might not think I had overlooked or neglected
anything.
A. I am persuaded you have not; and, indeed, that peroration has
confirmed me.
64M. I am glad it has had that effect. But it is now time to consult
our health. To-morrow, and all the time we continue in this Tusculan
villa, let us consider this subject; and especially those portions of it
which may ease our pain, alleviate our fears, and lessen our desires,
which is the greatest advantage we can reap from the whole of
philosophy.
BOOK II.
ON BEARING PAIN.
I.
Neoptolemus, in Ennius, indeed, says that the study of philosophy was
expedient for him; but that it required limiting to a few subjects, for
that to give himself up entirely to it was what he did not approve of.
And for my part, Brutus, I am perfectly persuaded that it is expedient
for me to philosophize; for what can I do better, especially as I have
no regular occupation? But I am not for limiting my philosophy to a few
subjects, as he does; for philosophy is a matter in which it is
difficult to acquire a little knowledge without acquainting yourself
with many, or all its branches, nor can you well take a few subjects
without selecting them out of a great number; nor can any one, who has
acquired the knowledge of a few points, avoid endeavoring with the same
eagerness to understand more. But still, in a busy life, and in one
mainly occupied with military matters, such as that of Neoptolemus was
at that time, even that limited degree of acquaintance with philosophy
may be of great use, and may yield fruit, not perhaps so plentiful as a
thorough knowledge of the whole of philosophy, but yet such as in some
degree may at times deliver us from the dominion of our desires, our
sorrows, and our fears; just as the effect of that discussion which we
lately maintained in my Tusculan villa seemed to be that a great
contempt of death was engendered, which contempt is of no small efficacy
towards delivering the mind from fear; for whoever dreads what cannot be
avoided can by no means live with a quiet and tranquil mind. But he who
is under no
65fear of death, not only because it is a thing absolutely
inevitable but also because he is persuaded that death itself hath
nothing terrible in it, provides himself with a very great resource
towards a happy life. However, I am not tolerant that many will argue
strenuously against us; and, indeed, that is a thing which can never be
avoided, except by abstaining from writing at all. For if my Orations,
which were addressed to the judgment and approbation of the people (for
that is a popular art, and the object of oratory is popular applause),
have been criticised by some people who are inclined to withhold their
praise from everything but what they are persuaded they can attain to
themselves, and who limit their ideas of good speaking by the hopes
which they conceive of what they themselves may attain to, and who
declare, when they are overwhelmed with a flow of words and sentences,
that they prefer the utmost poverty of thought and expression to that
plenty and copiousness (from which arose the Attic kind of oratory,
which they who professed it were strangers to, though they have now been
some time silenced, and laughed out of the very courts of justice), what
may I not expect, when at present I cannot have the least countenance
from the people by whom I used to be upheld before? For philosophy is
satisfied with a few judges, and of her own accord industriously avoids
the multitude, who are jealous of it, and utterly displeased with it; so
that, should any one undertake to cry down the whole of it, he would
have the people on his side; while, if he should attack that school
which I particularly profess, he would have great assistance from those
of the other philosophers.
II. But I have answered the detractors of philosophy in general, in my
Hortensius. And what I had to say in favor of the Academics, is, I
think, explained with sufficient accuracy in my four books of the
Academic Question.
But yet I am so far from desiring that no one should write against me,
that it is what I most earnestly wish; for philosophy would never have
been in such esteem in Greece itself, if it had not been for the
strength which it acquired from the contentions and disputations of the
66most learned men; and therefore I recommend all men who have abilities
to follow my advice to snatch this art also from declining Greece, and
to transport it to this city; as our ancestors by their study and
industry have imported all their other arts which were worth having.
Thus the praise of oratory, raised from a low degree, is arrived at such
perfection that it must now decline, and, as is the nature of all
things, verge to its dissolution in a very short time. Let philosophy,
then, derive its birth in Latin language from this time, and let us lend
it our assistance, and bear patiently to be contradicted and refuted;
and although those men may dislike such treatment who are bound and
devoted to certain predetermined opinions, and are under such
obligations to maintain them that they are forced, for the sake of
consistency, to adhere to them even though they do not themselves wholly
approve of them; we, on the other hand, who pursue only probabilities,
and who cannot go beyond that which seems really likely, can confute
others without obstinacy, and are prepared to be confuted ourselves
without resentment. Besides, if these studies are ever brought home to
us, we shall not want even Greek libraries, in which there is an
infinite number of books, by reason of the multitude of authors among
them; for it is a common practice with many to repeat the same things
which have been written by others, which serves no purpose but to stuff
their shelves; and this will be our case, too, if many apply themselves
to this study.
III. But let us excite those, if possible, who have had a liberal
education, and are masters of an elegant style, and who philosophize
with reason and method.
For there is a certain class of them who would willingly be called
philosophers, whose books in our language are said to be numerous, and
which I do not despise; for, indeed, I never read them: but still,
because the authors themselves declare that they write without any
regularity, or method, or elegance, or ornament, I do not care to read
what must be so void of entertainment. There is no one in the least
acquainted with literature who does not know the style and sentiments of
that school; wherefore, since they are at no pains to express themselves
well, I
67do not see why they should be read by anybody except by one
another. Let them read them, if they please, who are of the same
opinions; for in the same manner as all men read Plato and the other
Socratics, with those who sprung from them, even those who do not agree
with their opinions, or are very indifferent about them; but scarcely
any one except their own disciples take Epicurus or Metrodorus into
their hands; so they alone read these Latin books who think that the
arguments contained in them are sound. But, in my opinion, whatever is
published should be recommended to the reading of every man of learning;
and though we may not succeed in this ourselves, yet nevertheless we
must be sensible that this ought to be the aim of every writer. And on
this account I have always been pleased with the custom of the
Peripatetics and Academics, of disputing on both sides of the question;
not solely from its being the only method of discovering what is
probable on every subject, but also because it affords the greatest
scope for practising eloquence; a method that Aristotle first made use
of, and afterward all the Aristotelians; and in our own memory Plilo,
whom we have often heard, appointed one time to treat of the precepts of
the rhetoricians, and another for philosophical discussion, to which
custom I was brought to conform by my friends at my Tusculum; and
accordingly our leisure time was spent in this manner. And therefore, as
yesterday before noon we applied ourselves to speaking, and in the
afternoon went down into the Academy, the discussions which were held
there I have acquainted you with, not in the manner of a narration, but
in almost the very same words which were employed in the debate.
IV. The discourse, then, was introduced in this manner while we were
walking, and it was commenced by some such an opening as this:
A. It is not to be expressed how much I was delighted, or rather
edified, by your discourse of yesterday. For although I am conscious to
myself that I have never been too fond of life, yet at times, when I
have considered that there would be an end to this life, and that I must
some time or other part with all its good things, a certain dread
68and
uneasiness used to intrude itself on my thoughts; but now, believe me, I
am so freed from that kind of uneasiness that there is nothing that I
think less worth any regard.
M. I am not at all surprised at that, for it is the effect of
philosophy, which is the medicine of our souls; it banishes all
groundless apprehensions, frees us from desires, and drives away fears:
but it has not the same influence over all men; it is of very great
influence when it falls in with a disposition well adapted to it. For
not only does Fortune, as the old proverb says, assist the bold, but
reason does so in a still greater degree; for it, by certain precepts,
as it were, strengthens even courage itself. You were born naturally
great and soaring, and with a contempt for all things which pertain to
man alone; therefore a discourse against death took easy possession of a
brave soul. But do you imagine that these same arguments have any force
with those very persons who have invented, and canvassed, and published
them, excepting indeed some very few particular persons? For how few
philosophers will you meet with whose life and manners are conformable
to the dictates of reason! who look on their profession, not as a means
of displaying their learning, but as a rule for their own practice! who
follow their own precepts, and comply with their own decrees! You may
see some of such levity and such vanity, that it would have been better
for them to have been ignorant; some covetous of money, some others
eager for glory, many slaves to their lusts; so that their discourses
and their actions are most strangely at variance; than which nothing in
my opinion can be more unbecoming: for just as if one who professed to
teach grammar should speak with impropriety, or a master of music sing
out of tune, such conduct has the worst appearance in these men, because
they blunder in the very particular with which they profess that they
are well acquainted. So a philosopher who errs in the conduct of his
life is the more infamous because he is erring in the very thing which
he pretends to teach, and, while he lays down rules to regulate life by,
is irregular in his own life.
V.
A. Should this be the case, is it not to be feared that
69you are
dressing up philosophy in false colors? For what stronger argument can
there be that it is of little use than that some very profound
philosophers live in a discreditable manner?
M. That, indeed, is no argument at all, for as all the fields which
are cultivated are not fruitful (and this sentiment of Accius is false,
and asserted without any foundation,
The ground you sow on is of small avail;
To yield a crop good seed can never fail),
it is not every mind which has been properly cultivated that produces
fruit; and, to go on with the comparison, as a field, although it may be
naturally fruitful, cannot produce a crop without dressing, so neither
can the mind without education; such is the weakness of either without
the other. Whereas philosophy is the culture of the mind: this it is
which plucks up vices by the roots; prepares the mind for the receiving
of seeds; commits them to it, or, as I may say, sows them, in the hope
that, when come to maturity, they may produce a plentiful harvest. Let
us proceed, then, as we began. Say, if you please, what shall be the
subject of our disputation.
A. I look on pain to be the greatest of all evils.
M. What, even greater than infamy?
A. I dare not indeed assert that; and I blush to think I am so soon
driven from my ground.
M. You would have had greater reason for blushing had you persevered
in it; for what is so unbecoming—what can appear worse to you, than
disgrace, wickedness, immorality? To avoid which, what pain is there
which we ought not (I will not say to avoid shirking, but even) of our
own accord to encounter, and undergo, and even to court?
A. I am entirely of that opinion; but, notwithstanding that pain is
not the greatest evil, yet surely it is an evil.
M. Do you perceive, then, how much of the terror of pain you have
given up on a small hint?
A. I see that plainly; but I should be glad to give up more of it.
M. I will endeavor to make you do so; but it is a great 70undertaking,
and I must have a disposition on your part which is not inclined to
offer any obstacles.
A. You shall have such: for as I behaved yesterday, so now I will
follow reason wherever she leads.
VI. M. First, then, I will speak of the weakness of many philosophers,
and those, too, of various sects; the head of whom, both in authority
and antiquity, was Aristippus, the pupil of Socrates, who hesitated not
to say that pain was the greatest of all evils. And after him Epicurus
easily gave in to this effeminate and enervated doctrine. After him
Hieronymus the Rhodian said, that to be without pain was the chief good,
so great an evil did pain appear to him to be. The rest, with the
exceptions of Zeno, Aristo, Pyrrho, were pretty much of the same opinion
that you were of just now—that it was indeed an evil, but that there
were many worse. When, then, nature herself, and a certain generous
feeling of virtue, at once prevents you from persisting in the assertion
that pain is the chief evil, and when you were driven from such an
opinion when disgrace was contrasted with pain, shall philosophy, the
preceptress of life, cling to this idea for so many ages? What duty of
life, what praise, what reputation, would be of such consequence that a
man should be desirous of gaining it at the expense of submitting to
bodily pain, when he has persuaded himself that pain is the greatest
evil? On the other side, what disgrace, what ignominy, would he not
submit to that he might avoid pain, when persuaded that it was the
greatest of evils? Besides, what person, if it be only true that pain is
the greatest of evils, is not miserable, not only when he actually feels
pain, but also whenever he is aware that it may befall him. And who is
there whom pain may not befall? So that it is clear that there is
absolutely no one who can possibly be happy. Metrodorus, indeed, thinks
that man perfectly happy whose body is free from all disorders, and who
has an assurance that it will always continue so; but who is there who
can be assured of that?
VII. But Epicurus, indeed, says such things that it should seem that his
design was only to make people laugh; for he affirms somewhere that if a
wise man were to be burned or put to the torture—you expect, perhaps,
71that he is going to say he would bear it, he would support himself
under it with resolution, he would not yield to it (and that by
Hercules! would be very commendable, and worthy of that very Hercules
whom I have just invoked): but even this will not satisfy Epicurus, that
robust and hardy man! No; his wise man, even if he were in Phalaris’s
bull, would say, How sweet it is! how little do I regard it! What,
sweet? Is it not sufficient, if it is not disagreeable? But those very
men who deny pain to be an evil are not in the habit of saying that it
is agreeable to any one to be tormented; they rather say that it is
cruel, or hard to bear, afflicting, unnatural, but still not an evil:
while this man who says that it is the only evil, and the very worst of
all evils, yet thinks that a wise man would pronounce it sweet. I do not
require of you to speak of pain in the same words which Epicurus uses—a
man, as you know, devoted to pleasure: he may make no difference, if he
pleases, between Phalaris’s bull and his own bed; but I cannot allow the
wise man to be so indifferent about pain. If he bears it with courage,
it is sufficient: that he should rejoice in it, I do not expect; for
pain is, beyond all question, sharp, bitter, against nature, hard to
submit to and to bear. Observe Philoctetes: We may allow him to lament,
for he saw Hercules himself groaning loudly through extremity of pain on
Mount Е’ta. The arrows with which Hercules presented him were then no
consolation to him, when
The viper’s bite, impregnating his veins
With poison, rack’d him with its bitter pains.
And therefore he cries out, desiring help, and wishing to die,
Oh that some friendly hand its aid would lend,
My body from this rock’s vast height to send
Into the briny deep! I’m all on fire,
And by this fatal wound must soon expire.
It is hard to say that the man who was obliged to cry out in this manner
was not oppressed with evil, and great evil too.
VIII. But let us observe Hercules himself, who was subdued by pain at
the very time when he was on the point 72of attaining immortality by
death. What words does Sophocles here put in his mouth, in his
Trachiniæ? who, when Deianira had put upon him a tunic dyed in the
centaur’s blood, and it stuck to his entrails, says,
What tortures I endure no words can tell,
Far greater these, than those which erst befell
From the dire terror of thy consort, Jove—
E’en stern Eurystheus’ dire command above;
This of thy daughter, Е’neus, is the fruit,
Beguiling me with her envenom’d suit,
Whose close embrace doth on my entrails prey,
Consuming life; my lungs forbid to play;
The blood forsakes my veins; my manly heart
Forgets to beat; enervated, each part
Neglects its office, while my fatal doom
Proceeds ignobly from the weaver’s loom.
The hand of foe ne’er hurt me, nor the fierce
Giant issuing from his parent earth.
Ne’er could the Centaur such a blow enforce,
No barbarous foe, nor all the Grecian force;
This arm no savage people could withstand,
Whose realms I traversed to reform the land.
Thus, though I ever bore a manly heart,
I fall a victim to a woman’s art.
IX.
Assist, my son, if thou that name dost hear,
My groans preferring to thy mother’s tear:
Convey her here, if, in thy pious heart,
Thy mother shares not an unequal part:
Proceed, be bold, thy father’s fate bemoan,
Nations will join, you will not weep alone.
Oh, what a sight is this same briny source,
Unknown before, through all my labors’ course!
That virtue, which could brave each toil but late,
With woman’s weakness now bewails its fate.
Approach, my son; behold thy father laid,
A wither’d carcass that implores thy aid;
Let all behold: and thou, imperious Jove,
On me direct thy lightning from above:
Now all its force the poison doth assume,
And my burnt entrails with its flame consume.
Crestfallen, unembraced, I now let fall
Listless, those hands that lately conquer’d all;
When the Nemæan lion own’d their force,
And he indignant fell a breathless corse;
The serpent slew, of the Lernean lake,
As did the Hydra of its force partake:
By this, too, fell the Erymanthian boar:
73E’en Cerberus did his weak strength deplore.
This sinewy arm did overcome with ease
That dragon, guardian of the Golden Fleece.
My many conquests let some others trace;
It’s mine to say, I never knew disgrace.
31
Can we then, despise pain, when we see Hercules himself giving vent to
his expressions of agony with such impatience?
X. Let us see what Г†schylus says, who was not only a poet but a
Pythagorean philosopher also, for that is the account which you have
received of him; how doth he make Prometheus bear the pain he suffered
for the Lemnian theft, when he clandestinely stole away the celestial
fire, and bestowed it on men, and was severely punished by Jupiter for
the theft. Fastened to Mount Caucasus, he speaks thus:
Thou heav’n-born race of Titans here fast bound,
Behold thy brother! As the sailors sound
With care the bottom, and their ships confine
To some safe shore, with anchor and with line;
So, by Jove’s dread decree, the God of fire
Confines me here the victim of Jove’s ire.
With baneful art his dire machine he shapes;
From such a God what mortal e’er escapes?
When each third day shall triumph o’er the night,
Then doth the vulture, with his talons light,
Seize on my entrails; which, in rav’nous guise,
He preys on! then with wing extended flies
Aloft, and brushes with his plumes the gore:
But when dire Jove my liver doth restore,
Back he returns impetuous to his prey,
Clapping his wings, he cuts th’ ethereal way.
Thus do I nourish with my blood this pest,
Confined my arms, unable to contest;
Entreating only that in pity Jove
Would take my life, and this cursed plague remove.
But endless ages past unheard my moan,
Sooner shall drops dissolve this very stone.
32
And therefore it scarcely seems possible to avoid calling a man who is
suffering, miserable; and if he is miserable, then pain is an evil.
74XI. A. Hitherto you are on my side; I will see to that by-and-by;
and, in the mean while, whence are those verses? I do not remember them.
M. I will inform you, for you are in the right to ask. Do you see that
I have much leisure?
A. What, then?
M. I imagine, when you were at Athens, you attended frequently at the
schools of the philosophers.
A. Yes, and with great pleasure.
M. You observed, then, that though none of them at that time were very
eloquent, yet they used to mix verses with their harangues.
A. Yes, and particularly Dionysius the Stoic used to employ a great
many.
M. You say right; but they were quoted without any appropriateness or
elegance. But our friend Philo used to give a few select lines and well
adapted; and in imitation of him, ever since I took a fancy to this kind
of elderly declamation, I have been very fond of quoting our poets; and
where I cannot be supplied from them, I translate from the Greek, that
the Latin language may not want any kind of ornament in this kind of
disputation.
But, do you not see how much harm is done by poets? They introduce the
bravest men lamenting over their misfortunes: they soften our minds; and
they are, besides, so entertaining, that we do not only read them, but
get them by heart. Thus the influence of the poets is added to our want
of discipline at home, and our tender and delicate manner of living, so
that between them they have deprived virtue of all its vigor and energy.
Plato, therefore, was right in banishing them from his commonwealth,
where he required the best morals, and the best form of government. But
we, who have all our learning from Greece, read and learn these works of
theirs from our childhood; and look on this as a liberal and learned
education.
XII. But why are we angry with the poets? We may find some philosophers,
those masters of virtue, who have taught that pain was the greatest of
evils. But you, young man, when you said but just now that it appeared
so to you, upon being asked by me what appeared greater than infamy,
gave up that opinion at a word. Suppose I ask 75Epicurus the same
question. He will answer that a trifling degree of pain is a greater
evil than the greatest infamy; for that there is no evil in infamy
itself, unless attended with pain. What pain, then, attends Epicurus,
when he says that very thing, that pain is the greatest evil! And yet
nothing can be a greater disgrace to a philosopher than to talk thus.
Therefore, you allowed enough when you admitted that infamy appeared to
you to be a greater evil than pain. And if you abide by this admission,
you will see how far pain should be resisted; and that our inquiry
should be not so much whether pain be an evil, as how the mind may be
fortified for resisting it. The Stoics infer from some petty quibbling
arguments that it is no evil, as if the dispute were about a word, and
not about the thing itself. Why do you impose upon me, Zeno? For when
you deny what appears very dreadful to me to be an evil, I am deceived,
and am at a loss to know why that which appears to me to be a most
miserable thing should be no evil. The answer is, that nothing is an
evil but what is base and vicious. You return to your trifling, for you
do not remove what made me uneasy. I know that pain is not vice—you
need not inform me of that: but show me that it makes no difference to
me whether I am in pain or not. It has never anything to do, say you,
with a happy life, for that depends upon virtue alone; but yet pain is
to be avoided. If I ask, why? It is disagreeable, against nature, hard
to bear, woful and afflicting.
XIII. Here are many words to express that by so many different forms
which we call by the single word evil. You are defining pain, instead of
removing it, when you say, it is disagreeable, unnatural, scarcely
possible to be endured or borne, nor are you wrong in saying so: but the
man who vaunts himself in such a manner should not give way in his
conduct, if it be true that nothing is good but what is honest, and
nothing evil but what is disgraceful. This would be wishing, not
proving. This argument is a better one, and has more truth in it—that
all things which Nature abhors are to be looked upon as evil; that those
which she approves of are to be considered as good: for when this is
admitted, and the dispute 76about words removed, that which they with
reason embrace, and which we call honest, right, becoming, and sometimes
include under the general name of virtue, appears so far superior to
everything else that all other things which are looked upon as the gifts
of fortune, or the good things of the body, seem trifling and
insignificant; and no evil whatever, nor all the collective body of
evils together, appears to be compared to the evil of infamy. Wherefore,
if, as you granted in the beginning, infamy is worse than pain, pain is
certainly nothing; for while it appears to you base and unmanly to
groan, cry out, lament, or faint under pain; while you cherish notions
of probity, dignity, honor, and, keeping your eye on them, refrain
yourself, pain will certainly yield to virtue, and, by the influence of
imagination, will lose its whole force.—For you must either admit that
there is no such thing as virtue, or you must despise every kind of
pain. Will you allow of such a virtue as prudence, without which no
virtue whatever can even be conceived? What, then? Will that suffer you
to labor and take pains to no purpose? Will temperance permit you to do
anything to excess? Will it be possible for justice to be maintained by
one who through the force of pain discovers secrets, or betrays his
confederates, or deserts many duties of life? Will you act in a manner
consistently with courage, and its attendants, greatness of soul,
resolution, patience, and contempt for all worldly things? Can you hear
yourself called a great man when you lie grovelling, dejected, and
deploring your condition with a lamentable voice; no one would call you
even a man while in such a condition. You must therefore either abandon
all pretensions to courage, or else pain must be put out of the
question.
XIV. You know very well that, even though part of your Corinthian
furniture were gone, the remainder might be safe without that; but if
you lose one virtue (though virtue in reality cannot be lost), still if,
I say, you should acknowledge that you were deficient in one, you would
be stripped of all. Can you, then, call yourself a brave man, of a great
soul, endued with patience and steadiness above the frowns of fortune?
or Philoctetes? for I choose to instance him, rather than yourself, for
he certainly was not 77a brave man, who lay in his bed, which was watered
with his tears,
Whose groans, bewailings, and whose bitter cries,
With grief incessant rent the very skies.
I do not deny pain to be pain—for were that the case, in what would
courage consist?—but I say it should be assuaged by patience, if there
be such a thing as patience: if there be no such thing, why do we speak
so in praise of philosophy? or why do we glory in its name? Does pain
annoy us? Let it sting us to the heart: if you are without defensive
armor, bare your throat to it; but if you are secured by Vulcanian
armor, that is to say by resolution, resist it. Should you fail to do
so, that guardian of your honor, your courage, will forsake and leave
you.—By the laws of Lycurgus, and by those which were given to the
Cretans by Jupiter, or which Minos established under the direction of
Jupiter, as the poets say, the youths of the State are trained by the
practice of hunting, running, enduring hunger and thirst, cold and heat.
The boys at Sparta are scourged so at the altars that blood follows the
lash in abundance; nay, sometimes, as I used to hear when I was there,
they are whipped even to death; and yet not one of them was ever heard
to cry out, or so much as groan. What, then? Shall men not be able to
bear what boys do? and shall custom have such great force, and reason
none at all?
XV. There is some difference between labor and pain; they border upon
one another, but still there is a certain difference between them. Labor
is a certain exercise of the mind or body, in some employment or
undertaking of serious trouble and importance; but pain is a sharp
motion in the body, disagreeable to our senses.—Both these feelings,
the Greeks, whose language is more copious than ours, express by the
common name of О бЅ№ОЅОїП‚: therefore they call industrious men painstaking,
or, rather, fond of labor; we, more conveniently, call them laborious;
for laboring is one thing, and enduring pain another. You see, O Greece!
your barrenness of words, sometimes, though you think you are always so
rich in them. I say, then, that there is a difference between laboring
and being in 78pain. When Caius Marius had an operation performed for a
swelling in his thigh, he felt pain; when he headed his troops in a very
hot season, he labored. Yet these two feelings bear some resemblance to
one another; for the accustoming ourselves to labor makes the endurance
of pain more easy to us. And it was because they were influenced by this
reason that the founders of the Grecian form of government provided that
the bodies of their youth should be strengthened by labor, which custom
the Spartans transferred even to their women, who in other cities lived
more delicately, keeping within the walls of their houses; but it was
otherwise with the Spartans.
The Spartan women, with a manly air,
Fatigues and dangers with their husbands share;
They in fantastic sports have no delight,
Partners with them in exercise and fight.
And in these laborious exercises pain interferes sometimes. They are
thrown down, receive blows, have bad falls, and are bruised, and the
labor itself produces a sort of callousness to pain.
XVI. As to military service (I speak of our own, not of that of the
Spartans, for they used to march slowly to the sound of the flute, and
scarce a word of command was given without an anapæst), you may see, in
the first place, whence the very name of an army (exercitus33) is
derived; and, secondly, how great the labor is of an army on its march:
then consider that they carry more than a fortnight’s provision, and
whatever else they may want; that they carry the burden of the
stakes,34 for as to shield, sword, or helmet, they look on them as no
more encumbrance than their own limbs, for they say that arms are the
limbs of a soldier, and those, indeed, they carry so commodiously that,
when there is occasion, they throw down their burdens, and use their
arms as readily as their limbs. Why need I mention the exercises of the
legions? And how great the labor is which is undergone in the running,
encounters, shouts! Hence it is that their minds are worked 79up to make
so light of wounds in action. Take a soldier of equal bravery, but
undisciplined, and he will seem a woman. Why is it that there is this
sensible difference between a raw recruit and a veteran soldier? The age
of the young soldiers is for the most part in their favor; but it is
practice only that enables men to bear labor and despise wounds.
Moreover, we often see, when the wounded are carried off the field, the
raw, untried soldier, though but slightly wounded, cries out most
shamefully; but the more brave, experienced veteran only inquires for
some one to dress his wounds, and says,
Patroclus, to thy aid I must appeal
Ere worse ensue, my bleeding wounds to heal;
The sons of Æsculapius are employ’d,
No room for me, so many are annoy’d.
XVII. This is certainly Eurypylus himself. What an experienced
man!—While his friend is continually enlarging on his misfortunes, you
may observe that he is so far from weeping that he even assigns a reason
why he should bear his wounds with patience.
Who at his enemy a stroke directs,
His sword to light upon himself expects.
Patroclus, I suppose, will lead him off to his chamber to bind up his
wounds, at least if he be a man: but not a word of that; he only
inquires how the battle went:
Say how the Argives bear themselves in fight?
And yet no words can show the truth as well as those, your deeds and
visible sufferings.
Peace! and my wounds bind up;
but though Eurypylus could bear these afflictions, Г†sopus could not,
Where Hector’s fortune press’d our yielding troops;
and he explains the rest, though in pain. So unbounded is military glory
in a brave man! Shall, then, a veteran soldier be able to behave in this
manner, and shall a wise and learned man not be able? Surely the latter
might be 80able to bear pain better, and in no small degree either. At
present, however, I am confining myself to what is engendered by
practice and discipline. I am not yet come to speak of reason and
philosophy. You may often hear of old women living without victuals for
three or four days; but take away a wrestler’s provisions but for one
day, and he will implore the aid of Jupiter Olympius, the very God for
whom he exercises himself: he will cry out that he cannot endure it.
Great is the force of custom! Sportsmen will continue whole nights in
the snow; they will bear being almost frozen upon the mountains. From
practice boxers will not so much as utter a groan, however bruised by
the cestus. But what do you think of those to whom a victory in the
Olympic games seemed almost on a par with the ancient consulships of the
Roman people? What wounds will the gladiators bear, who are either
barbarians, or the very dregs of mankind! How do they, who are trained
to it, prefer being wounded to basely avoiding it! How often do they
prove that they consider nothing but the giving satisfaction to their
masters or to the people! for when covered with wounds, they send to
their masters to learn their pleasure: if it is their will, they are
ready to lie down and die. What gladiator, of even moderate reputation,
ever gave a sigh? who ever turned pale? who ever disgraced himself
either in the actual combat, or even when about to die? who that had
been defeated ever drew in his neck to avoid the stroke of death? So
great is the force of practice, deliberation, and custom! Shall this,
then, be done by
A Samnite rascal, worthy of his trade;
and shall a man born to glory have so soft a part in his soul as not to
be able to fortify it by reason and reflection? The sight of the
gladiators’ combats is by some looked on as cruel and inhuman, and I do
not know, as it is at present managed, but it may be so; but when the
guilty fought, we might receive by our ears perhaps (but certainly by
our eyes we could not) better training to harden us against pain and
death.
XVIII. I have now said enough about the effects of exercise, custom, and
careful meditation. Proceed we now 81to consider the force of reason,
unless you have something to reply to what has been said.
A. That I should interrupt you! By no means; for your discourse has
brought me over to your opinion. Let the Stoics, then, think it their
business to determine whether pain be an evil or not, while they
endeavor to show by some strained and trifling conclusions, which are
nothing to the purpose, that pain is no evil. My opinion is, that
whatever it is, it is not so great as it appears; and I say, that men
are influenced to a great extent by some false representations and
appearance of it, and that all which is really felt is capable of being
endured. Where shall I begin, then? Shall I superficially go over what I
said before, that my discourse may have a greater scope?
This, then, is agreed upon by all, and not only by learned men, but also
by the unlearned, that it becomes the brave and magnanimous—those that
have patience and a spirit above this world—not to give way to pain.
Nor has there ever been any one who did not commend a man who bore it in
this manner. That, then, which is expected from a brave man, and is
commended when it is seen, it must surely be base in any one to be
afraid of at its approach, or not to bear when it comes. But I would
have you consider whether, as all the right affections of the soul are
classed under the name of virtues, the truth is that this is not
properly the name of them all, but that they all have their name from
that leading virtue which is superior to all the rest: for the name
“virtue” comes from vir, a man, and courage is the peculiar
distinction of a man: and this virtue has two principal duties, to
despise death and pain. We must, then, exert these, if we would be men
of virtue, or, rather, if we would be men, because virtue (virtus) takes
its very name from vir, man.
XIX. You may inquire, perhaps, how? And such an inquiry is not amiss,
for philosophy is ready with her assistance. Epicurus offers himself to
you, a man far from a bad—or, I should rather say, a very good man: he
advises no more than he knows. “Despise pain,” says he. Who is it saith
this? Is it the same man who calls pain the greatest of all evils? It is
not, indeed, very consistent in him. Let us hear what he says: “If the
pain is excessive, 82it must needs be short.” I must have that over
again, for I do not apprehend what you mean exactly by “excessive” or
“short.” That is excessive than which nothing can be greater; that is
short than which nothing is shorter. I do not regard the greatness of
any pain from which, by reason of the shortness of its continuance, I
shall be delivered almost before it reaches me. But if the pain be as
great as that of Philoctetes, it will appear great indeed to me, but yet
not the greatest that I am capable of bearing; for the pain is confined
to my foot. But my eye may pain me, I may have a pain in the head, or
sides, or lungs, or in every part of me. It is far, then, from being
excessive. Therefore, says he, pain of a long continuance has more
pleasure in it than uneasiness. Now, I cannot bring myself to say so
great a man talks nonsense; but I imagine he is laughing at us. My
opinion is that the greatest pain (I say the greatest, though it may be
ten atoms less than another) is not therefore short, because acute. I
could name to you a great many good men who have been tormented many
years with the acutest pains of the gout. But this cautious man doth not
determine the measure of that greatness or of duration, so as to enable
us to know what he calls excessive with regard to pain, or short with
respect to its continuance. Let us pass him by, then, as one who says
just nothing at all; and let us force him to acknowledge,
notwithstanding he might behave himself somewhat boldly under his colic
and his strangury, that no remedy against pain can be had from him who
looks on pain as the greatest of all evils. We must apply, then, for
relief elsewhere, and nowhere better (if we seek for what is most
consistent with itself) than to those who place the chief good in
honesty, and the greatest evil in infamy. You dare not so much as groan,
or discover the least uneasiness in their company, for virtue itself
speaks to you through them.
XX. Will you, when you may observe children at Lacedæmon, and young men
at Olympia, and barbarians in the amphitheatre, receive the severest
wounds, and bear them without once opening their mouths—will you, I
say, if any pain should by chance attack you, cry out like a woman? Will
you not rather bear it with resolution and constancy? 83and not cry, It
is intolerable; nature cannot bear it! I hear what you say: Boys bear
this because they are led thereto by glory; some bear it through shame,
many through fear, and yet are we afraid that nature cannot bear what is
borne by many, and in such different circumstances? Nature not only
bears it, but challenges it, for there is nothing with her preferable,
nothing which she desires more than credit, and reputation, and praise,
and honor, and glory. I choose here to describe this one thing under
many names, and I have used many that you may have the clearer idea of
it; for what I mean to say is, that whatever is desirable of itself,
proceeding from virtue, or placed in virtue, and commendable on its own
account (which I would rather agree to call the only good than deny it
to be the chief good) is what men should prefer above all things. And as
we declare this to be the case with respect to honesty, so we speak in
the contrary manner of infamy; nothing is so odious, so detestable,
nothing so unworthy of a man. And if you are thoroughly convinced of
this (for, at the beginning of this discourse, you allowed that there
appeared to you more evil in infamy than in pain), it follows that you
ought to have the command over yourself, though I scarcely know how this
expression may seem an accurate one, which appears to represent man as
made up of two natures, so that one should be in command and the other
be subject to it.
XXI. Yet this division does not proceed from ignorance; for the soul
admits of a twofold division, one of which partakes of reason, the other
is without it. When, therefore, we are ordered to give a law to
ourselves, the meaning is, that reason should restrain our rashness.
There is in the soul of every man something naturally soft, low,
enervated in a manner, and languid. Were there nothing besides this, men
would be the greatest of monsters; but there is present to every man
reason, which presides over and gives laws to all; which, by improving
itself, and making continual advances, becomes perfect virtue. It
behooves a man, then, to take care that reason shall have the command
over that part which is bound to practise obedience. In what manner? you
will say. Why, as a master has over his slave, a general over his 84army,
a father over his son. If that part of the soul which I have called soft
behaves disgracefully, if it gives itself up to lamentations and
womanish tears, then let it be restrained, and committed to the care of
friends and relations, for we often see those persons brought to order
by shame whom no reasons can influence. Therefore, we should confine
those feelings, like our servants, in safe custody, and almost with
chains. But those who have more resolution, and yet are not utterly
immovable, we should encourage with our exhortations, as we would good
soldiers, to recollect themselves, and maintain their honor. That wisest
man of all Greece, in the Niptræ, does not lament too much over his
wounds, or, rather, he is moderate in his grief:
Move slow, my friends; your hasty speed refrain,
Lest by your motion you increase my pain.
Pacuvius is better in this than Sophocles, for in the one Ulysses
bemoans his wounds too vehemently; for the very people who carried him
after he was wounded, though his grief was moderate, yet, considering
the dignity of the man, did not scruple to say,
And thou, Ulysses, long to war inured,
Thy wounds, though great, too feebly hast endured.
The wise poet understood that custom was no contemptible instructor how
to bear pain. But the same hero complains with more decency, though in
great pain:
Assist, support me, never leave me so;
Unbind my wounds, oh! execrable woe!
He begins to give way, but instantly checks himself:
Away! begone! but cover first the sore;
For your rude hands but make my pains the more.
Do you observe how he constrains himself? not that his bodily pains were
less, but because he checks the anguish of his mind. Therefore, in the
conclusion of the Niptræ, he blames others, even when he himself is
dying:
Complaints of fortune may become the man,
None but a woman will thus weeping stand.
85And so that soft place in his soul obeys his reason, just as an abashed
soldier does his stern commander.
XXII. The man, then, in whom absolute wisdom exists (such a man, indeed,
we have never as yet seen, but the philosophers have described in their
writings what sort of man he will be, if he should exist); such a man,
or at least that perfect and absolute reason which exists in him, will
have the same authority over the inferior part as a good parent has over
his dutiful children: he will bring it to obey his nod without any
trouble or difficulty. He will rouse himself, prepare and arm himself,
to oppose pain as he would an enemy. If you inquire what arms he will
provide himself with, they will be contention, encouragement, discourse
with himself. He will say thus to himself: Take care that you are guilty
of nothing base, languid, or unmanly. He will turn over in his mind all
the different kinds of honor. Zeno of Elea will occur to him, who
suffered everything rather than betray his confederates in the design of
putting an end to the tyranny. He will reflect on Anaxarchus, the pupil
of Democritus, who, having fallen into the hands of Nicocreon, King of
Cyprus, without the least entreaty for mercy or refusal, submitted to
every kind of torture. Calanus the Indian will occur to him, an ignorant
man and a barbarian, born at the foot of Mount Caucasus, who committed
himself to the flames by his own free, voluntary act. But we, if we have
the toothache, or a pain in the foot, or if the body be anyways
affected, cannot bear it. For our sentiments of pain as well as pleasure
are so trifling and effeminate, we are so enervated and relaxed by
luxuries, that we cannot bear the sting of a bee without crying out. But
Caius Marius, a plain countryman, but of a manly soul, when he had an
operation performed on him, as I mentioned above, at first refused to be
tied down; and he is the first instance of any one’s having had an
operation performed on him without being tied down. Why, then, did
others bear it afterward? Why, from the force of example. You see, then,
that pain exists more in opinion than in nature; and yet the same Marius
gave a proof that there is something very sharp in pain for he would not
submit to have the other thigh cut. So that he bore his pain with
resolution as a man; but, 86like a reasonable person, he was not willing
to undergo any greater pain without some necessary reason. The whole,
then, consists in this—that you should have command over yourself. I
have already told you what kind of command this is; and by considering
what is most consistent with patience, fortitude, and greatness of soul,
a man not only restrains himself, but, somehow or other, mitigates even
pain itself.
XXIII. Even as in a battle the dastardly and timorous soldier throws
away his shield on the first appearance of an enemy, and runs as fast as
he can, and on that account loses his life sometimes, though he has
never received even one wound, when he who stands his ground has nothing
of the sort happen to him, so they who cannot bear the appearance of
pain throw themselves away, and give themselves up to affliction and
dismay. But they that oppose it, often come off more than a match for
it. For the body has a certain resemblance to the soul: as burdens are
more easily borne the more the body is exerted, while they crush us if
we give way, so the soul by exerting itself resists the whole weight
that would oppress it; but if it yields, it is so pressed that it cannot
support itself. And if we consider things truly, the soul should exert
itself in every pursuit, for that is the only security for its doing its
duty. But this should be principally regarded in pain, that we must not
do anything timidly, or dastardly, or basely, or slavishly, or
effeminately, and, above all things, we must dismiss and avoid that
Philoctetean sort of outcry. A man is allowed sometimes to groan, but
yet seldom; but it is not permissible even in a woman to howl; for such
a noise as this is forbidden, by the twelve tables, to be used even at
funerals. Nor does a wise or brave man ever groan, unless when he exerts
himself to give his resolution greater force, as they who run in the
stadium make as much noise as they can. The wrestlers, too, do the same
when they are training; and the boxers, when they aim a blow with the
cestus at their adversary, give a groan, not because they are in pain,
or from a sinking of their spirits, but because their whole body is put
upon the stretch by the throwing-out of these groans, and the blow comes
the stronger.
87XXIV. What! they who would speak louder than ordinary are they
satisfied with working their jaws, sides, or tongue or stretching the
common organs of speech and utterance? The whole body and every muscle
is at full stretch if I may be allowed the expression; every nerve is
exerted to assist their voice. I have actually seen the knees of Marcus
Antonius touch the ground when he was speaking with vehemence for
himself, with relation to the Varian law. For, as the engines you throw
stones or darts with throw them out with the greater force the more they
are strained and drawn back; so it is in speaking, running, or
boxing—the more people strain themselves, the greater their force.
Since, therefore, this exertion has so much influence—if in a moment of
pain groans help to strengthen the mind, let us use them; but if they be
groans of lamentation, if they be the expression of weakness or
abjectness, or unmanly weeping, then I should scarcely call him a man
who yielded to them. For even supposing that such groaning could give
any ease, it still should be considered whether it were consistent with
a brave and resolute man. But if it does not ease our pain, why should
we debase ourselves to no purpose? For what is more unbecoming in a man
than to cry like a woman? But this precept which is laid down with
respect to pain is not confined to it. We should apply this exertion of
the soul to everything else. Is anger inflamed? is lust excited? we must
have recourse to the same citadel, and apply to the same arms. But since
it is pain which we are at present discussing, we will let the other
subjects alone. To bear pain, then, sedately and calmly, it is of great
use to consider with all our soul, as the saying is, how noble it is to
do so, for we are naturally desirous (as I said before, but it cannot be
too often repeated) and very much inclined to what is honorable, of
which, if we discover but the least glimpse, there is nothing which we
are not prepared to undergo and suffer to attain it. From this impulse
of our minds, this desire for genuine glory and honorable conduct, it is
that such dangers are supported in war, and that brave men are not
sensible of their wounds in action, or, if they are sensible of them,
prefer death to the departing but the least step 88from their honor. The
Decii saw the shining swords of their enemies when they were rushing
into the battle. But the honorable character and the glory of the death
which they were seeking made all fear of death of little weight. Do you
imagine that Epaminondas groaned when he perceived that his life was
flowing out with his blood? No; for he left his country triumphing over
the Lacedæmonians, whereas he had found it in subjection to them. These
are the comforts, these are the things that assuage the greatest pain.
XXV. You may ask, How the case is in peace? What is to be done at home?
How we are to behave in bed? You bring me back to the philosophers, who
seldom go to war. Among these, Dionysius of Heraclea, a man certainly of
no resolution, having learned fortitude of Zeno, quitted it on being in
pain; for, being tormented with a pain in his kidneys, in bewailing
himself he cried out that those things were false which he had formerly
conceived of pain. And when his fellow-disciple, Cleanthes, asked him
why he had changed his opinion, he answered, “That the case of any man
who had applied so much time to philosophy, and yet was unable to bear
pain, might be a sufficient proof that pain is an evil; that he himself
had spent many years at philosophy, and yet could not bear pain: it
followed, therefore, that pain was an evil.” It is reported that
Cleanthes on that struck his foot on the ground, and repeated a verse
out of the Epigonæ:
Amphiaraus, hear’st thou this below?
He meant Zeno: he was sorry the other had degenerated from him.
But it was not so with our friend Posidonius, whom I have often seen
myself; and I will tell you what Pompey used to say of him: that when he
came to Rhodes, after his departure from Syria, he had a great desire to
hear Posidonius, but was informed that he was very ill of a severe fit
of the gout; yet he had great inclination to pay a visit to so famous a
philosopher. Accordingly, when he had seen him, and paid his
compliments, and had spoken with great respect of him, he said he was
very sorry that he could not hear him lecture. “But indeed you may,”
89replied the other, “nor will I suffer any bodily pain to occasion so
great a man to visit me in vain.” On this Pompey relates that, as he lay
on his bed, he disputed with great dignity and fluency on this very
subject: that nothing was good but what was honest; and that in his
paroxysms he would often say, “Pain, it is to no purpose;
notwithstanding you are troublesome, I will never acknowledge you an
evil.” And in general all celebrated and notorious afflictions become
endurable by disregarding them.
XXVI. Do we not observe that where those exercises called gymnastic are
in esteem, those who enter the lists never concern themselves about
dangers? that where the praise of riding and hunting is highly esteemed,
they who practice these arts decline no pain? What shall I say of our
own ambitious pursuits or desire of honors? What fire have not
candidates run through to gain a single vote? Therefore Africanus had
always in his hands Xenophon, the pupil of Socrates, being particularly
pleased with his saying, that the same labors were not equally heavy to
the general and to the common man, because the honor itself made the
labor lighter to the general. But yet, so it happens, that even with the
illiterate vulgar an idea of honor is of great influence, though they
cannot understand what it is. They are led by report and common opinion
to look on that as honorable which has the general voice. Not that I
would have you, should the multitude be ever so fond of you, rely on
their judgment, nor approve of everything which they think right: you
must use your own judgment. If you are satisfied with yourself when you
have approved of what is right, you will not only have the mastery over
yourself (which I recommended to you just now), but over everybody, and
everything. Lay this down, then, as a rule, that a great capacity, and
lofty elevation of soul, which distinguishes itself most by despising
and looking down with contempt on pain, is the most excellent of all
things, and the more so if it does not depend on the people and does not
aim at applause, but derives its satisfaction from itself. Besides, to
me, indeed, everything seems the more commendable the less the people
are courted, and the fewer eyes there 90are to see it. Not that you
should avoid the public, for every generous action loves the public
view; yet no theatre for virtue is equal to a consciousness of it.
XXVII. And let this be principally considered: that this bearing of
pain, which I have often said is to be strengthened by an exertion of
the soul, should be the same in everything. For you meet with many who,
through a desire of victory, or for glory, or to maintain their rights,
or their liberty, have boldly received wounds, and borne themselves up
under them; and yet those very same persons, by relaxing that
intenseness of their minds, were unequal to bearing the pain of a
disease; for they did not support themselves under their former
sufferings by reason or philosophy, but by inclination and glory.
Therefore some barbarians and savage people are able to fight very
stoutly with the sword, but cannot bear sickness like men; but the
Grecians, men of no great courage, but as wise as human nature will
admit of, cannot look an enemy in the face, yet the same will bear to be
visited with sickness tolerably, and with a sufficiently manly spirit;
and the Cimbrians and Celtiberians are very alert in battle, but bemoan
themselves in sickness. For nothing can be consistent which has not
reason for its foundation. But when you see those who are led by
inclination or opinion, not retarded by pain in their pursuits, nor
hindered by it from succeeding in them, you may conclude, either that
pain is no evil, or that, notwithstanding you may choose to call an evil
whatever is disagreeable and contrary to nature, yet it is so very
trifling an evil that it may so effectually be got the better of by
virtue as quite to disappear. And I would have you think of this night
and day; for this argument will spread itself, and take up more room
some time or other, and not be confined to pain alone; for if the
motives to all our actions are to avoid disgrace and acquire honor, we
may not only despise the stings of pain, but the storms of fortune,
especially if we have recourse to that retreat which was pointed out in
our yesterday’s discussion; for, as if some God had advised a man who
was pursued by pirates to throw himself overboard, saying, “There is
something at hand to receive you; either a dolphin will take you up, as
it did Arion of 91Methymna; or those horses sent by Neptune to Pelops
(who are said to have carried chariots so rapidly as to be borne up by
the waves) will receive you, and convey you wherever you please. Cast
away all fear.” So, though your pains be ever so sharp and disagreeable,
if the case is not such that it is worth your while to endure them, you
see whither you may betake yourself. I think this will do for the
present. But perhaps you still abide by your opinion.
A. Not in the least, indeed; and I hope I am freed by these two days’
discourses from the fear of two things that I greatly dreaded.
M. To-morrow, then, for rhetoric, as we were saying. But I see we must
not drop our philosophy.
A. No, indeed; we will have the one in the forenoon, and this at the
usual time.
M. It shall be so, and I will comply with your very laudable
inclinations.
BOOK III.
ON GRIEF OF MIND.
I.
What reason shall I assign, O Brutus, why, as we consist of mind and
body, the art of curing and preserving the body should be so much sought
after, and the invention of it, as being so useful, should be ascribed
to the immortal Gods; but the medicine of the mind should not have been
so much the object of inquiry while it was unknown, nor so much attended
to and cultivated after its discovery, nor so well received or approved
of by some, and accounted actually disagreeable, and looked upon with an
envious eye by many? Is it because we, by means of the mind, judge of
the pains and disorders of the body, but do not, by means of the body,
arrive at any perception of the disorders of the mind? Hence it comes
that the mind only judges of itself when that very faculty by which it
is judged is in a bad state. Had nature given us faculties for
discerning and viewing herself, and could we go through life by keeping
our eye on her—our best guide—
92there would be no reason certainly why
any one should be in want of philosophy or learning; but, as it is, she
has furnished us only with some feeble rays of light, which we
immediately extinguish so completely by evil habits and erroneous
opinions that the light of nature is nowhere visible. The seeds of
virtues are natural to our constitutions, and, were they suffered to
come to maturity, would naturally conduct us to a happy life; but now,
as soon as we are born and received into the world, we are instantly
familiarized with all kinds of depravity and perversity of opinions; so
that we may be said almost to suck in error with our nurse’s milk. When
we return to our parents, and are put into the hands of tutors and
governors, we are imbued with so many errors that truth gives place to
falsehood, and nature herself to established opinion.
II. To these we may add the poets; who, on account of the appearance
they exhibit of learning and wisdom, are heard, read, and got by heart,
and make a deep impression on our minds. But when to these are added the
people, who are, as it were, one great body of instructors, and the
multitude, who declare unanimously for what is wrong, then are we
altogether overwhelmed with bad opinions, and revolt entirely from
nature; so that they seem to deprive us of our best guide who have
decided that there is nothing better for man, nothing more worthy of
being desired by him, nothing more excellent, than honors and commands,
and a high reputation with the people; which indeed every excellent man
aims at; but while he pursues that only true honor which nature has in
view above all other objects, he finds himself busied in arrant trifles,
and in pursuit of no conspicuous form of virtue, but only some shadowy
representation of glory. For glory is a real and express substance, not
a mere shadow. It consists in the united praise of good men, the free
voice of those who form a true judgment of pre-eminent virtue; it is, as
it were, the very echo of virtue; and being generally the attendant on
laudable actions, should not be slighted by good men. But popular fame,
which would pretend to imitate it, is hasty and inconsiderate, and
generally commends wicked and immoral actions, and throws discredit upon
the appearance and beauty of honesty by assuming
93a resemblance of it.
And it is owing to their not being able to discover the difference
between them that some men ignorant of real excellence, and in what it
consists, have been the destruction of their country and of themselves.
And thus the best men have erred, not so much in their intentions as by
a mistaken conduct. What? is no cure to be attempted to be applied to
those who are carried away by the love of money, or the lust of
pleasures, by which they are rendered little short of madmen, which is
the case of all weak people? or is it because the disorders of the mind
are less dangerous than those of the body? or because the body will
admit of a cure, while there is no medicine whatever for the mind?
III. But there are more disorders of the mind than of the body, and they
are of a more dangerous nature; for these very disorders are the more
offensive because they belong to the mind and disturb it; and the mind,
when disordered, is, as Ennius says, in a constant error: it can neither
bear nor endure anything, and is under the perpetual influence of
desires. Now, what disorders can be worse to the body than these two
distempers of the mind (for I overlook others), weakness and desire? But
how, indeed, can it be maintained that the mind cannot prescribe for
itself, when she it is who has invented the medicines for the body,
when, with regard to bodily cures, constitution and nature have a great
share, nor do all who suffer themselves to be cured find that effect
instantly; but those minds which are disposed to be cured, and submit to
the precepts of the wise, may undoubtedly recover a healthy state?
Philosophy is certainly the medicine of the soul, whose assistance we do
not seek from abroad, as in bodily disorders, but we ourselves are bound
to exert our utmost energy and power in order to effect our cure. But as
to philosophy in general, I have, I think, in my Hortensius,
sufficiently spoken of the credit and attention which it deserves: since
that, indeed, I have been continually either disputing or writing on its
most material branches; and I have laid down in these books all the
discussions which took place between myself and my particular friends at
my Tusculan villa. But as I have spoken in the two former of pain and
death, this book shall be
94devoted to the account of the third day of
our disputations.
We came down into the Academy when the day was already declining towards
afternoon, and I asked one of those who were present to propose a
subject for us to discourse on; and then the business was carried on in
this manner:
IV.
A. My opinion is, that a wise man is subject to grief.
M. What, and to the other perturbations of mind, as fears, lusts,
anger? For these are pretty much like what the Greeks call
ПЂбЅ±ОёО·. I might
call them diseases, and that would be a literal translation, but it is
not agreeable to our way of speaking. For envy, delight, and pleasure
are all called by the Greeks diseases, being affections of the mind not
in subordination to reason; but we, I think, are right in calling the
same motions of a disturbed soul perturbations, and in very seldom using
the term diseases; though, perhaps, it appears otherwise to you.
A. I am of your opinion.
M. And do you think a wise man subject to these?
A. Entirely, I think.
M. Then that boasted wisdom is but of small account, if it differs so
little from madness?
A. What? does every commotion of the mind seem to you to be madness?
M. Not to me only; but I apprehend, though I have often been surprised
at it, that it appeared so to our ancestors many ages before Socrates;
from whom is derived all that philosophy which relates to life and
morals.
A. How so?
M. Because the name madness
35 implies a sickness of the mind and
disease; that is to say, an unsoundness and an unhealthiness of mind,
which they call madness. But the philosophers call all perturbations of
the soul diseases, and their opinion is that no fool is ever free from
these; but all that are diseased are unsound; and the minds of all fools
are diseased; therefore all fools are mad. For they held that soundness
of the mind depends on a certain
95tranquillity and steadiness; and a
mind which was destitute of these qualities they called insane, because
soundness was inconsistent with a perturbed mind just as much as with a
disordered body.
V. Nor were they less ingenious in calling the state of the soul devoid
of the light of the mind, “a being out of one’s mind,” “a being beside
one’s self.” From whence we may understand that they who gave these
names to things were of the same opinion with Socrates, that all silly
people were unsound, which the Stoics have carefully preserved as being
derived from him; for whatever mind is distempered (and, as I just now
said, the philosophers call all perturbed motions of the mind
distempers) is no more sound than a body is when in a fit of sickness.
Hence it is that wisdom is the soundness of the mind, folly a sort of
unsoundness, which is insanity, or a being out of one’s mind: and these
are much better expressed by the Latin words than the Greek, which you
will find the case also in many other topics. But we will discuss that
point elsewhere: let us now attend to our present subject. The very
meaning of the word describes the whole thing about which we are
inquiring, both as to its substance and character. For we must
necessarily understand by “sound” those whose minds are under no
perturbation from any motion as if it were a disease. They who are
differently affected we must necessarily call “unsound.” So that nothing
is better than what is usual in Latin, to say that they who are run away
with by their lust or anger have quitted the command over themselves;
though anger includes lust, for anger is defined to be the lust of
revenge. They, then, who are said not to be masters of themselves, are
said to be so because they are not under the government of reason, to
which is assigned by nature the power over the whole soul. Why the
Greeks should call this mania, I do not easily apprehend; but we define
it much better than they, for we distinguish this madness (
insania),
which, being allied to folly, is more extensive, from what we call
furor, or raving. The Greeks, indeed, would do so too, but they have
no one word that will express it: what we call
furor, they call
ОјОµО»О±ОіП‡ОїО»бЅ·О±, as if the reason
96were affected only by a black bile, and
not disturbed as often by a violent rage, or fear, or grief. Thus we say
Athamas, Alcmæon, Ajax, and Orestes were raving (
furere); because a
person affected in this manner was not allowed by the Twelve Tables to
have the management of his own affairs; therefore the words are not, if
he is mad (
insanus), but if he begins to be raving (
furiosus). For
they looked upon madness to be an unsettled humor that proceeded from
not being of sound mind; yet such a person might perform his ordinary
duties, and discharge the usual and customary requirements of life: but
they considered one that was raving as afflicted with a total blindness
of the mind, which, notwithstanding it is allowed to be greater than
madness, is nevertheless of such a nature that a wise man may be subject
to raving (
furor), but cannot possibly be afflicted by insanity
(
insania). But this is another question: let us now return to our
original subject.
VI. I think you said that it was your opinion that a wise man was liable
to grief.
A. And so, indeed, I think.
M. It is natural enough to think so, for we are not the offspring of
flints; but we have by nature something soft and tender in our souls,
which may be put into a violent motion by grief, as by a storm; nor did
that Crantor, who was one of the most distinguished men that our Academy
has ever produced, say this amiss: “I am by no means of their opinion
who talk so much in praise of I know not what insensibility, which
neither can exist, nor ought to exist”. “I would choose,” says he, “never
to be ill; but should I be so, still I should choose to retain my
sensation, whether there was to be an amputation or any other separation
of anything from my body. For that insensibility cannot be but at the
expense of some unnatural ferocity of mind, or stupor of body.”But let
us consider whether to talk in this manner be not allowing that we are
weak, and yielding to our softness. Notwithstanding, let us be hardy
enough, not only to lop off every arm of our miseries, but even to pluck
up every fibre of their roots. Yet still something, perhaps, may be left
behind, so deep does folly strike its roots: but whatever may be
97left
it will be no more than is necessary. But let us be persuaded of this,
that unless the mind be in a sound state, which philosophy alone can
effect, there can be no end of our miseries. Wherefore, as we began, let
us submit ourselves to it for a cure; we shall be cured if we choose to
be. I shall advance something further. I shall not treat of grief alone,
though that indeed is the principal thing; but, as I originally
proposed, of every perturbation of the mind, as I termed it; disorder,
as the Greeks call it: and first, with your leave, I shall treat it in
the manner of the Stoics, whose method is to reduce their arguments into
a very small space; afterward I shall enlarge more in my own way.
VII. A man of courage is also full of faith. I do not use the word
confident, because, owing to an erroneous custom of speaking, that word
has come to be used in a bad sense, though it is derived from confiding,
which is commendable. But he who is full of faith is certainly under no
fear; for there is an inconsistency between faith and fear. Now, whoever
is subject to grief is subject to fear; for whatever things we grieve at
when present we dread when hanging over us and approaching. Thus it
comes about that grief is inconsistent with courage: it is very
probable, therefore, that whoever is subject to grief is also liable to
fear, and to a broken kind of spirits and sinking. Now, whenever these
befall a man, he is in a servile state, and must own that he is
overpowered; for whoever admits these feelings, must admit timidity and
cowardice. But these cannot enter into the mind of a man of courage;
neither, therefore, can grief: but the man of courage is the only wise
man; therefore grief cannot befall the wise man. It is, besides,
necessary that whoever is brave should be a man of great soul; that
whoever is a man of a great soul should be invincible; whoever is
invincible looks down with contempt on all things here, and considers
them, beneath him. But no one can despise those things on account of
which he may be affected with grief; from whence it follows that a wise
man is never affected with grief: for all wise men are brave; therefore
a wise man is not subject to grief. And as the eye, when disordered, is
not in a good condition for performing its
98office properly; and as the
other parts, and the whole body itself, when unsettled, cannot perform
their office and business; so the mind, when disordered, is but
ill-fitted to perform its duty. The office of the mind is to use its
reason well; but the mind of a wise man is always in condition to make
the best use of his reason, and therefore is never out of order. But
grief is a disorder of the mind; therefore a wise man will be always
free from it.
VIII. And from these considerations we may get at a very probable
definition of the temperate man, whom the Greeks call
ПѓбЅЅП†ПЃП‰ОЅ: and they
call that virtue
ПѓП‰П†ПЃОїПѓбЅ»ОЅО·ОЅ, which I at one time call temperance, at
another time moderation, and sometimes even modesty; but I do not know
whether that virtue may not be properly called frugality, which has a
more confined meaning with the Greeks; for they call frugal men
П‡ПЃО·ПѓбЅ·ОјОїП…П‚, which implies only that they are useful; but our name has a
more extensive meaning: for all abstinence, all innocency (which the
Greeks have no ordinary name for, though they might use the word
бјЂОІО»бЅ±ОІОµО№О±, for innocency is that disposition of mind which would offend
no one) and several other virtues are comprehended under frugality; but
if this quality were of less importance, and confined in as small a
compass as some imagine, the surname of Piso
36 would not have been in
so great esteem. But as we allow him not the name of a frugal man
(
frugi), who either quits his post through fear, which is cowardice;
or who reserves to his own use what was privately committed to his
keeping, which is injustice; or who fails in his military undertakings
through rashness, which is folly—for that reason the word frugality
takes in these three virtues of fortitude, justice, and prudence, though
it is indeed common to all virtues, for they are all connected and knit
together. Let us allow, then, frugality itself to be another and fourth
virtue; for its peculiar property seems to be, to govern and appease all
tendencies to too eager a desire after anything, to restrain lust, and
to preserve a decent steadiness in everything. The vice in contrast to
this is called prodigality (
nequitia). Frugality, I imagine, is
derived from the
99word
fruge, the best thing which the earth produces;
nequitia is derived (though this is perhaps rather more strained;
still, let us try it; we shall only be thought to have been trifling if
there is nothing in what we say) from the fact of everything being to no
purpose (
nequicquam) in such a man; from which circumstance he is
called also
Nihil, nothing. Whoever is frugal, then, or, if it is more
agreeable to you, whoever is moderate and temperate, such a one must of
course be consistent; whoever is consistent, must be quiet; the quiet
man must be free from all perturbation, therefore from grief likewise:
and these are the properties of a wise man; therefore a wise man must be
free from grief.
IX. So that Dionysius of Heraclea is right when, upon this complaint of
Achilles in Homer,
Well hast thou spoke, but at the tyrant’s name
My rage rekindles, and my soul’s in flame:
’Tis just resentment, and becomes the brave,
Disgraced, dishonor’d like the vilest slave
37—
he reasons thus: Is the hand as it should be, when it is affected with a
swelling? or is it possible for any other member of the body, when
swollen or enlarged, to be in any other than a disordered state? Must
not the mind, then, when it is puffed up, or distended, be out of order?
But the mind of a wise man is always free from every kind of disorder:
it never swells, never is puffed up; but the mind when in anger is in a
different state. A wise man, therefore, is never angry; for when he is
angry, he lusts after something; for whoever is angry naturally has a
longing desire to give all the pain he can to the person who he thinks
has injured him; and whoever has this earnest desire must necessarily be
much pleased with the accomplishment of his wishes; hence he is
delighted with his neighbor’s misery; and as a wise man is not capable
of such feelings as these, he is therefore not capable of anger. But
should a wise man be subject to grief, he may likewise 100be subject to
anger; for as he is free from anger, he must likewise be free from
grief. Again, could a wise man be subject to grief, he might also be
liable to pity, or even might be open to a disposition towards envy
(invidentia); I do not say to envy (invidia), for that can only
exist by the very act of envying: but we may fairly form the word
invidentia from invidendo, and so avoid the doubtful name invidia;
for this word is probably derived from in and video, looking too
closely into another’s fortune; as it is said in the Melanippus,
Who envies me the flower of my children?
where the Latin is invidit florem. It may appear not good Latin, but
it is very well put by Accius; for as video governs an accusative
case, so it is more correct to say invideo florem than flori. We are
debarred from saying so by common usage. The poet stood in his own
right, and expressed himself with more freedom.
X. Therefore compassion and envy are consistent in the same man; for
whoever is uneasy at any one’s adversity is also uneasy at another’s
prosperity: as Theophrastus, while he laments the death of his companion
Callisthenes, is at the same time disturbed at the success of Alexander;
and therefore he says that Callisthenes met with man of the greatest
power and good fortune, but one who did not know how to make use of his
good fortune. And as pity is an uneasiness which arises from the
misfortunes of another, so envy is an uneasiness that proceeds from the
good success of another: therefore whoever is capable of pity is capable
of envy. But a wise man is incapable of envy, and consequently incapable
of pity. But were a wise man used to grieve, to pity also would be
familiar to him; therefore to grieve is a feeling which cannot affect a
wise man. Now, though these reasonings of the Stoics, and their
conclusions, are rather strained and distorted, and ought to be
expressed in a less stringent and narrow manner, yet great stress is to
be laid on the opinions of those men who have a peculiarly bold and
manly turn of thought and sentiment. For our friends the Peripatetics,
notwithstanding all their erudition, gravity, and fluency of language,
do not satisfy me about the moderation of these disorders and diseases
101of the soul which they insist upon; for every evil, though moderate, is
in its nature great. But our object is to make out that the wise man is
free from all evil; for as the body is unsound if it is ever so slightly
affected, so the mind under any moderate disorder loses its soundness;
therefore the Romans have, with their usual accuracy of expression,
called trouble, and anguish, and vexation, on account of the analogy
between a troubled mind and a diseased body, disorders. The Greeks call
all perturbation of mind by pretty nearly the same name; for they name
every turbid motion of the soul ПЂбЅ±ОёОїП‚, that is to say, a distemper. But
we have given them a more proper name; for a disorder of the mind is
very like a disease of the body. But lust does not resemble sickness;
neither does immoderate joy, which is an elated and exulting pleasure of
the mind. Fear, too, is not very like a distemper, though it is akin to
grief of mind, but properly, as is also the case with sickness of the
body, so too sickness of mind has no name separated from pain. And
therefore I must explain the origin of this pain, that is to say, the
cause that occasions this grief in the mind, as if it were a sickness of
the body. For as physicians think they have found out the cure when they
have discovered the cause of the distemper, so we shall discover the
method of curing melancholy when the cause of it is found out.
XI. The whole cause, then, is in opinion; and this observation applies
not to this grief alone, but to every other disorder of the mind, which
are of four sorts, but consisting of many parts. For as every disorder
or perturbation is a motion of the mind, either devoid of reason, or in
despite of reason, or in disobedience to reason, and as that motion is
excited by an opinion of either good or evil; these four perturbations
are divided equally into two parts: for two of them proceed from an
opinion of good, one of which is an exulting pleasure, that is to say, a
joy elated beyond measure, arising from an opinion of some present great
good; the other is a desire which may fairly be called even a lust, and
is an immoderate inclination after some conceived great good without any
obedience to reason. Therefore these two kinds, the exulting pleasure
and the lust, have their rise from an opinion of good, as 102the other
two, fear and grief, have from an opinion of evil. For fear is an
opinion of some great evil impending over us, and grief is an opinion of
some great evil present; and, indeed, it is a freshly conceived opinion
of an evil so great that to grieve at it seems right: it is of that kind
that he who is uneasy at it thinks he has good reason to be so. Now we
should exert, our utmost efforts to oppose these perturbations—which
are, as it were, so many furies let loose upon us and urged on by
folly—if we are desirous to pass this share of life that is allotted to
us with ease and satisfaction. But of the other feelings I shall speak
elsewhere: our business at present is to drive away grief if we can, for
that shall be the object of our present discussion, since you have said
that it was your opinion that a wise man might be subject to grief,
which I can by no means allow of; for it is a frightful, miserable, and
detestable thing, which we should fly from with our utmost efforts—with
all our sails and oars, as I may say.
XII. That descendant of Tantalus, how does he appear to you—he who
sprung from Pelops, who formerly stole Hippodamia from her
father-in-law, King Œnomaus, and married her by force?—he who was
descended from Jupiter himself, how broken-hearted and dispirited does
he not seem!
Stand off, my friends, nor come within my shade,
That no pollutions your sound hearts pervade,
So foul a stain my body doth partake.
Will you condemn yourself, Thyestes, and deprive yourself of life, on
account of the greatness of another’s crime? What do you think of that
son of Phœbus? Do you not look upon him as unworthy of his own father’s
light?
Hollow his eyes, his body worn away,
His furrow’d cheeks his frequent tears betray;
His beard neglected, and his hoary hairs
Rough and uncomb’d, bespeak his bitter cares.
O foolish Г†etes! these are evils which you yourself have been the cause
of, and are not occasioned by any accidents with which chance has
visited you; and you behaved as you did, even after you had been inured
to your distress, and after the first swelling of the mind had
subsided!—whereas grief consists (as I shall show) in the notion of
103some recent evil—but your grief, it is very plain, proceeded from the
loss of your kingdom, not of your daughter, for you hated her, and
perhaps with reason, but you could not calmly bear to part with your
kingdom. But surely it is an impudent grief which preys upon a man for
not being able to command those that are free. Dionysius, it is true,
the tyrant of Syracuse, when driven from his country, taught a school at
Corinth; so incapable was he of living without some authority. But what
could be more impudent than Tarquin, who made war upon those who could
not bear his tyranny; and, when he could not recover his kingdom by the
aid of the forces of the Veientians and the Latins, is said to have
betaken himself to Cuma, and to have died in that city of old age and
grief!
XIII. Do you, then, think that it can befall a wise man to be oppressed
with grief, that is to say, with misery? for, as all perturbation is
misery, grief is the rack itself. Lust is attended with heat, exulting
joy with levity, fear with meanness, but grief with something greater
than these; it consumes, torments, afflicts, and disgraces a man; it
tears him, preys upon his mind, and utterly destroys him: if we do not
so divest ourselves of it as to throw it completely off, we cannot be
free from misery. And it is clear that there must be grief where
anything has the appearance of a present sore and oppressing evil.
Epicurus is of opinion that grief arises naturally from the imagination
of any evil; so that whosoever is eye-witness of any great misfortune,
if he conceives that the like may possibly befall himself, becomes sad
instantly from such an idea. The Cyrenaics think that grief is not
engendered by every kind of evil, but only by unexpected, unforeseen
evil; and that circumstance is, indeed, of no small effect on the
heightening of grief; for whatsoever comes of a sudden appears more
formidable. Hence these lines are deservedly commended:
I knew my son, when first he drew his breath,
Destined by fate to an untimely death;
And when I sent him to defend the Greeks,
War was his business, not your sportive freaks.
XIV. Therefore, this ruminating beforehand upon future evils which you
see at a distance makes their approach
104more tolerable; and on this
account what Euripides makes Theseus say is much commended. You will
give me leave to translate them, as is usual with me:
I treasured up what some learn’d sage did tell,
And on my future misery did dwell;
I thought of bitter death, of being drove
Far from my home by exile, and I strove
With every evil to possess my mind,
That, when they came, I the less care might find.
38
But Euripides says that of himself, which Theseus said he had heard from
some learned man, for the poet had been a pupil of Anaxagoras, who, as
they relate, on hearing of the death of his son, said, “I knew that my
son was mortal;” which speech seems to intimate that such things afflict
those men who have not thought on them before. Therefore, there is no
doubt but that all those things which are considered evils are the
heavier from not being foreseen. Though, notwithstanding this is not the
only circumstance which occasions the greatest grief, still, as the
mind, by foreseeing and preparing for it, has great power to make all
grief the less, a man should at all times consider all the events that
may befall him in this life; and certainly the excellence and divine
nature of wisdom consists in taking a near view of, and gaining a
thorough acquaintance with, all human affairs, in not being surprised
when anything happens, and in thinking, before the event, that there is
nothing but what may come to pass.
Wherefore ev’ry man,
When his affairs go on most swimmingly,
E’en then it most behooves to arm himself
Against the coming storm: loss, danger, exile,
Returning ever, let him look to meet;
His son in fault, wife dead, or daughter sick;
All common accidents, and may have happen’d
That nothing shall seem new or strange. But if
Aught has fall’n out beyond his hopes, all that
Let him account clear gain.39
105XV. Therefore, as Terence has so well expressed what he borrowed from
philosophy, shall not we, from whose fountains he drew it, say the same
thing in a better manner, and abide by it with more steadiness? Hence
came that steady countenance, which, according to Xantippe, her husband
Socrates always had; so that she said that she never observed any
difference in his looks when he went out and when he came home. Yet the
look of that old Roman, M. Crassus, who, as Lucilius says, never smiled
but once in his lifetime, was not of this kind, but placid and serene,
for so we are told. He, indeed, might well have had the same look at all
times who never changed his mind, from which the countenance derives its
expression. So that I am ready to borrow of the Cyrenaics those arms
against the accidents and events of life by means of which, by long
premeditation, they break the force of all approaching evils; and at the
same time I think that those very evils themselves arise more from
opinion than nature, for if they were real, no forecast could make them
lighter. But I shall speak more particularly on these matters after I
have first considered Epicurus’s opinion, who thinks that all people
must necessarily be uneasy who believe themselves to be in any evils,
let them be either foreseen and expected, or habitual to them; for with
him evils are not the less by reason of their continuance, nor the
lighter for having been foreseen; and it is folly to ruminate on evils
to come, or such as, perhaps, never may come: every evil is disagreeable
enough when it does come; but he who is constantly considering that some
evil may befall him is loading himself with a perpetual evil; and even
should such evil never light on him, he voluntarily takes upon himself
unnecessary misery, so that he is under constant uneasiness, whether he
actually suffers any evil, or only thinks of it. But he makes the
alleviation of grief depend on two things—a ceasing to think on evil,
and a turning to the contemplation of pleasure. For he thinks that the
mind may possibly be under the power of reason, and follow her
directions: he forbids us, therefore, to mind trouble, and calls us off
from sorrowful reflections; he throws a mist over our eyes to hinder us
from the contemplation of misery. Having sounded a retreat
106from this
statement, he drives our thoughts on again, and encourages them to view
and engage the whole mind in the various pleasures with which he thinks
the life of a wise man abounds, either from reflecting on the past, or
from the hope of what is to come. I have said these things in my own
way; the Epicureans have theirs. However, let us examine what they say;
how they say it is of little consequence.
XVI. In the first place, they are wrong in forbidding men to premeditate
on futurity and blaming their wish to do so; for there is nothing that
breaks the edge of grief and lightens it more than considering, during
one’s whole life, that there is nothing which it is impossible should
happen, or than, considering what human nature is, on what conditions
life was given, and how we may comply with them. The effect of which is
that we are always grieving, but that we never do so; for whoever
reflects on the nature of things, the various turns of life, and the
weakness of human nature, grieves, indeed, at that reflection; but while
so grieving he is, above all other times, behaving as a wise man, for he
gains these two things by it: one, that while he is considering the
state of human nature he is performing the especial duties of
philosophy, and is provided with a triple medicine against adversity—in
the first place, because he has long reflected that such things might
befall him, and this reflection by itself contributes much towards
lessening and weakening all misfortunes; and, secondly, because he is
persuaded that we should bear all the accidents which can happen to man
with the feelings and spirit of a man; and, lastly, because he considers
that what is blamable is the only evil. But it is not your fault that
something has happened to you which it was impossible for man to avoid.
For that withdrawing of our thoughts which he recommends when he calls
us off from contemplating our misfortunes is an imaginary action; for it
is not in our power to dissemble or to forget those evils which lie
heavy on us; they tear, vex, and sting us—they burn us up, and leave no
breathing time. And do you order us to forget them (for such
forgetfulness is contrary to nature), and at the same time deprive us of
the only assistance which nature affords, the being accustomed to them?
107For that, though it is but a slow medicine (I mean that which is
brought by lapse of time), is still a very effectual one. You order me
to employ my thoughts on something good, and forget my misfortunes. You
would say something worthy a great philosopher if you thought those
things good which are best suited to the dignity of human nature.
XVII. Should Pythagoras, Socrates, or Plato say to me, Why are you
dejected or sad? Why do you faint, and yield to fortune, which, perhaps,
may have power to harass and disturb you, but should not quite unman
you? There is great power in the virtues; rouse them, if they chance to
droop. Take fortitude for your guide, which will give you such spirits
that you will despise everything that can befall man, and look on it as
a trifle. Add to this temperance, which is moderation, and which was
just now called frugality, which will not suffer you to do anything base
or bad—for what is worse or baser than an effeminate man? Not even
justice will suffer you to act in this manner, though she seems to have
the least weight in this affair; but still, notwithstanding, even she
will inform you that you are doubly unjust when you both require what
does not belong to you, inasmuch as though you who have been born mortal
demand to be placed in the condition of the immortals, and at the same
time you take it much to heart that you are to restore what was lent
you. What answer will you make to prudence, who informs you that she is
a virtue sufficient of herself both to teach you a good life and also to
secure you a happy one? And, indeed, if she were fettered by external
circumstances, and dependent on others, and if she did not originate in
herself and return to herself, and also embrace everything in herself,
so as to seek no adventitious aid from any quarter, I cannot imagine why
she should appear deserving of such lofty panegyrics, or of being sought
after with such excessive eagerness. Now, Epicurus, if you call me back
to such goods as these, I will obey you, and follow you, and use you as
my guide, and even forget, as you order me, all my misfortunes; and I
will do this the more readily from a persuasion that they are not to be
ranked among evils at all. But you are for bringing my thoughts over to
pleasure.
108What pleasures? Pleasures of the body, I imagine, or such as
are recollected or imagined on account of the body. Is this all? Do I
explain your opinion rightly? for your disciples are used to deny that
we understand at all what Epicurus means. This is what he says, and what
that subtle fellow, old Zeno, who is one of the sharpest of them, used,
when I was attending lectures at Athens, to enforce and talk so loudly
of; saying that he alone was happy who could enjoy present pleasure, and
who was at the same time persuaded that he should enjoy it without pain,
either during the whole or the greatest part of his life; or if, should
any pain interfere, if it was very sharp, then it must be short; should
it be of longer continuance, it would have more of what was sweet than
bitter in it; that whosoever reflected on these things would be happy,
especially if satisfied with the good things which he had already
enjoyed, and if he were without fear of death or of the Gods.
XVIII. You have here a representation of a happy life according to
Epicurus, in the words of Zeno, so that there is no room for
contradiction in any point. What, then? Can the proposing and thinking
of such a life make Thyestes’s grief the less, or Æetes’s, of whom I
spoke above, or Telamon’s, who was driven from his country to penury and
banishment? in wonder at whom men exclaimed thus:
Is this the man surpassing glory raised?
Is this that Telamon so highly praised
By wondering Greece, at whose sight, like the sun,
All others with diminish’d lustre shone?
Now, should any one, as the same author says, find his spirits sink with
the loss of his fortune, he must apply to those grave philosophers of
antiquity for relief, and not to these voluptuaries: for what great
abundance of good do they promise? Suppose that we allow that to be
without pain is the chief good? Yet that is not called pleasure. But it
is not necessary at present to go through the whole: the question is, to
what point are we to advance in order to abate our grief? Grant that to
be in pain is the greatest evil: whosoever, then, has proceeded so far
as not to be in pain, is he, therefore, in immediate possession of the
greatest good? Why, Epicurus, do we use any evasions,
109and not allow in
our own words the same feeling to be pleasure which you are used to
boast of with such assurance? Are these your words or not? This is what
you say in that book which contains all the doctrine of your school; for
I will perform on this occasion the office of a translator, lest any one
should imagine that I am inventing anything. Thus you speak: “Nor can I
form any notion of the chief good, abstracted from those pleasures which
are perceived by taste, or from what depends on hearing music, or
abstracted from ideas raised by external objects visible to the eye, or
by agreeable motions, or from those other pleasures which are perceived
by the whole man by means of any of his senses; nor can it possibly be
said that the pleasures of the mind are excited only by what is good,
for I have perceived men’s minds to be pleased with the hopes of
enjoying those things which I mentioned above, and with the idea that it
should enjoy them without any interruption from pain.” And these are his
exact words, so that any one may understand what were the pleasures with
which Epicurus was acquainted. Then he speaks thus, a little lower down:
“I have often inquired of those who have been called wise men what would
be the remaining good if they should exclude from consideration all
these pleasures, unless they meant to give us nothing but words. I could
never learn anything from them; and unless they choose that all virtue
and wisdom should vanish and come to nothing, they must say with me that
the only road to happiness lies through those pleasures which I
mentioned above.” What follows is much the same, and his whole book on
the chief good everywhere abounds with the same opinions. Will you,
then, invite Telamon to this kind of life to ease his grief? And should
you observe any one of your friends under affliction, would you rather
prescribe him a sturgeon than a treatise of Socrates? or advise him to
listen to the music of a water organ rather than to Plato? or lay before
him the beauty and variety of some garden, put a nosegay to his nose,
burn perfumes before him, and bid him crown himself with a garland of
roses and woodbines? Should you add one thing more, you would certainly
wipe out all his grief.
110XIX. Epicurus must admit these arguments, or he must take out of his
book what I just now said was a literal translation; or, rather, he must
destroy his whole book, for it is crammed full of pleasures. We must
inquire, then, how we can ease him of his grief who speaks in this
manner:
My present state proceeds from fortune’s stings;
By birth I boast of a descent from kings;
Hence may you see from what a noble height
I’m sunk by fortune to this abject plight.
What! to ease his grief, must we mix him a cup of sweet wine, or
something of that kind? Lo! the same poet presents us with another
sentiment somewhere else:
I, Hector, once so great, now claim your aid.
We should assist her, for she looks out for help:
Where shall I now apply, where seek support?
Where hence betake me, or to whom resort?”
No means remain of comfort or of joy,
In flames my palace, and in ruins Troy;
Each wall, so late superb, deformed nods,
And not an altar’s left t’ appease the Gods.
You know what should follow, and particularly this:
Of father, country, and of friends bereft,
Not one of all these sumptuous temples left;
Which, while the fortune of our house did stand,
With rich wrought ceilings spoke the artist’s hand.
O excellent poet! though despised by those who sing the verses of
Euphorion. He is sensible that all things which come on a sudden are
harder to be borne. Therefore, when he had set off the riches of Priam
to the best advantage, which had the appearance of a long continuance,
what does he add?
Lo! these all perish’d in one blazing pile;
The foe old Priam of his life beguiled,
And with his blood, thy altar, Jove, defiled.
Admirable poetry! There is something mournful in the subject, as well as
in the words and measure. We must drive away this grief of hers: how is
that to be done? Shall we lay her on a bed of down; introduce a singer;
111shall we burn cedar, or present here with some pleasant liquor, and
provide her something to eat? Are these the good things which remove the
most afflicting grief? For you but just now said you knew of no other
good. I should agree with Epicurus that we ought to be called off from
grief to contemplate good things, if we could only agree upon what was
good.
XX. It may be said, What! do you imagine Epicurus really meant this, and
that he maintained anything so sensual? Indeed I do not imagine so, for
I am sensible that he has uttered many excellent things and sentiments,
and delivered maxims of great weight. Therefore, as I said before, I am
speaking of his acuteness, not of his morals. Though he should hold
those pleasures in contempt which he just now commended, yet I must
remember wherein he places the chief good. For he was not contented with
barely saying this, but he has explained what he meant: he says that
taste, and embraces, and sports, and music, and those forms which affect
the eyes with pleasure, are the chief good. Have I invented this? have I
misrepresented him? I should be glad to be confuted; for what am I
endeavoring at but to clear up truth in every question? Well, but the
same man says that pleasure is at its height where pain ceases, and that
to be free from all pain is the very greatest pleasure. Here are three
very great mistakes in a very few words. One is, that he contradicts
himself; for, but just now, he could not imagine anything good unless
the senses were in a manner tickled with some pleasure; but now he says
that to be free from pain is the highest pleasure. Can any one
contradict himself more? The next mistake is, that where there is
naturally a threefold division—the first, to be pleased; next, to be in
pain; the last, to be affected neither by pleasure nor pain—he imagines
the first and the last to be the same, and makes no difference between
pleasure and a cessation of pain. The last mistake he falls into in
common with some others, which is this: that as virtue is the most
desirable thing, and as philosophy has been investigated with a view to
the attainment of it, he has separated the chief good from virtue. But
he commends virtue, and that frequently; and indeed C. Gracchus, when he
had made the 112largest distributions of the public money, and had
exhausted the treasury, nevertheless spoke much of defending the
treasury. What signifies what men say when we see what they do? That
Piso, who was surnamed Frugal, had always harangued against the law that
was proposed for distributing the corn; but when it had passed, though a
man of consular dignity, he came to receive the corn. Gracchus observed
Piso standing in the court, and asked him, in the hearing of the people,
how it was consistent for him to take corn by a law he had himself
opposed. “It was,” said he, “against your distributing my goods to every
man as you thought proper; but, as you do so, I claim my share.” Did not
this grave and wise man sufficiently show that the public revenue was
dissipated by the Sempronian law? Read Gracchus’s speeches, and you will
pronounce him the advocate of the treasury. Epicurus denies that any one
can live pleasantly who does not lead a life of virtue; he denies that
fortune has any power over a wise man; he prefers a spare diet to great
plenty, and maintains that a wise man is always happy. All these things
become a philosopher to say, but they are not consistent with pleasure.
But the reply is, that he doth not mean that pleasure: let him mean
any pleasure, it must be such a one as makes no part of virtue. But
suppose we are mistaken as to his pleasure; are we so, too, as to his
pain? I maintain, therefore, the impropriety of language which that man
uses, when talking of virtue, who would measure every great evil by
pain.
XXI. And indeed the Epicureans, those best of men—for there is no order
of men more innocent—complain that I take great pains to inveigh
against Epicurus. We are rivals, I suppose, for some honor or
distinction. I place the chief good in the mind, he in the body; I in
virtue, he in pleasure; and the Epicureans are up in arms, and implore
the assistance of their neighbors, and many are ready to fly to their
aid. But as for my part, I declare that I am very indifferent about the
matter, and that I consider the whole discussion which they are so
anxious about at an end. For what! is the contention about the Punic
war? on which very subject, though M. Cato and L. Lentulus were of
different opinions, still there was no 113difference between them. But
these men behave with too much heat, especially as the opinions which
they would uphold are no very spirited ones, and such as they dare not
plead for either in the senate or before the assembly of the people, or
before the army or the censors. But, however, I will argue with them
another time, and with such a disposition that no quarrel shall arise
between us; for I shall be ready to yield to their opinions when founded
on truth. Only I must give them this advice: That were it ever so true,
that a wise man regards nothing but the body, or, to express myself with
more decency, never does anything except what is expedient, and views
all things with exclusive reference to his own advantage, as such things
are not very commendable, they should confine them to their own breasts,
and leave off talking with that parade of them.
XXII. What remains is the opinion of the Cyrenaics, who think that men
grieve when anything happens unexpectedly. And that is indeed, as I said
before, a great aggravation of a misfortune; and I know that it appeared
so to Chrysippus—“Whatever falls out unexpected is so much the
heavier.” But the whole question does not turn on this; though the
sudden approach of an enemy sometimes occasions more confusion than it
would if you had expected him, and a sudden storm at sea throws the
sailors into a greater fright than one which they have foreseen; and it
is the same in many other cases. But when you carefully consider the
nature of what was expected, you will find nothing more than that all
things which come on a sudden appear greater; and this upon two
accounts: first of all, because you have not time to consider how great
the accident is; and, secondly, because you are probably persuaded that
you could have guarded against it had you foreseen if, and therefore the
misfortune, having been seemingly encountered by your own fault, makes
your grief the greater. That it is so, time evinces; which, as it
advances, brings with it so much mitigation that though the same
misfortunes continue, the grief not only becomes the less, but in some
cases is entirely removed. Many Carthaginians were slaves at Rome, and
many Macedonians, when Perseus their king was taken prisoner. I saw,
114too, when I was a young man, some Corinthians in the Peloponnesus. They
might all have lamented with Andromache,
All these I saw......;
but they had perhaps given over lamenting themselves, for by their
countenances, and speech, and other gestures you might have taken them
for Argives or Sicyonians. And I myself was more concerned at the ruined
walls of Corinth than the Corinthians themselves were, whose minds by
frequent reflection and time had become callous to such sights. I have
read a book of Clitomachus, which he sent to his fellow-citizens who
were prisoners, to comfort them after the destruction of Carthage. There
is in it a treatise written by Carneades, which, as Clitomachus says, he
had inserted into his book; the subject was, “That it appeared probable
that a wise man would grieve at the state of subjection of his country,”
and all the arguments which Carneades used against this proposition are
set down in the book. There the philosopher applies such a strong
medicine to a fresh grief as would be quite unnecessary in one of any
continuance; nor, if this very book had been sent to the captives some
years after, would it have found any wounds to cure, but only scars; for
grief, by a gentle progress and slow degrees, wears away imperceptibly.
Not that the circumstances which gave rise to it are altered, or can be,
but that custom teaches what reason should—that those things which
before seemed to be of some consequence are of no such great importance,
after all.
XXIII. It may be said, What occasion is there to apply to reason, or to
any sort of consolation such as we generally make use of, to mitigate
the grief of the afflicted? For we have this argument always at hand,
that nothing ought to appear unexpected. But how will any one be enabled
to bear his misfortunes the better by knowing that it is unavoidable
that such things should happen to man? Saying this subtracts nothing
from the sum of the grief: it only asserts that nothing has fallen out
but what might have been anticipated; and yet this manner of speaking
has some little consolation in it, though I apprehend not a great deal.
Therefore those unlooked-for things have not so much force as to give
rise to all our 115grief; the blow perhaps may fall the heavier, but
whatever happens does not appear the greater on that account. No, it is
the fact of its having happened lately, and not of its having befallen
us unexpectedly, that makes it seem the greater. There are two ways,
then, of discerning the truth, not only of things that seem evil, but of
those that have the appearance of good. For we either inquire into the
nature of the thing, of what description, and magnitude, and importance
it is—as sometimes with regard to poverty, the burden of which we may
lighten when by our disputations we show how few things nature requires,
and of what a trifling kind they are—or, without any subtle arguing, we
refer them to examples, as here we instance a Socrates, there a
Diogenes, and then again that line in Cæcilius,
Wisdom is oft conceal’d in mean attire.
For as poverty is of equal weight with all, what reason can be given why
what was borne by Fabricius should be spoken of by any one else as
unsupportable when it falls upon themselves? Of a piece with this is
that other way of comforting, which consists in pointing out that
nothing has happened but what is common to human nature; for this
argument doth not only inform us what human nature is, but implies that
all things are tolerable which others have borne and are bearing.
XXIV. Is poverty the subject? They tell you of many who have submitted
to it with patience. Is it the contempt of honors? They acquaint you
with some who never enjoyed any, and were the happier for it; and of
those who have preferred a private retired life to public employment,
mentioning their names with respect; they tell you of the verse40 of
that most powerful king who praises an old man, and pronounces him happy
because he was unknown to fame and seemed likely to arrive at the hour
of death in obscurity and without notice. Thus, too, they have examples
for those who are deprived of their children: they who are under any
great grief are comforted by instances of like affliction; and thus the
endurance 116of every misfortune is rendered more easy by the fact of
others having undergone the same, and the fate of others causes what has
happened to appear less important than it has been previously thought,
and reflection thus discovers to us how much opinion had imposed on us.
And this is what the Telamon declares, “I, when my son was born,” etc.;
and thus Theseus, “I on my future misery did dwell;” and Anaxagoras, “I
knew my son was mortal.” All these men, by frequently reflecting on
human affairs, had discovered that they were by no means to be estimated
by the opinion of the multitude; and, indeed, it seems to me to be
pretty much the same case with those who consider beforehand as with
those who derive their remedies from time, excepting that a kind of
reason cures the one, and the other remedy is provided by nature; by
which we discover (and this contains the whole marrow of the matter)
that what was imagined to be the greatest evil is by no means so great
as to defeat the happiness of life. And the effect of this is, that the
blow is greater by reason of its not having been foreseen, and not, as
they suppose, that when similar misfortunes befall two different people,
that man only is affected with grief whom this calamity has befallen
unexpectedly. So that some persons, under the oppression of grief, are
said to have borne it actually worse for hearing of this common
condition of man, that we are born under such conditions as render it
impossible for a man to be exempt from all evil.
XXV. For this reason Carneades, as I see our friend Antiochus writes,
used to blame Chrysippus for commending these verses of Euripides:
Man, doom’d to care, to pain, disease, and strife,
Walks his short journey thro’ the vale of life:
Watchful attends the cradle and the grave,
And passing generations longs to save:
Last, dies himself: yet wherefore should we mourn?
For man must to his kindred dust return;
Submit to the destroying hand of fate,
As ripen’d ears the harvest-sickle wait.
41
117He would not allow a speech of this kind to avail at all to the cure of
our grief, for he said it was a lamentable case itself that we were
fallen into the hands of such a cruel fate; and that a speech like that,
preaching up comfort from the misfortunes of another, was a comfort
adapted only to those of a malevolent disposition. But to me it appears
far otherwise; for the necessity of bearing what is the common condition
of humanity forbids your resisting the will of the Gods, and reminds you
that you are a man, which reflection greatly alleviates grief; and the
enumeration of these examples is not produced with a view to please
those of a malevolent disposition, but in order that any one in
affliction may be induced to bear what he observes many others have
previously borne with tranquillity and moderation. For they who are
falling to pieces, and cannot hold together through the greatness of
their grief, should be supported by all kinds of assistance. From whence
Chrysippus thinks that grief is called О»бЅ»ПЂО·, as it were О»бЅ»ПѓО№П‚, that is
to say, a dissolution of the whole man—the whole of which I think may
be pulled up by the roots by explaining, as I said at the beginning, the
cause of grief; for it is nothing else but an opinion and judgment
formed of a present acute evil. And thus any bodily pain, let it be ever
so grievous, may be endurable where any hopes are proposed of some
considerable good; and we receive such consolation from a virtuous and
illustrious life that they who lead such lives are seldom attacked by
grief, or but slightly affected by it.
XXVI. But as besides this opinion of great evil there is this other
added also—that we ought to lament what has happened, that it is right
so to do, and part of our duty, then is brought about that terrible
disorder of mind, grief. And it is to this opinion that we owe all those
various and horrid kinds of lamentation, that neglect of our persons,
that womanish tearing of our cheeks, that striking on our thighs,
breasts, and heads. Thus Agamemnon, in Homer and in Accius,
Tears in his grief his uncomb’d locks;
42
from whence comes that pleasant saying of Bion, that the 118foolish king
in his sorrow tore away the hairs of his head, imagining that his grief
would be alleviated by baldness. But men do all these things from being
persuaded that they ought to do so. And thus Г†schines inveighs against
Demosthenes for sacrificing within seven days after the death of his
daughter. But with what eloquence, with what fluency, does he attack
him! what sentiments does he collect! what words does he hurl against
him! You may see by this that an orator may do anything; but nobody
would approve of such license if it were not that we have an idea innate
in our minds that every good man ought to lament the loss of a relation
as bitterly as possible. And it is owing to this that some men, when in
sorrow, betake themselves to deserts, as Homer says of Bellerophon:
Distracted in his mind,
Forsook by heaven, forsaking human kind,
Wide o’er the Aleïan field he chose to stray,
A long, forlorn, uncomfortable way!43
And thus Niobe is feigned to have been turned into stone, from her never
speaking, I suppose, in her grief. But they imagine Hecuba to have been
converted into a bitch, from her rage and bitterness of mind. There are
others who love to converse with solitude itself when in grief, as the
nurse in Ennius,
Fain would I to the heavens find earth relate
Medea’s ceaseless woes and cruel fate.
44
XXVII. Now all these things are done in grief, from a persuasion of
their truth and propriety and necessity; and it is plain that those who
behave thus do so from a conviction of its being their duty; for should
these mourners by chance drop their grief, and either act or speak for a
moment in a more calm or cheerful manner, they presently check
themselves and return to their lamentations again, and blame themselves
for having been guilty of any intermissions
119from their grief; and
parents and masters generally correct children not by words only, but by
blows, if they show any levity by either word or deed when the family is
under affliction, and, as it were, oblige them to be sorrowful. What!
does it not appear, when you have ceased to mourn, and have discovered
that your grief has been ineffectual, that the whole of that mourning
was voluntary on your part? What does that man say in Terence who
punishes himself, the Self-tormentor?
I think I do my son less harm, O Chremes,
As long as I myself am miserable.
He determines to be miserable: and can any one determine on anything
against his will?
I well might think that I deserved all evil.
He would think he deserved any misfortune were he otherwise than
miserable! Therefore, you see, the evil is in opinion, not in nature.
How is it when some things do of themselves prevent your grieving at
them? as in Homer, so many died and were buried daily that they had not
leisure to grieve: where you find these lines—
The great, the bold, by thousands daily fall,
And endless were the grief to weep for all.
Eternal sorrows what avails to shed?
Greece honors not with solemn fasts the dead:
Enough when death demands the brave to pay
The tribute of a melancholy day.
One chief with patience to the grave resign’d,
Our care devolves on others left behind.
45
Therefore it is in our own power to lay aside grief upon occasion; and
is there any opportunity (seeing the thing is in our own power) that we
should let slip of getting rid of care and grief? It was plain that the
friends of Cnæus Pompeius, when they saw him fainting under his wounds,
at the very moment of that most miserable and bitter sight were under
great uneasiness how they themselves,
120surrounded by the enemy as they
were, should escape, and were employed in nothing but encouraging the
rowers and aiding their escape; but when they reached Tyre, they began
to grieve and lament over him. Therefore, as fear with them, prevailed
over grief, cannot reason and true philosophy have the same effect with
a wise man?
XXVIII. But what is there more effectual to dispel grief than the
discovery that it answers no purpose, and has been undergone to no
account? Therefore, if we can get rid of it, we need never have been
subject to it. It must be acknowledged, then, that men take up grief
wilfully and knowingly; and this appears from the patience of those who,
after they have been exercised in afflictions and are better able to
bear whatever befalls them, suppose themselves hardened against fortune;
as that person in Euripides,
Had this the first essay of fortune been,
And I no storms thro’ all my life had seen,
Wild as a colt I’d broke from reason’s sway;
But frequent griefs have taught me to obey.
46
As, then, the frequent bearing of misery makes grief the lighter, we
must necessarily perceive that the cause and original of it does not lie
in the calamity itself. Your principal philosophers, or lovers of
wisdom, though they have not yet arrived at perfect wisdom, are not they
sensible that they are in the greatest evil? For they are foolish, and
foolishness is the greatest of all evils, and yet they lament not. How
shall we account for this? Because opinion is not fixed upon that kind
of evil, it is not our opinion that it is right, meet, and our duty to
be uneasy because we are not all wise men. Whereas this opinion is
strongly affixed to that uneasiness where mourning is concerned, which
is the greatest of all grief. Therefore Aristotle, when he blames some
ancient philosophers for imagining that by their genius they had brought
philosophy 121to the highest perfection, says, they must be either
extremely foolish or extremely vain; but that he himself could see that
great improvements had been made therein in a few years, and that
philosophy would in a little time arrive at perfection. And Theophrastus
is reported to have reproached nature at his death for giving to stags
and crows so long a life, which was of no use to them, but allowing only
so short a span to men, to whom length of days would have been of the
greatest use; for if the life of man could have been lengthened, it
would have been able to provide itself with all kinds of learning, and
with arts in the greatest perfection. He lamented, therefore, that he
was dying just when he had begun to discover these. What! does not every
grave and distinguished philosopher acknowledge himself ignorant of many
things, and confess that there are many things which he must learn over
and over again? And yet, though these men are sensible that they are
standing still in the very midway of folly, than which nothing can be
worse, they are under no great affliction, because no opinion that it is
their duty to lament is ever mingled with this knowledge. What shall we
say of those who think it unbecoming in a man to grieve? among whom we
may reckon Q. Maximus, when he buried his son that had been consul, and
L. Paulus, who lost two sons within a few days of one another. Of the
same opinion was M. Cato, who lost his son just after he had been
elected prætor, and many others, whose names I have collected in my book
on Consolation. Now what made these men so easy, but their persuasion
that grief and lamentation was not becoming in a man? Therefore, as some
give themselves up to grief from an opinion that it is right so to do,
they refrained themselves, from an opinion that it was discreditable;
from which we may infer that grief is owing more to opinion than nature.
XXIX. It may be said, on the other side, Who is so mad as to grieve of
his own accord? Pain proceeds from nature, which you must submit to, say
they, agreeably to what even your own Crantor teaches, for it presses
and gains upon you unavoidably, and cannot possibly be resisted. So that
the very same Oileus, in Sophocles, who had before comforted Telamon on
the death of Ajax, on 122hearing of the death of his own son, is
broken-hearted. On this alteration of his mind we have these lines:
Show me the man so well by wisdom taught
That what he charges to another’s fault,
When like affliction doth himself betide,
True to his own wise counsel will abide.
47
Now, when they urge these things, their endeavor is to prove that nature
is absolutely and wholly irresistible; and yet the same people allow
that we take greater grief on ourselves than nature requires. What
madness is it, then, in us to require the same from others? But there
are many reasons for our taking grief on us. The first is from the
opinion of some evil, on the discovery and certainty of which grief
comes of course. Besides, many people are persuaded that they are doing
something very acceptable to the dead when they lament bitterly over
them. To these may be added a kind of womanish superstition, in
imagining that when they have been stricken by the afflictions sent by
the Gods, to acknowledge themselves afflicted and humbled by them is the
readiest way of appeasing them. But most men appear to be unaware what
contradictions these things are full of. They commend those who die
calmly, but they blame those who can bear the loss of another with the
same calmness, as if it were possible that it should be true, as is
occasionally said in love speeches, that any one can love another more
than himself. There is, indeed, something excellent in this, and, if you
examine it, something no less just than true, that we love those who
ought to be most dear to us as well as we love ourselves; but to love
them more than ourselves is absolutely impossible; nor is it desirable
in friendship that I should love my friend more than myself, or that he
should love me so; for this would occasion much confusion in life, and
break in upon all the duties of it.
123XXX. But we will speak of this another time: at present it is
sufficient not to attribute our misery to the loss of our friends, nor
to love them more than, if they themselves could be sensible of our
conduct, they would approve of, or at least not more than we do
ourselves. Now as to what they say, that some are not at all appeased by
our consolations; and, moreover, as to what they add, that the
comforters themselves acknowledge they are miserable when fortune varies
the attack and falls on them—in both these cases the solution is easy:
for the fault here is not in nature, but in our own folly; and much may
be said against folly. But men who do not admit of consolation seem to
bespeak misery for themselves; and they who cannot bear their
misfortunes with that temper which they recommend to others are not more
faulty in this particular than most other persons; for we see that
covetous men find fault with others who are covetous, as do the
vainglorious with those who appear too wholly devoted to the pursuit of
glory. For it is the peculiar characteristic of folly to perceive the
vices of others, but to forget its own. But since we find that grief is
removed by length of time, we have the greatest proof that the strength
of it depends not merely on time, but on the daily consideration of it.
For if the cause continues the same, and the man be the same, how can
there be any alteration in the grief, if there is no change in what
occasioned the grief, nor in him who grieves? Therefore it is from daily
reflecting that there is no real evil in the circumstance for which you
grieve, and not from the length of time, that you procure a remedy for
your grief.
XXXI. Here some people talk of moderate grief; but if such be natural,
what occasion is there for consolation? for nature herself will
determine, the measure of it: but if it depends on and is caused by
opinion, the whole opinion should be destroyed. I think that it has been
sufficiently said, that grief arises from an opinion of some present
evil, which includes this belief, that it is incumbent on us to grieve.
To this definition Zeno has added, very justly, that the opinion of this
present evil should be recent. Now this word recent they explain thus:
those are not the only recent things which happened a little while ago;
but as 124long as there shall be any force, or vigor, or freshness in that
imagined evil, so long it is entitled to the name of recent. Take the
case of Artemisia, the wife of Mausolus, King of Caria, who made that
noble sepulchre at Halicarnassus; while she lived, she lived in grief,
and died of it, being worn out by it, for that opinion was always recent
with her: but you cannot call that recent which has already begun to
decay through time. Now the duty of a comforter is, to remove grief
entirely, to quiet it, or draw it off as much as you can, or else to
keep it under, and prevent its spreading any further, and to divert
one’s attention to other matters. There are some who think, with
Cleanthes, that the only duty of a comforter is to prove that what one
is lamenting is by no means an evil. Others, as the Peripatetics, prefer
urging that the evil is not great. Others, with Epicurus, seek to divert
your attention from the evil to good: some think it sufficient to show
that nothing has happened but what you had reason to expect; and this is
the practice of the Cyrenaics. But Chrysippus thinks that the main thing
in comforting is, to remove the opinion from the person who is grieving,
that to grieve is his bounden duty. There are others who bring together
all these various kinds of consolations, for people are differently
affected; as I have done myself in my book on Consolation; for as my own
mind was much disordered, I have attempted in that book to discover
every method of cure. But the proper season is as much to be attended to
in the cure of the mind as of the body; as Prometheus in Г†schylus, on
its being said to him,
I think, Prometheus, you this tenet hold,
That all men’s reason should their rage control?
answers,
Yes, when one reason properly applies;
Ill-timed advice will make the storm but rise.
48
XXXII. But the principal medicine to be applied in consolation is, to
maintain either that it is no evil at all,
125or a very inconsiderable
one: the next best to that is, to speak of the common condition of life,
having a view, if possible, to the state of the person whom you comfort
particularly. The third is, that it is folly to wear one’s self out with
grief which can avail nothing. For the comfort of Cleanthes is suitable
only for a wise man, who is in no need of any comfort at all; for could
you persuade one in grief that nothing is an evil but what is base, you
would not only cure him of grief, but folly. But the time for such
precepts is not well chosen. Besides, Cleanthes does not seem to me
sufficiently aware that affliction may very often proceed from that very
thing which he himself allows to be the greatest misfortune. For what
shall we say? When Socrates had convinced Alcibiades, as we are told,
that he had no distinctive qualifications as a man different from other
people, and that, in fact, there was no difference between him, though a
man of the highest rank, and a porter; and when Alcibiades became uneasy
at this, and entreated Socrates, with tears in his eyes, to make him a
man of virtue, and to cure him of that mean position; what shall we say
to this, Cleanthes? Was there no evil in what afflicted Alcibiades thus?
What strange things does Lycon say? who, making light of grief, says
that it arises from trifles, from things that affect our fortune or
bodies, not from the evils of the mind. What, then? did not the grief of
Alcibiades proceed from the defects and evils of the mind? I have
already said enough of Epicurus’s consolation.
XXXIII. Nor is that consolation much to be relied on, though it is
frequently practised, and sometimes has some effect, namely, “That you
are not alone in this.” It has its effect, as I said, but not always,
nor with every person, for some reject it; but much depends on the
application of it; for you ought rather to show, not how men in general
have been affected with such evils, but how men of sense have borne
them. As to Chrysippus’s method, it is certainly founded in truth; but
it is difficult to apply it in time of distress. It is a work of no
small difficulty to persuade a person in affliction that he grieves
merely because he thinks it right so to do. Certainly, then, as in
pleadings we do not state all cases alike (if I may adopt
126the language
of lawyers for a moment), but adapt what we have to say to the time, to
the nature of the subject under debate, and to the person; so, too, in
alleviating grief, regard should be had to what kind of cure the party
to be comforted can admit of. But, somehow or other, we have rambled
from what you originally proposed. For your question was concerning a
wise man, with whom nothing can have the appearance of evil that is not
dishonorable; or at least, anything else would seem so small an evil
that by his wisdom he would so overmatch it as to make it wholly
disappear; and such a man makes no addition to his grief through
opinion, and never conceives it right to torment himself above measure,
nor to wear himself out with grief, which is the meanest thing
imaginable. Reason, however, it seems, has demonstrated (though it was
not directly our object at the moment to inquire whether anything can be
called an evil except what is base) that it is in our power to discern
that all the evil which there is in affliction has nothing natural in
it, but is contracted by our own voluntary judgment of it, and the error
of opinion.
XXXIV. But the kind of affliction of which I have treated is that which
is the greatest; in order that when we have once got rid of that, it may
appear a business of less consequence to look after remedies for the
others. For there are certain things which are usually said about
poverty; and also certain statements ordinarily applied to retired and
undistinguished life. There are particular treatises on banishment, on
the ruin of one’s country, on slavery, on weakness, on blindness, and on
every incident that can come under the name of an evil. The Greeks
divide these into different treatises and distinct books; but they do it
for the sake of employment: not but that all such discussions are full
of entertainment. And yet, as physicians, in curing the whole body,
attend to even the most insignificant part of the body which is at all
disordered, so does philosophy act, after it has removed grief in
general; still, if any other deficiency exists—should poverty bite,
should ignominy sting, should banishment bring a dark cloud over us, or
should any of those things which I have just mentioned appear, there is
for each its appropriate
127consolation, which you shall hear whenever you
please. But we must have recourse again to the same original principle,
that a wise man is free from all sorrow, because it is vain, because it
answers no purpose, because it is not founded in nature, but on opinion
and prejudice, and is engendered by a kind of invitation to grieve, when
once men have imagined that it is their duty to do so. When, then, we
have subtracted what is altogether voluntary, that mournful uneasiness
will be removed; yet some little anxiety, some slight pricking, will
still remain. They may indeed call this natural, provided they give it
not that horrid, solemn, melancholy name of grief, which can by no means
consist with wisdom. But how various and how bitter are the roots of
grief! Whatever they are, I propose, after having felled the trunk, to
destroy them all; even if it should be necessary, by allotting a
separate dissertation to each, for I have leisure enough to do so,
whatever time it may take up. But the principle of every uneasiness is
the same, though they may appear under different names. For envy is an
uneasiness; so are emulation, detraction, anguish, sorrow, sadness,
tribulation, lamentation, vexation, grief, trouble, affliction, and
despair. The Stoics define all these different feelings; and all those
words which I have mentioned belong to different things, and do not, as
they seem, express the same ideas; but they are to a certain extent
distinct, as I shall make appear perhaps in another place. These are
those fibres of the roots which, as I said at first, must be traced back
and cut off and destroyed, so that not one shall remain. You say it is a
great and difficult undertaking: who denies it? But what is there of any
excellency which has not its difficulty? Yet philosophy undertakes to
effect it, provided we admit its superintendence. But enough of this.
The other books, whenever you please, shall be ready for you here or
anywhere else.
128BOOK IV.
On other perturbations of the mind.
I.
I have often wondered, Brutus, on many occasions, at the ingenuity
and virtues of our countrymen; but nothing has surprised me more than
their development in those studies, which, though they came somewhat
late to us, have been transported into this city from Greece. For the
system of auspices, and religious ceremonies, and courts of justice, and
appeals to the people, the senate, the establishment of an army of
cavalry and infantry, and the whole military discipline, were instituted
as early as the foundation of the city by royal authority, partly too by
laws, not without the assistance of the Gods. Then with what a
surprising and incredible progress did our ancestors advance towards all
kind of excellence, when once the republic was freed from the regal
power! Not that this is a proper occasion to treat of the manners and
customs of our ancestors, or of the discipline and constitution of the
city; for I have elsewhere, particularly in the six books I wrote on the
Republic, given a sufficiently accurate account of them. But while I am
on this subject, and considering the study of philosophy, I meet with
many reasons to imagine that those studies were brought to us from
abroad, and not merely imported, but preserved and improved; for they
had Pythagoras, a man of consummate wisdom and nobleness of character,
in a manner, before their eyes, who was in Italy at the time that Lucius
Brutus, the illustrious founder of your nobility, delivered his country
from tyranny. As the doctrine of Pythagoras spread itself on all sides,
it seems probable to me that it reached this city; and this is not only
probable of itself, but it does really appear to have been the case from
many remains of it. For who can imagine that, when it flourished so much
in that part of Italy which was called Magna Græcia, and in some of the
129largest and most powerful cities, in which, first the name of
Pythagoras, and then that of those men who were afterward his followers,
was in so high esteem; who can imagine, I say, that our people could
shut their ears to what was said by such learned men? Besides, it is
even my opinion that it was the great esteem in which the Pythagoreans
were held, that gave rise to that opinion among those who came after
him, that King Numa was a Pythagorean. For, being acquainted with the
doctrine and principles of Pythagoras, and having heard from their
ancestors that this king was a very wise and just man, and not being
able to distinguish accurately between times and periods that were so
remote, they inferred, from his being so eminent for his wisdom, that he
had been a pupil of Pythagoras.
II. So far we proceed on conjecture. As to the vestiges of the
Pythagoreans, though I might collect many, I shall use but a few;
because they have no connection with our present purpose. For, as it is
reported to have been a custom with them to deliver certain precepts in
a more abstruse manner in verse, and to bring their minds from severe
thought to a more composed state by songs and musical instruments; so
Cato, a writer of the very highest authority, says in his Origins, that
it was customary with our ancestors for the guests at their
entertainments, every one in his turn, to celebrate the praises and
virtues of illustrious men in song to the sound of the flute; from
whence it is clear that poems and songs were then composed for the
voice. And, indeed, it is also clear that poetry was in fashion from the
laws of the Twelve Tables, wherein it is provided that no song should be
made to the injury of another. Another argument of the erudition of
those times is, that they played on instruments before the shrines of
their Gods, and at the entertainments of their magistrates; but that
custom was peculiar to the sect I am speaking of. To me, indeed, that
poem of Appius Cæcus, which Panætius commends so much in a certain
letter of his which is addressed to Quintus Tubero, has all the marks of
a Pythagorean author. We have many things derived from the Pythagoreans
in our customs, which I pass over, that we may
130not seem to have learned
that elsewhere which we look upon ourselves as the inventors of. But to
return to our purpose. How many great poets as well as orators have
sprung up among us! and in what a short time! so that it is evident that
our people could arrive at any learning as soon as they had an
inclination for it. But of other studies I shall speak elsewhere if
there is occasion, as I have already often done.
III. The study of philosophy is certainly of long standing with us; but
yet I do not find that I can give you the names of any philosopher
before the age of Lælius and Scipio, in whose younger days we find that
Diogenes the Stoic, and Carneades the Academic, were sent as ambassadors
by the Athenians to our senate. And as these had never been concerned in
public affairs, and one of them was a Cyrenean, the other a Babylonian,
they certainly would never have been forced from their studies, nor
chosen for that employment, unless the study of philosophy had been in
vogue with some of the great men at that time; who, though they might
employ their pens on other subjects—some on civil law, others on
oratory, others on the history of former times—yet promoted this most
extensive of all arts, the principle of living well, even more by their
life than by their writings. So that of that true and elegant philosophy
(which was derived from Socrates, and is still preserved by the
Peripatetics and by the Stoics, though they express themselves
differently in their disputes with the Academics) there are few or no
Latin records; whether this proceeds from the importance of the thing
itself, or from men’s being otherwise employed, or from their concluding
that the capacity of the people was not equal to the apprehension of
them. But, during this silence, C. Amafinius arose and took upon himself
to speak; on the publishing of whose writings the people were moved, and
enlisted themselves chiefly under this sect, either because the doctrine
was more easily understood, or because they were invited thereto by the
pleasing thoughts of amusement, or that, because there was nothing
better, they laid hold of what was offered them. And after Amafinius,
when many of the same sentiments had written much about them, the
Pythagoreans
131spread over all Italy: but that these doctrines should be
so easily understood and approved of by the unlearned is a great proof
that they were not written with any great subtlety, and they think their
establishment to be owing to this.
IV. But let every one defend his own opinion, for every one is at
liberty to choose what he likes: I shall keep to my old custom; and,
being under no restraint from the laws of any particular school, which
in philosophy every one must necessarily confine himself to, I shall
always inquire what has the most probability in every question, and this
system, which I have often practised on other occasions, I have adhered
closely to in my Tusculan Disputations. Therefore, as I have acquainted
you with the disputations of the three former days, this book shall
conclude the discussion of the fourth day. When we had come down into
the Academy, as we had done the former days, the business was carried on
thus:
M. Let any one say, who pleases, what he would wish to have discussed.
A. I do not think a wise man can possibly be free from every
perturbation of mind.
M. He seemed by yesterday’s discourse to be free from grief; unless
you agreed with us only to avoid taking up time.
A. Not at all on that account, for I was extremely satisfied with your
discourse.
M. You do not think, then, that a wise man is subject to grief?
A. No, by no means.
M. But if that cannot disorder the mind of a wise man, nothing else
can. For what—can such a man be disturbed by fear? Fear proceeds from
the same things when absent which occasion grief when present. Take away
grief, then, and you remove fear.
The two remaining perturbations are, a joy elate above measure, and
lust; and if a wise man is not subject to these, his mind will be always
at rest.
A. I am entirely of that opinion.
M. Which, then, shall we do? Shall I immediately crowd all my sails?
or shall I make use of my oars, as if I were just endeavoring to get
clear of the harbor?
132A. What is it that you mean, for I do not exactly comprehend you?
V.
M. Because, Chrysippus and the Stoics, when they discuss the
perturbations of the mind, make great part of their debate to consist in
definitions and distinctions; while they employ but few words on the
subject of curing the mind, and preventing it from being disordered.
Whereas the Peripatetics bring a great many things to promote the cure
of it, but have no regard to their thorny partitions and definitions. My
question, then, was, whether I should instantly unfold the sails of my
eloquence, or be content for a while to make less way with the oars of
logic?
A. Let it be so; for by the employment of both these means the subject
of our inquiry will be more thoroughly discussed.
M. It is certainly the better way; and should anything be too obscure,
you may examine that afterward.
A. I will do so; but those very obscure points you will, as usual,
deliver with more clearness than the Greeks.
M. I will, indeed, endeavor to do so; but it well requires great
attention, lest, by losing one word, the whole should escape you. What
the Greeks call
ПЂбЅ±ОёО· we choose to name perturbations (or disorders)
rather than diseases; in explaining which, I shall follow, first, that
very old description of Pythagoras, and afterward that of Plato; for
they both divide the mind into two parts, and make one of these partake
of reason, and the other they represent without it. In that which
partakes of reason they place tranquillity, that is to say, a placid and
undisturbed constancy; to the other they assign the turbid motions of
anger and desire, which are contrary and opposite to reason. Let this,
then, be our principle, the spring of all our reasonings. But
notwithstanding, I shall use the partitions and definitions of the
Stoics in describing these perturbations; who seem to me to have shown
very great acuteness on this question.
VI. Zeno’s definition, then, is this: “A perturbation” (which he calls a
πάθος) “is a commotion of the mind repugnant to reason, and against
nature.” Some of them define it even more briefly, saying that a
perturbation is a somewhat too vehement appetite; but by too vehement
they mean an appetite
133that recedes further from the constancy of
nature. But they would have the divisions of perturbations to arise from
two imagined goods, and from two imagined evils; and thus they become
four: from the good proceed lust and joy—joy having reference to some
present good, and lust to some future one. They suppose fear and grief
to proceed from evils: fear from something future, grief from something
present; for whatever things are dreaded as approaching always occasion
grief when present. But joy and lust depend on the opinion of good; as
lust, being inflamed and provoked, is carried on eagerly towards what
has the appearance of good; and joy is transported and exults on
obtaining what was desired: for we naturally pursue those things that
have the appearance of good, and avoid the contrary. Wherefore, as soon
as anything that has the appearance of good presents itself, nature
incites us to endeavor to obtain it. Now, where this strong desire is
consistent and founded on prudence, it is by the Stoics called
ОІОїбЅ»О»О·ПѓО№П‚,
and the name which we give it is volition; and this they allow to none
but their wise man, and define it thus: Volition is a reasonable desire;
but whatever is incited too violently in opposition to reason, that is a
lust, or an unbridled desire, which is discoverable in all fools. And,
therefore, when we are affected so as to be placed in any good
condition, we are moved in two ways; for when the mind is moved in a
placid and calm motion, consistent with reason, that is called joy; but
when it exults with a vain, wanton exultation, or immoderate joy, then
that feeling may be called immoderate ecstasy or transport, which they
define to be an elation of the mind without reason. And as we naturally
desire good things, so in like manner we naturally seek to avoid what is
evil; and this avoidance of which, if conducted in accordance with
reason, is called caution; and this the wise man alone is supposed to
have: but that caution which is not under the guidance of reason, but is
attended with a base and low dejection, is called fear. Fear is,
therefore, caution destitute of reason. But a wise man is not affected
by any present evil; while the grief of a fool proceeds from being
affected with an imaginary evil, by which his mind is contracted and
sunk, since it is not under the dominion
134of reason. This, then, is the
first definition, which makes grief to consist in a shrinking of the
mind contrary to the dictates of reason. Thus, there are four
perturbations, and but three calm rational emotions; for grief has no
exact opposite.
VII. But they insist upon it that all perturbations depend on opinion
and judgment; therefore they define them more strictly, in order not
only the better to show how blamable they are, but to discover how much
they are in our power. Grief, then, is a recent opinion of some present
evil, in which it seems to be right that the mind should shrink and be
dejected. Joy is a recent opinion of a present good, in which it seems
to be right that the mind should be elated. Fear is an opinion of an
impending evil which we apprehend will be intolerable. Lust is an
opinion of a good to come, which would be of advantage were it already
come, and present with us. But however I have named the judgments and
opinions of perturbations, their meaning is, not that merely the
perturbations consist in them, but that the effects likewise of these
perturbations do so; as grief occasions a kind of painful pricking, and
fear engenders a recoil or sudden abandonment of the mind, joy gives
rise to a profuse mirth, while lust is the parent of an unbridled habit
of coveting. But that imagination, which I have included in all the
above definitions, they would have to consist in assenting without
warrantable grounds. Now, every perturbation has many subordinate parts
annexed to it of the same kind. Grief is attended with enviousness
(
invidentia)—I use that word for instruction’s sake, though it is not
so common; because envy (
invidia) takes in not only the person who
envies, but the person, too, who is envied—emulation, detraction, pity,
vexation, mourning, sadness, tribulation, sorrow, lamentation,
solicitude, disquiet of mind, pain, despair, and many other similar
feelings are so too. Under fear are comprehended sloth, shame, terror,
cowardice, fainting, confusion, astonishment. In pleasure they
comprehend malevolence—that is, pleased at another’s
misfortune—delight, boastfulness, and the like. To lust they associate
anger, fury, hatred, enmity, discord, wants, desire, and other feelings
of that kind.
135But they define these in this manner:
VIII. Enviousness (
invidentia), they say, is a grief arising from the
prosperous circumstances of another, which are in no degree injurious to
the person who envies; for where any one grieves at the prosperity of
another, by which he is injured, such a one is not properly said to
envy—as when Agamemnon grieves at Hector’s success; but where any one,
who is in no way hurt by the prosperity of another, is in pain at his
success, such a one envies indeed. Now the name “emulation” is taken in
a double sense, so that the same word may stand for praise and
dispraise: for the imitation of virtue is called emulation (however,
that sense of it I shall have no occasion for here, for that carries
praise with it); but emulation is also a term applied to grief at
another’s enjoying what I desired to have, and am without. Detraction
(and I mean by that, jealousy) is a grief even at another’s enjoying
what I had a great inclination for. Pity is a grief at the misery of
another who suffers wrongfully; for no one is moved by pity at the
punishment of a parricide or of a betrayer of his country. Vexation is a
pressing grief. Mourning is a grief at the bitter death of one who was
dear to you. Sadness is a grief attended with tears. Tribulation is a
painful grief. Sorrow, an excruciating grief. Lamentation, a grief where
we loudly bewail ourselves. Solicitude, a pensive grief. Trouble, a
continued grief. Affliction, a grief that harasses the body. Despair, a
grief that excludes all hope of better things to come. But those
feelings which are included under fear, they define thus: There is
sloth, which is a dread of some ensuing labor; shame and terror, which
affect the body—hence blushing attends shame; a paleness, and tremor,
and chattering of the teeth attend terror—cowardice, which is an
apprehension of some approaching evil; dread, a fear that unhinges the
mind, whence comes that line of Ennius,
Then dread discharged all wisdom from my mind;
fainting is the associate and constant attendant on dread; confusion, a
fear that drives away all thought; alarm, a continued fear.
136IX. The different species into which they divide pleasure come under
this description; so that malevolence is a pleasure in the misfortunes
of another, without any advantage to yourself; delight, a pleasure that
soothes the mind by agreeable impressions on the ear. What is said of
the ear may be applied to the sight, to the touch, smell, and taste. All
feelings of this kind are a sort of melting pleasure that dissolves the
mind. Boastfulness is a pleasure that consists in making an appearance,
and setting off yourself with insolence.—The subordinate species of
lust they define in this manner: Anger is a lust of punishing any one
who, as we imagine, has injured us without cause. Heat is anger just
forming and beginning to exist, which the Greeks call ОёбЅ»ОјП‰ПѓО№П‚. Hatred is
a settled anger. Enmity is anger waiting for an opportunity of revenge.
Discord is a sharper anger conceived deeply in the mind and heart. Want
an insatiable lust. Regret is when one eagerly wishes to see a person
who is absent. Now here they have a distinction; so that with them
regret is a lust conceived on hearing of certain things reported of some
one, or of many, which the Greeks call ОєО±П„О·ОіОїПЃбЅµОјО±П„О±, or predicaments; as
that they are in possession of riches and honors: but want is a lust for
those very honors and riches. But these definers make intemperance the
fountain of all these perturbations; which is an absolute revolt from
the mind and right reason—a state so averse to all rules of reason that
the appetites of the mind can by no means be governed and restrained.
As, therefore, temperance appeases these desires, making them obey right
reason, and maintains the well-weighed judgments of the mind, so
intemperance, which is in opposition to this, inflames, confounds, and
puts every state of the mind into a violent motion. Thus, grief and
fear, and every other perturbation of the mind, have their rise from
intemperance.
X. Just as distempers and sickness are bred in the body from the
corruption of the blood, and the too great abundance of phlegm and bile,
so the mind is deprived of its health, and disordered with sickness,
from a confusion of depraved opinions that are in opposition to one
another. From these perturbations arise, first, diseases, which they
call ОЅОїПѓбЅµОјО±П„О±; and also those feelings which are in opposition 137to these
diseases, and which admit certain faulty distastes or loathings; then
come sicknesses, which are called ἀῤῥωστήματα by the Stoics, and these
two have their opposite aversions. Here the Stoics, especially
Chrysippus, give themselves unnecessary trouble to show the analogy
which the diseases of the mind have to those of the body: but,
overlooking all that they say as of little consequence, I shall treat
only of the thing itself. Let us, then, understand perturbation to imply
a restlessness from the variety and confusion of contradictory opinions;
and that when this heat and disturbance of the mind is of any standing,
and has taken up its residence, as it were, in the veins and marrow,
then commence diseases and sickness, and those aversions which are in
opposition to these diseases and sicknesses.
XI. What I say here may be distinguished in thought, though they are in
fact the same; inasmuch as they both have their rise from lust and joy.
For should money be the object of our desire, and should we not
instantly apply to reason, as if it were a kind of Socratic medicine to
heal this desire, the evil glides into our veins, and cleaves to our
bowels, and from thence proceeds a distemper or sickness, which, when it
is of any continuance, is incurable, and the name of this disease is
covetousness. It is the same with other diseases; as the desire of
glory, a passion for women, to which the Greeks give the name of
П†О№О»ОїОіП…ОЅОµбЅ·О±: and thus all other diseases and sicknesses are generated.
But those feelings which are the contrary of these are supposed to have
fear for their foundation, as a hatred of women, such as is displayed in
the Woman-hater of Atilius; or the hatred of the whole human species, as
Timon is reported to have done, whom they call the Misanthrope. Of the
same kind is inhospitality. And all these diseases proceed from a
certain dread of such things as they hate and avoid. But they define
sickness of mind to be an overweening opinion, and that fixed and deeply
implanted in the heart, of something as very desirable which is by no
means so. What proceeds from aversion, they define thus: a vehement idea
of something to be avoided, deeply implanted, and inherent in our minds,
when there is no reason for avoiding it; and this kind of opinion is a
deliberate 138belief that one understands things of which one is wholly
ignorant. Now, sickness of the mind has all these subordinate divisions:
avarice, ambition, fondness for women, obstinacy, gluttony, drunkenness,
covetousness, and other similar vices. But avarice is a violent opinion
about money, as if it were vehemently to be desired and sought after,
which opinion is deeply implanted and inherent in our minds; and the
definition of all the other similar feelings resembles these. But the
definitions of aversions are of this sort: inhospitality is a vehement
opinion, deeply implanted and inherent in your mind, that you should
avoid a stranger. Thus, too, the hatred of women, like that felt by
Hippolytus, is defined; and the hatred of the human species like that
displayed by Timon.
XII. But to come to the analogy of the state of body and mind, which I
shall sometimes make use of, though more sparingly than the Stoics. Some
men are more inclined to particular disorders than others; and,
therefore, we say that some people are rheumatic, others dropsical, not
because they are so at present, but because they are often so: some are
inclined to fear, others to some other perturbation. Thus in some there
is a continual anxiety, owing to which they are anxious; in some a
hastiness of temper, which differs from anger, as anxiety differs from
anguish: for all are not anxious who are sometimes vexed, nor are they
who are anxious always uneasy in that manner: as there is a difference
between being drunk and drunkenness; and it is one thing to be a lover,
another to be given to women. And this disposition of particular people
to particular disorders is very common: for it relates to all
perturbations; it appears in many vices, though it has no name. Some
are, therefore, said to be envious, malevolent, spiteful, fearful,
pitiful, from a propensity to those perturbations, not from their being
always carried away by them. Now this propensity to these particular
disorders may be called a sickness from analogy with the body; meaning,
that is to say, nothing more than a propensity towards sickness. But
with regard to whatever is good, as some are more inclined to different
good qualities than others, we may call this a facility or tendency:
this tendency to evil is a proclivity or inclination to falling; 139but
where anything is neither good nor bad, it may have the former name.
XIII. Even as there may be, with respect to the body, a disease, a
sickness, and a defect, so it is with the mind. They call that a disease
where the whole body is corrupted; they call that sickness where a
disease is attended with a weakness, and that a defect where the parts
of the body are not well compacted together; from whence it follows that
the members are misshapen, crooked, and deformed. So that these two, a
disease and sickness, proceed from a violent concussion and perturbation
of the health of the whole body; but a defect discovers itself even when
the body is in perfect health. But a disease of the mind is
distinguishable only in thought from a sickness. But a viciousness is a
habit or affection discordant and inconsistent with itself through life.
Thus it happens that, in the one case, a disease and sickness may arise
from a corruption of opinions; in the other case, the consequence may be
inconstancy and inconsistency. For every vice of the mind does not imply
a disunion of parts; as is the case with those who are not far from
being wise men. With them there is that affection which is inconsistent
with itself while it is foolish; but it is not distorted, nor depraved.
But diseases and sicknesses are parts of viciousness; but it is a
question whether perturbations are parts of the same, for vices are
permanent affections: perturbations are such as are restless; so that
they cannot be parts of permanent ones. As there is some analogy between
the nature of the body and mind in evil, so is there in good; for the
distinctions of the body are beauty, strength, health, firmness,
quickness of motion: the same may be said of the mind. The body is said
to be in a good state when all those things on which health depends are
consistent: the same may be said of the mind when its judgments and
opinions are not at variance with one another. And this union is the
virtue of the mind, which, according to some people, is temperance
itself; others make it consist in an obedience to the precepts of
temperance, and a compliance with them, not allowing it to be any
distinct species of itself. But, be it one or the other, it is to be
found only in a wise man. But there is a certain 140soundness of mind,
which even a fool may have, when the perturbation of his mind is removed
by the care and management of his physicians. And as what is called
beauty arises from an exact proportion of the limbs, together with a
certain sweetness of complexion, so the beauty of the mind consists in
an equality and constancy of opinions and judgments, joined to a certain
firmness and stability, pursuing virtue, or containing within itself the
very essence of virtue. Besides, we give the very same names to the
faculties of the mind as we do to the powers of the body, the nerves,
and other powers of action. Thus the velocity of the body is called
swiftness: a praise which we ascribe to the mind, from its running over
in its thoughts so many things in so short a time.
XIV. Herein, indeed, the mind and body are unlike: that though the mind
when in perfect health may be visited by sickness, as the body may, yet
the body may be disordered without our fault; the mind cannot. For all
the disorders and perturbations of the mind proceed from a neglect of
reason; these disorders, therefore, are confined to men: the beasts are
not subject to such perturbations, though they act sometimes as if they
had reason. There is a difference, too, between ingenious and dull men;
the ingenious, like the Corinthian brass, which is long before it
receives rust, are longer before they fall into these perturbations, and
are recovered sooner: the case is different with the dull. Nor does the
mind of an ingenious man fall into every kind of perturbation, for it
never yields to any that are brutish and savage; and some of their
perturbations have at first even the appearance of humanity, as mercy,
grief, and fear. But the sicknesses and diseases of the mind are thought
to be harder to eradicate than those leading vices which are in
opposition to virtues; for vices may be removed, though the diseases of
the mind should continue, which diseases are not cured with that
expedition with which vices are removed. I have now acquainted you with
the arguments which the Stoics put forth with such exactness; which they
call logic, from their close arguing: and since my discourse has got
clear of these rocks, I will proceed with the remainder of it, provided
I have been sufficiently clear in what I have already 141said, considering
the obscurity of the subject I have treated.
A. Clear enough; but should there be occasion for a more exact
inquiry, I shall take another opportunity of asking you. I expect you
now to hoist your sails, as you just now called them, and proceed on
your course.
XV. M. Since I have spoken before of virtue in other places, and shall
often have occasion to speak again (for a great many questions that
relate to life and manners arise from the spring of virtue); and since,
as I say, virtue consists in a settled and uniform affection of mind,
making those persons praiseworthy who are possessed of her, she herself
also, independent of anything else, without regard to any advantage,
must be praiseworthy; for from her proceed good inclinations, opinions,
actions, and the whole of right reason; though virtue may be defined in
a few words to be right reason itself. The opposite to this is
viciousness (for so I choose to translate what the Greeks call ОєО±ОєбЅ·О±,
rather than by perverseness; for perverseness is the name of a
particular vice; but viciousness includes all), from whence arise those
perturbations which, as I just now said, are turbid and violent motions
of the mind, repugnant to reason, and enemies in a high degree to the
peace of the mind and a tranquil life, for they introduce piercing and
anxious cares, and afflict and debilitate the mind through fear; they
violently inflame our hearts with exaggerated appetite, which is in
reality an impotence of mind, utterly irreconcilable with temperance and
moderation, which we sometimes call desire, and sometimes lust, and
which, should it even attain the object of its wishes, immediately
becomes so elated that it loses all its resolution, and knows not what
to pursue; so that he was in the right who said “that exaggerated
pleasure was the very greatest of mistakes.” Virtue, then, alone can
effect the cure of these evils.
XVI. For what is not only more miserable, but more base and sordid, than
a man afflicted, weakened, and oppressed with grief? And little short of
this misery is one who dreads some approaching evil, and who, through
faintheartedness, is under continual suspense. The poets, to express the
greatness of this evil, imagine a stone to 142hang over the head of
Tantalus, as a punishment for his wickedness, his pride, and his
boasting. And this is the common punishment of folly; for there hangs
over the head of every one whose mind revolts from reason some similar
fear. And as these perturbations of the mind, grief and fear, are of a
most wasting nature, so those two others, though of a more merry cast (I
mean lust, which is always coveting something with eagerness, and empty
mirth, which is an exulting joy), differ very little from madness. Hence
you may understand what sort of person he is whom we call at one time
moderate, at another modest or temperate, at another constant and
virtuous; while sometimes we include all these names in the word
frugality, as the crown of all; for if that word did not include all
virtues, it would never have been proverbial to say that a frugal man
does everything rightly. But when the Stoics apply this saying to their
wise man, they seem to exalt him too much, and to speak of him with too
much admiration.
XVII. Whoever, then, through moderation and constancy, is at rest in his
mind, and in calm possession of himself, so as neither to pine with
care, nor be dejected with fear, nor to be inflamed with desire,
coveting something greedily, nor relaxed by extravagant mirth—such a
man is that identical wise man whom we are inquiring for: he is the
happy man, to whom nothing in this life seems intolerable enough to
depress him; nothing exquisite enough to transport him unduly. For what
is there in this life that can appear great to him who has acquainted
himself with eternity and the utmost extent of the universe? For what is
there in human knowledge, or the short span of this life, that can
appear great to a wise man? whose mind is always so upon its guard that
nothing can befall him which is unforeseen, nothing which is unexpected,
nothing, in short, which is new. Such a man takes so exact a survey on
all sides of him, that he always knows the proper place and spot to live
in free from all the troubles and annoyances of life, and encounters
every accident that fortune can bring upon him with a becoming calmness.
Whoever conducts himself in this manner will be free from grief, and
from every other perturbation; and a mind free from these feelings
renders men completely happy; whereas 143a mind disordered and drawn off
from right and unerring reason loses at once, not only its resolution,
but its health.—Therefore the thoughts and declarations of the
Peripatetics are soft and effeminate, for they say that the mind must
necessarily be agitated, but at the same time they lay down certain
bounds beyond which that agitation is not to proceed. And do you set
bounds to vice? or is it no vice to disobey reason? Does not reason
sufficiently declare that there is no real good which you should desire
too ardently, or the possession of which you should allow to transport
you? and that there is no evil that should be able to overwhelm you, or
the suspicion of which should distract you? and that all these things
assume too melancholy or too cheerful an appearance through our own
error? But if fools find this error lessened by time, so that, though
the cause remains the same, they are not affected, in the same manner,
after some time, as they were at first, why, surely a wise man ought not
to be influenced at all by it. But what are those degrees by which we
are to limit it? Let us fix these degrees in grief, a difficult subject,
and one much canvassed.—Fannius writes that P. Rutilius took it much to
heart that his brother was refused the consulship; but he seems to have
been too much affected by this disappointment, for it was the occasion
of his death: he ought, therefore, to have borne it with more
moderation. But let us suppose that while he was bearing this with
moderation, the death of his children had intervened; here would have
started a fresh grief, which, admitting it to be moderate in itself, yet
still must have been a great addition to the other. Now, to these let us
add some acute pains of body, the loss of his fortune, blindness,
banishment. Supposing, then, each separate misfortune to occasion a
separate additional grief, the whole would be too great to be
supportable.
XVIII. The man who attempts to set bounds to vice acts like one who
should throw himself headlong from Leucate, persuaded that he could stop
himself whenever he pleased. Now, as that is impossible, so a perturbed
and disordered mind cannot restrain itself, and stop where it pleases.
Certainly whatever is bad in its increase is bad in its birth. Now grief
and all other perturbations 144are doubtless baneful in their progress,
and have, therefore, no small share of evil at the beginning; for they
go on of themselves when once they depart from reason, for every
weakness is self-indulgent, and indiscreetly launches out, and does not
know where to stop. So that it makes no difference whether you approve
of moderate perturbations of mind, or of moderate injustice, moderate
cowardice, and moderate intemperance; for whoever prescribes bounds to
vice admits a part of it, which, as it is odious of itself, becomes the
more so as it stands on slippery ground, and, being once set forward,
glides on headlong, and cannot by any means be stopped.
XIX. Why should I say more? Why should I add that the Peripatetics say
that these perturbations, which we insist upon it should be extirpated,
are not only natural, but were given to men by nature for a good
purpose? They usually talk in this manner. In the first place, they say
much in praise of anger; they call it the whetstone of courage, and they
say that angry men exert themselves most against an enemy or against a
bad citizen: that those reasons are of little weight which are the
motives of men who think thus, as—it is a just war; it becomes us to
fight for our laws, our liberties, our country: they will allow no force
to these arguments unless our courage is warmed by anger.—Nor do they
confine their argument to warriors; but their opinion is that no one can
issue any rigid commands without some bitterness and anger. In short,
they have no notion of an orator either accusing or even defending a
client without he is spurred on by anger. And though this anger should
not be real, still they think his words and gestures ought to wear the
appearance of it, so that the action of the orator may excite the anger
of his hearer. And they deny that any man has ever been seen who does
not know what it is to be angry; and they name what we call lenity by
the bad appellation of indolence. Nor do they commend only this lust
(for anger is, as I defined it above, the lust of revenge), but they
maintain that kind of lust or desire to be given us by nature for very
good purposes, saying that no one can execute anything well but what he
is in earnest about. Themistocles used to walk in the public places in
the night because he could 145not sleep; and when asked the reason, his
answer was, that Miltiades’s trophies kept him awake. Who has not heard
how Demosthenes used to watch, who said that it gave him pain if any
mechanic was up in a morning at his work before him? Lastly, they urge
that some of the greatest philosophers would never have made that
progress in their studies without some ardent desire spurring them
on.—We are informed that Pythagoras, Democritus, and Plato visited the
remotest parts of the world; for they thought that they ought to go
wherever anything was to be learned. Now, it is not conceivable that
these things could be effected by anything but by the greatest ardor of
mind.
XX. They say that even grief, which we have already said ought to be
avoided as a monstrous and fierce beast, was appointed by nature, not
without some good purpose, in order that men should lament when they had
committed a fault, well knowing they had exposed themselves to
correction, rebuke, and ignominy; for they think that those who can bear
ignominy and infamy without pain have acquired a complete impunity for
all sorts of crimes; for with them reproach is a stronger check than
conscience. From whence we have that scene in Afranius borrowed from
common life; for when the abandoned son saith, “Wretched that I am!” the
severe father replies,
Let him but grieve, no matter what the cause.
And they say the other divisions of sorrow have their use; that pity
incites us to hasten to the assistance of others, and to alleviate the
calamities of men who have undeservedly fallen into them; that even envy
and detraction are not without their use, as when a man sees that
another person has attained what he cannot, or observes another to be
equally successful with himself; that he who should take away fear would
take away all industry in life, which those men exert in the greatest
degree who are afraid of the laws and of the magistrates, who dread
poverty, ignominy, death, and pain. But while they argue thus, they
allow indeed of these feelings being retrenched, though they deny that
they either can or should be plucked up by the roots; so that their
opinion is that mediocrity is 146best in everything. When they reason in
this manner, what think you—is what they say worth attending to or not?
A. I think it is. I wait, therefore, to hear what you will say in
reply to them.
XXI. M. Perhaps I may find something to say; but I will make this
observation first: do you take notice with what modesty the Academics
behave themselves? for they speak plainly to the purpose. The
Peripatetics are answered by the Stoics; they have my leave to fight it
out, who think myself no otherwise concerned than to inquire for what
may seem to be most probable. Our present business is, then, to see if
we can meet with anything in this question which is the probable, for
beyond such approximation to truth as that human nature cannot proceed.
The definition of a perturbation, as Zeno, I think, has rightly
determined it, is thus: That a perturbation is a commotion of the mind
against nature, in opposition to right reason; or, more briefly, thus,
that a perturbation is a somewhat too vehement appetite; and when he
says somewhat too vehement, he means such as is at a greater distance
from the constant course of nature. What can I say to these definitions?
The greater part of them we have from those who dispute with sagacity
and acuteness: some of them expressions, indeed, such as the “ardors of
the mind,” and “the whetstones of virtue,” savoring of the pomp of
rhetoricians. As to the question, if a brave man can maintain his
courage without becoming angry, it may be questioned with regard to the
gladiators; though we often observe much resolution even in them: they
meet, converse, they make objections and demands, they agree about
terms, so that they seem calm rather than angry. But let us admit a man
of the name of Placideianus, who was one of that trade, to be in such a
mind, as Lucilius relates of him,
If for his blood you thirst, the task be mine;
His laurels at my feet he shall resign;
Not but I know, before I reach his heart,
First on myself a wound he will impart.
I hate the man; enraged I fight, and straight
In action we had been, but that I wait
Till each his sword had fitted to his hand.
My rage I scarce can keep within command.
147XXII. But we see Ajax in Homer advancing to meet Hector in battle
cheerfully, without any of this boisterous wrath. For he had no sooner
taken up his arms than the first step which he made inspired his
associates with joy, his enemies with fear; so that even Hector, as he
is represented by Homer,
49 trembling, condemned himself for having
challenged him to fight. Yet these heroes conversed together, calmly and
quietly, before they engaged; nor did they show any anger or outrageous
behavior during the combat. Nor do I imagine that Torquatus, the first
who obtained this surname, was in a rage when he plundered the Gaul of
his collar; or that Marcellus’s courage at Clastidium was only owing to
his anger. I could almost swear that Africanus, with whom we are better
acquainted, from our recollection of him being more recent, was noways
inflamed by anger when he covered Alienus Pelignus with his shield, and
drove his sword into the enemy’s breast. There may be some doubt of L.
Brutus, whether he was not influenced by extraordinary hatred of the
tyrant, so as to attack Aruns with more than usual rashness; for I
observe that they mutually killed each other in close fight. Why, then,
do you call in the assistance of anger? Would courage, unless it began
to get
148furious, lose its energy? What! do you imagine that Hercules,
whom the very courage which you would try to represent as anger raised
to heaven, was angry when he engaged the Erymanthian boar, or the Nemæan
lion? Or was Theseus in a passion when he seized on the horns of the
Marathonian bull? Take care how you make courage to depend in the least
on rage. For anger is altogether irrational, and that is not courage
which is void of reason.
XXIII. We ought to hold all things here in contempt; death is to be
looked on with indifference; pains and labors must be considered as
easily supportable. And when these sentiments are established on
judgment and conviction, then will that stout and firm courage take
place; unless you attribute to anger whatever is done with vehemence,
alacrity, and spirit. To me, indeed, that very Scipio
50 who was chief
priest, that favorer of the saying of the Stoics, “That no private man
could be a wise man,” does not seem to be angry with Tiberius Gracchus,
even when he left the consul in a hesitating frame of mind, and, though
a private man himself, commanded, with the authority of a consul, that
all who meant well to the republic should follow him. I do not know
whether I have done anything in the republic that has the appearance of
courage; but if I have, I certainly did not do it in wrath. Doth
anything come nearer madness than anger? And indeed Ennius has well
defined it as the beginning of madness. The changing color, the
alteration of our voice, the look of our eyes, our manner of fetching
our breath, the little command we have over our words and actions, how
little do all these things indicate a sound mind! What can make a worse
appearance than Homer’s Achilles, or Agamemnon, during the quarrel? And
as to Ajax, anger drove him into downright madness, and was the occasion
of his death. Courage, therefore, does not want the assistance of anger;
it is sufficiently provided, armed, and prepared of itself. We may as
well say that drunkenness or madness is of service to courage, because
those who
149are mad or drunk often do a great many things with unusual
vehemence. Ajax was always brave; but still he was most brave when he
was in that state of frenzy:
The greatest feat that Ajax e’er achieved
Was, when his single arm the Greeks relieved.
Quitting the field; urged on by rising rage,
Forced the declining troops again t’engage.
Shall we say, then, that madness has its use?
XXIV. Examine the definitions of courage: you will find it does not
require the assistance of passion. Courage is, then, an affection of
mind that endures all things, being itself in proper subjection to the
highest of all laws; or it may be called a firm maintenance of judgment
in supporting or repelling everything that has a formidable appearance,
or a knowledge of what is formidable or otherwise, and maintaining
invariably a stable judgment of all such things, so as to bear them or
despise them; or, in fewer words, according to Chrysippus (for the above
definitions are Sphærus’s, a man of the first ability as a layer-down of
definitions, as the Stoics think. But they are all pretty much alike:
they give us only common notions, some one way, and some another). But
what is Chrysippus’s definition? Fortitude, says he, is the knowledge of
all things that are bearable, or an affection of the mind which bears
and supports everything in obedience to the chief law of reason without
fear. Now, though we should attack these men in the same manner as
Carneades used to do, I fear they are the only real philosophers; for
which of these definitions is there which does not explain that obscure
and intricate notion of courage which every man conceives within
himself? And when it is thus explained, what can a warrior, a commander,
or an orator want more? And no one can think that they will be unable to
behave themselves courageously without anger. What! do not even the
Stoics, who maintain that all fools are mad, make the same inferences?
for, take away perturbations, especially a hastiness of temper, and they
will appear to talk very absurdly. But what they assert is this: they
say that all fools are mad, as all dunghills stink; not that they always
do so, but stir them, and you will perceive it. And in like manner, a
warm-tempered man is 150not always in a passion; but provoke him, and you
will see him run mad. Now, that very warlike anger, which is of such
service in war, what is the use of it to him when he is at home with his
wife, children, and family? Is there, then, anything that a disturbed
mind can do better than one which is calm and steady? Or can any one be
angry without a perturbation of mind? Our people, then, were in the
right, who, as all vices depend on our manners, and nothing is worse
than a passionate disposition, called angry men the only morose men.51
XXV. Anger is in no wise becoming in an orator, though it is not amiss
to affect it. Do you imagine that I am angry when in pleading I use any
extraordinary vehemence and sharpness? What! when I write out my
speeches after all is over and past, am I then angry while writing? Or
do you think Г†sopus was ever angry when he acted, or Accius was so when
he wrote? Those men, indeed, act very well, but the orator acts better
than the player, provided he be really an orator; but, then, they carry
it on without passion, and with a composed mind. But what wantonness is
it to commend lust! You produce Themistocles and Demosthenes; to these
you add Pythagoras, Democritus, and Plato. What! do you then call
studies lust? But these studies of the most excellent and admirable
things, such as those were which you bring forward on all occasions,
ought to be composed and tranquil; and what kind of philosophers are
they who commend grief, than which nothing is more detestable? Afranius
has said much to this purpose:
Let him but grieve, no matter what the cause.
But he spoke this of a debauched and dissolute youth. But we are
inquiring into the conduct of a constant and wise man. We may even allow
a centurion or standard-bearer to be angry, or any others, whom, not to
explain too far the mysteries of the rhetoricians, I shall not mention
here; for to touch the passions, where reason cannot be come at, may
have its use; but my inquiry, as I often repeat, is about a wise man.
151XXVI. But even envy, detraction, pity, have their use. Why should you
pity rather than assist, if it is in your power to do so? Is it because
you cannot be liberal without pity? We should not take sorrows on
ourselves upon another’s account; but we ought to relieve others of
their grief if we can. But to detract from another’s reputation, or to
rival him with that vicious emulation which resembles an enmity, of what
use can that conduct be? Now, envy implies being uneasy at another’s
good because one does not enjoy it one’s self; but detraction is the
being uneasy at another’s good, merely because he enjoys it. How can it
be right that you should voluntarily grieve, rather than take the
trouble of acquiring what you want to have? for it is madness in the
highest degree to desire to be the only one that has any particular
happiness. But who can with correctness speak in praise of a mediocrity
of evils? Can any one in whom there is lust or desire be otherwise than
libidinous or desirous? or can a man who is occupied by anger avoid
being angry? or can one who is exposed to any vexation escape being
vexed? or if he is under the influence of fear, must he not be fearful?
Do we look, then, on the libidinous, the angry, the anxious, and the
timid man, as persons of wisdom, of excellence? of which I could speak
very copiously and diffusely, but I wish to be as concise as possible.
And so I will merely say that wisdom is an acquaintance with all divine
and human affairs, and a knowledge of the cause of everything. Hence it
is that it imitates what is divine, and looks upon all human concerns as
inferior to virtue. Did you, then, say that it was your opinion that
such a man was as naturally liable to perturbation as the sea is exposed
to winds? What is there that can discompose such gravity and constancy?
Anything sudden or unforeseen? How can anything of this kind befall one
to whom nothing is sudden and unforeseen that can happen to man? Now, as
to their saying that redundancies should be pared off, and only what is
natural remain, what, I pray you, can be natural which may be too
exuberant?
XXVII. All these assertions proceed from the roots of errors, which must
be entirely plucked up and destroyed, not pared and amputated. But as I
suspect that your inquiry 152is not so much respecting the wise man as
concerning yourself (for you allow that he is free from all
perturbations, and you would willingly be so too yourself), let us see
what remedies there are which may be applied by philosophy to the
diseases of the mind. There is certainly some remedy; nor has nature
been so unkind to the human race as to have discovered so many things
salutary to the body, and none which are medicinal to the mind. She has
even been kinder to the mind than to the body; inasmuch as you must seek
abroad for the assistance which the body requires, while the mind has
all that it requires within itself. But in proportion as the excellency
of the mind is of a higher and more divine nature, the more diligence
does it require; and therefore reason, when it is well applied,
discovers what is best, but when it is neglected, it becomes involved in
many errors. I shall apply, then, all my discourse to you; for though
you pretend to be inquiring about the wise man, your inquiry may
possibly be about yourself. Various, then, are the cures of those
perturbations which I have expounded, for every disorder is not to be
appeased the same way. One medicine must be applied to the man who
mourns, another to the pitiful, another to the person who envies; for
there is this difference to be maintained in all the four perturbations:
we are to consider whether our discourse had better be directed to
perturbations in general, which are a contempt of reason, or a somewhat
too vehement appetite; or whether it would be better applied to
particular descriptions, as, for instance, to fear, lust, and the rest,
and whether it appears preferable to endeavor to remove that which has
occasioned the grief, or rather to attempt wholly to eradicate every
kind of grief. As, should any one grieve that he is poor, the question
is, Would you maintain poverty to be no evil, or would you contend that
a man ought not to grieve at anything? Certainly this last is the best
course; for should you not convince him with regard to poverty, you must
allow him to grieve; but if you remove grief by particular arguments,
such as I used yesterday, the evil of poverty is in some manner removed.
XXVIII. But any perturbation of the mind of this sort may be, as it
were, wiped away by the method of appeasing 153the mind, if you succeed in
showing that there is no good in that which has given rise to joy and
lust, nor any evil in that which has occasioned fear or grief. But
certainly the most effectual cure is to be achieved by showing that all
perturbations are of themselves vicious, and have nothing natural or
necessary in them. As we see, grief itself is easily softened when we
charge those who grieve with weakness and an effeminate mind; or when we
commend the gravity and constancy of those who bear calmly whatever
befalls them here, as accidents to which all men are liable; and,
indeed, this is generally the feeling of those who look on these as real
evils, but yet think they should be borne with resignation. One imagines
pleasure to be a good, another money; and yet the one may be called off
from intemperance, the other from covetousness. The other method and
address, which, at the same time that it removes the false opinion,
withdraws the disorder, has more subtlety in it; but it seldom succeeds,
and is not applicable to vulgar minds, for there are some diseases which
that medicine can by no means remove. For, should any one be uneasy
because he is without virtue, without courage, destitute of a sense of
duty or honesty, his anxiety proceeds from a real evil; and yet we must
apply another method of cure to him, and such a one as all the
philosophers, however they may differ about other things, agree in. For
they must necessarily agree in this, that commotions of the mind in
opposition to right reason are vicious; and that even admitting those
things to be evils which occasion fear or grief, and those to be goods
which provoke desire or joy, yet that very commotion itself is vicious;
for we mean by the expressions magnanimous and brave, one who is
resolute, sedate, grave, and superior to everything in this life; but
one who either grieves, or fears, or covets, or is transported with
passion, cannot come under that denomination; for these things are
consistent only with those who look on the things of this world as
things with which their minds are unequal to contend.
XXIX. Wherefore, as I before said, the philosophers have all one method
of cure, so that we need say nothing about what sort of thing that is
which 154disturbs the mind, but we must speak only concerning the
perturbation itself. Thus, first, with regard to desire itself, when the
business is only to remove that, the inquiry is not to be, whether that
thing be good or evil which provokes lust, but the lust itself is to be
removed; so that whether whatever is honest is the chief good, or
whether it consists in pleasure, or in both these things together, or in
the other three kinds of goods, yet should there be in any one too
vehement an appetite for even virtue itself, the whole discourse should
be directed to the deterring him from that vehemence. But human nature,
when placed in a conspicuous point of view, gives us every argument for
appeasing the mind, and, to make this the more distinct, the laws and
conditions of life should be explained in our discourse. Therefore, it
was not without reason that Socrates is reported, when Euripides was
exhibiting his play called Orestes, to have repeated the first three
verses of that tragedy—
What tragic story men can mournful tell,
Whate’er from fate or from the gods befell,
That human nature can support—
52
But, in order to persuade those to whom any misfortune has happened that
they can and ought to bear it, it is very useful to set before them an
enumeration of other persons who have borne similar calamities. Indeed,
the method of appeasing grief was explained in my dispute of yesterday,
and in my book on Consolation, which I wrote in the midst of my own
grief; for I was not myself so wise a man as to be insensible to grief,
and I used this, notwithstanding Chrysippus’s advice to the contrary,
who is against applying a medicine to the agitations of the mind while
they are fresh; but I did it, and committed a violence on nature, that
the greatness of my grief might give way to the greatness of the
medicine.
XXX. But fear borders upon grief, of which I have already said enough;
but I must say a little more on that. Now, as grief proceeds from what
is present, so does fear 155from future evil; so that some have said that
fear is a certain part of grief: others have called fear the harbinger
of trouble, which, as it were, introduces the ensuing evil. Now, the
reasons that make what is present supportable, make what is to come very
contemptible; for, with regard to both, we should take care to do
nothing low or grovelling, soft or effeminate, mean or abject. But,
notwithstanding we should speak of the inconstancy, imbecility, and
levity of fear itself, yet it is of very great service to speak
contemptuously of those very things of which we are afraid. So that it
fell out very well, whether it was by accident or design, that I
disputed the first and second day on death and pain—the two things that
are the most dreaded: now, if what I then said was approved of, we are
in a great degree freed from fear. And this is sufficient, as far as
regards the opinion of evils.
XXXI. Proceed we now to what are goods—that is to say, to joy and
desire. To me, indeed, one thing alone seems to embrace the question of
all that relates to the perturbations of the mind—the fact, namely,
that all perturbations are in our own power; that they are taken up upon
opinion, and are voluntary. This error, then, must be got rid of; this
opinion must be removed; and, as with regard to imagined evils, we are
to make them more supportable, so with respect to goods, we are to
lessen the violent effects of those things which are called great and
joyous. But one thing is to be observed, that equally relates both to
good and evil: that, should it be difficult to persuade any one that
none of those things which disturb the mind are to be looked on as good
or evil, yet a different cure is to be applied to different feelings;
and the malevolent person is to be corrected by one way of reasoning,
the lover by another, the anxious man by another, and the fearful by
another: and it would be easy for any one who pursues the best approved
method of reasoning, with regard to good and evil, to maintain that no
fool can be affected with joy, as he never can have anything good. But,
at present, my discourse proceeds upon the common received notions. Let,
then, honors, riches, pleasures, and the rest be the very good things
which they are imagined to be; yet a too elevated and exulting joy on
the possession 156of them is unbecoming; just as, though it might be
allowable to laugh, to giggle would be indecent. Thus, a mind enlarged
by joy is as blamable as a contraction of it by grief; and eager longing
is a sign of as much levity in desiring as immoderate joy is in
possessing; and, as those who are too dejected are said to be
effeminate, so they who are too elated with joy are properly called
volatile; and as feeling envy is a part of grief, and the being pleased
with another’s misfortune is a kind of joy, both these feelings are
usually corrected by showing the wildness and insensibility of them: and
as it becomes a man to be cautious, but it is unbecoming in him to be
fearful, so to be pleased is proper, but to be joyful improper. I have,
in order that I might be the better understood, distinguished pleasure
from joy. I have already said above, that a contraction of the mind can
never be right, but that an elation of it may; for the joy of Hector in
Nævius is one thing—
’Tis joy indeed to hear my praises sung
By you, who are the theme of honor’s tongue—
but that of the character in Trabea another: “The kind procuress,
allured by my money, will observe my nod, will watch my desires, and
study my will. If I but move the door with my little finger, instantly
it flies open; and if Chrysis should unexpectedly discover me, she will
run with joy to meet me, and throw herself into my arms.”
Now he will tell you how excellent he thinks this:
Not even fortune herself is so fortunate.
XXXII. Any one who attends the least to the subject will be convinced
how unbecoming this joy is. And as they are very shameful who are
immoderately delighted with the enjoyment of venereal pleasures, so are
they very scandalous who lust vehemently after them. And all that which
is commonly called love (and, believe me, I can find out no other name
to call it by) is of such a trivial nature that nothing, I think, is to
be compared to it: of which Cæcilius says,
I hold the man of every sense bereaved
Who grants not Love to be of Gods the chief:
157Whose mighty power whate’er is good effects,
Who gives to each his beauty and defects:
Hence, health and sickness; wit and folly, hence,
The God that love and hatred doth dispense!
An excellent corrector of life this same poetry, which thinks that love,
the promoter of debauchery and vanity, should have a place in the
council of the Gods! I am speaking of comedy, which could not subsist at
all without our approving of these debaucheries. But what said that
chief of the Argonauts in tragedy?
My life I owe to honor less than love.
What, then, are we to say of this love of Medea?—what a train of
miseries did it occasion! And yet the same woman has the assurance to
say to her father, in another poet, that she had a husband
Dearer by love than ever fathers were.
XXXIII. However, we may allow the poets to trifle, in whose fables we
see Jupiter himself engaged in these debaucheries: but let us apply to
the masters of virtue—the philosophers who deny love to be anything
carnal; and in this they differ from Epicurus, who, I think, is not much
mistaken. For what is that love of friendship? How comes it that no one
is in love with a deformed young man, or a handsome old one? I am of
opinion that this love of men had its rise from the Gymnastics of the
Greeks, where these kinds of loves are admissible and permitted;
therefore Ennius spoke well:
The censure of this crime to those is due
Who naked bodies first exposed to view.
Now, supposing them chaste, which I think is hardly possible, they are
uneasy and distressed, and the more so because they contain and refrain
themselves. But, to pass over the love of women, where nature has
allowed more liberty, who can misunderstand the poets in their rape of
Ganymede, or not apprehend what Laius says, and what he desires, in
Euripides? Lastly, what have the principal poets and the most learned
men published of themselves in their poems and songs? What doth Alcæus,
who was 158distinguished in his own republic for his bravery, write on the
love of young men? And as for Anacreon’s poetry, it is wholly on love.
But Ibycus of Rhegium appears, from his writings, to have had this love
stronger on him than all the rest.
XXXIV. Now we see that the loves of all these writers were entirely
libidinous. There have arisen also some among us philosophers (and Plato
is at the head of them, whom Dicæarchus blames not without reason) who
have countenanced love. The Stoics, in truth, say, not only that their
wise man may be a lover, but they even define love itself as an endeavor
to originate friendship out of the appearance of beauty. Now, provided
there is any one in the nature of things without desire, without care,
without a sigh, such a one may be a lover; for he is free from all lust:
but I have nothing to say to him, as it is lust of which I am now
speaking. But should there be any love—as there certainly is—which is
but little, or perhaps not at all, short of madness, such as his is in
the Leucadia—
Should there be any God whose care I am—
it is incumbent on all the Gods to see that he enjoys his amorous
pleasure.
Wretch that I am!
Nothing is more true, and he says very appropriately,
What, are you sane, who at this rate lament?
He seems even to his friends to be out of his senses: then how tragical
he becomes!
Thy aid, divine Apollo, I implore,
And thine, dread ruler of the wat’ry store!
Oh! all ye winds, assist me!
He thinks that the whole world ought to apply itself to help his love:
he excludes Venus alone, as unkind to him.
Thy aid, O Venus, why should I invoke?
He thinks Venus too much employed in her own lust to have regard to
anything else, as if he himself had not said and committed these
shameful things from lust.
159XXXV. Now, the cure for one who is affected in this manner is to show
how light, how contemptible, how very trifling he is in what he desires;
how he may turn his affections to another object, or accomplish his
desires by some other means; or else to persuade him that he may
entirely disregard it: sometimes he is to be led away to objects of
another kind, to study, business, or other different engagements and
concerns: very often the cure is effected by change of place, as sick
people, that have not recovered their strength, are benefited by change
of air. Some people think an old love may be driven out by a new one, as
one nail drives out another: but, above all things, the man thus
afflicted should be advised what madness love is: for of all the
perturbations of the mind, there is not one which is more vehement; for
(without charging it with rapes, debaucheries, adultery, or even incest,
the baseness of any of these being very blamable; not, I say, to mention
these) the very perturbation of the mind in love is base of itself, for,
to pass over all its acts of downright madness, what weakness do not
those very things which are looked upon as indifferent argue?
Affronts and jealousies, jars, squabbles, wars,
Then peace again. The man who seeks to fix
These restless feelings, and to subjugate
Them to some regular law, is just as wise
As one who’d try to lay down rules by which
Men should go mad.
53
Now, is not this inconstancy and mutability of mind enough to deter any
one by its own deformity? We are to demonstrate, as was said of every
perturbation, that there are no such feelings which do not consist
entirely of opinion and judgment, and are not owing to ourselves. For if
love were natural, all would be in love, and always so, and all love the
same object; nor would one be deterred by shame, another by reflection,
another by satiety.
XXXVI. Anger, too, when it disturbs the mind any time, leaves no room to
doubt its being madness: by the 160instigation of which we see such
contention as this between brothers:
Where was there ever impudence like thine?
Who on thy malice ever could refine?
54
You know what follows: for abuses are thrown out by these brothers with
great bitterness in every other verse; so that you may easily know them
for the sons of Atreus, of that Atreus who invented a new punishment for
his brother:
I who his cruel heart to gall am bent,
Some new, unheard-of torment must invent.
Now, what were these inventions? Hear Thyestes:
My impious brother fain would have me eat
My children, and thus serves them up for meat.
To what length now will not anger go? even as far as madness. Therefore
we say, properly enough, that angry men have given up their power, that
is, they are out of the power of advice, reason, and understanding; for
these ought to have power over the whole mind. Now, you should put those
out of the way whom they endeavor to attack till they have recollected
themselves; but what does recollection here imply but getting together
again the dispersed parts of their mind into their proper place? or else
you must beg and entreat them, if they have the means of revenge, to
defer it to another opportunity, till their anger cools. But the
expression of cooling implies, certainly, that there was a heat raised
in their minds in opposition to reason; from which consideration that
saying of Archytas is commended, who being somewhat provoked at his
steward, “How would I have treated you,” said he, “if I had not been in
a passion?”
XXXVII. Where, then, are they who say that anger has its use? Can
madness be of any use? But still it is natural. Can anything be natural
that is against reason? or how is it, if anger is natural, that one
person is more inclined to anger than another? or that the lust of
revenge should cease before it has revenged itself? or that any one
161should repent of what he had done in a passion? as we see that
Alexander the king did, who could scarcely keep his hands from himself,
when he had killed his favorite Clytus, so great was his compunction.
Now who that is acquainted with these instances can doubt that this
motion of the mind is altogether in opinion and voluntary? for who can
doubt that disorders of the mind, such as covetousness and a desire of
glory, arise from a great estimation of those things by which the mind
is disordered? from whence we may understand that every perturbation of
the mind is founded in opinion. And if boldness—that is to say, a firm
assurance of mind—is a kind of knowledge and serious opinion not
hastily taken up, then diffidence is a fear of an expected and impending
evil; and if hope is an expectation of good, fear must, of course, be an
expectation of evil. Thus fear and other perturbations are evils.
Therefore, as constancy proceeds from knowledge, so does perturbation
from error. Now, they who are said to be naturally inclined to anger, or
to pity, or to envy, or to any feeling of this kind, their minds are
constitutionally, as it were, in bad health; yet they are curable, as
the disposition of Socrates is said to have been; for when Zopyrus, who
professed to know the character of every one from his person, had heaped
a great many vices on him in a public assembly, he was laughed at by
others, who could perceive no such vices in Socrates; but Socrates kept
him in countenance by declaring that such vices were natural to him, but
that he had got the better of them by his reason. Therefore, as any one
who has the appearance of the best constitution may yet appear to be
naturally rather inclined to some particular disorder, so different
minds may be more particularly inclined to different diseases. But as to
those men who are said to be vicious, not by nature, but their own
fault, their vices proceed from wrong opinions of good and bad things,
so that one is more prone than another to different motions and
perturbations. But, just as it is in the case of the body, an inveterate
disease is harder to be got rid of than a sudden disorder; and it is
more easy to cure a fresh tumor in the eyes than to remove a defluxion
of any continuance.
XXXVIII. But as the cause of perturbations is now discovered, 162for all
of them arise from the judgment or opinion, or volition, I shall put an
end to this discourse. But we ought to be assured, since the boundaries
of good and evil are now discovered, as far as they are discoverable by
man, that nothing can be desired of philosophy greater or more useful
than the discussions which we have held these four days. For besides
instilling a contempt of death, and relieving pain so as to enable men
to bear it, we have added the appeasing of grief, than which there is no
greater evil to man. For though every perturbation of mind is grievous,
and differs but little from madness, yet we are used to say of others
when they are under any perturbation, as of fear, joy, or desire, that
they are agitated and disturbed; but of those who give themselves up to
grief, that they are miserable, afflicted, wretched, unhappy. So that it
doth not seem to be by accident, but with reason proposed by you, that I
should discuss grief, and the other perturbations separately; for there
lies the spring and head of all our miseries; but the cure of grief, and
of other disorders, is one and the same in that they are all voluntary,
and founded on opinion; we take them on ourselves because it seems right
so to do. Philosophy undertakes to eradicate this error, as the root of
all our evils: let us therefore surrender ourselves to be instructed by
it, and suffer ourselves to be cured; for while these evils have
possession of us, we not only cannot be happy, but cannot be right in
our minds. We must either deny that reason can effect anything, while,
on the other hand, nothing can be done right without reason, or else,
since philosophy depends on the deductions of reason, we must seek from
her, if we would be good or happy, every help and assistance for living
well and happily.
163BOOK V.
WHETHER VIRTUE ALONE BE SUFFICIENT FOR A HAPPY LIFE.
I.
This fifth day, Brutus, shall put an end to our Tusculan
Disputations: on which day we discussed your favorite subject. For I
perceive from that book which you wrote for me with the greatest
accuracy, as well as from your frequent conversation, that you are
clearly of this opinion, that virtue is of itself sufficient for a happy
life: and though it may be difficult to prove this, on account of the
many various strokes of fortune, yet it is a truth of such a nature that
we should endeavor to facilitate the proof of it. For among all the
topics of philosophy, there is not one of more dignity or importance.
For as the first philosophers must have had some inducement to neglect
everything for the search of the best state of life: surely, the
inducement must have been the hope of living happily, which impelled
them to devote so much care and pains to that study. Now, if virtue was
discovered and carried to perfection by them, and if virtue is a
sufficient security for a happy life, who can avoid thinking the work of
philosophizing excellently recommended by them, and undertaken by me?
But if virtue, as being subject to such various and uncertain accidents,
were but the slave of fortune, and were not of sufficient ability to
support herself, I am afraid that it would seem desirable rather to
offer up prayers, than to rely on our own confidence in virtue as the
foundation for our hope of a happy life. And, indeed, when I reflect on
those troubles with which I have been so severely exercised by fortune,
I begin to distrust this opinion; and sometimes even to dread the
weakness and frailty of human nature, for I am afraid lest, when nature
had given us infirm bodies, and had joined to them incurable diseases
and intolerable pains, she perhaps also gave us minds participating in
these bodily pains, and harassed
164also with troubles and uneasinesses,
peculiarly their own. But here I correct myself for forming my judgment
of the power of virtue more from the weakness of others, or of myself
perhaps, than from virtue itself: for she herself (provided there is
such a thing as virtue; and your uncle Brutus has removed all doubt of
it) has everything that can befall mankind in subjection to her; and by
disregarding such things, she is far removed from being at all concerned
at human accidents; and, being free from every imperfection, she thinks
that nothing which is external to herself can concern her. But we, who
increase every approaching evil by our fear, and every present one by
our grief, choose rather to condemn the nature of things than our own
errors.
II. But the amendment of this fault, and of all our other vices and
offences, is to be sought for in philosophy: and as my own inclination
and desire led me, from my earliest youth upward, to seek her
protection, so, under my present misfortunes, I have had recourse to the
same port from whence I set out, after having been tossed by a violent
tempest. O Philosophy, thou guide of life! thou discoverer of virtue and
expeller of vices! what had not only I myself, but the whole life of
man, been without you? To you it is that we owe the origin of cities;
you it was who called together the dispersed race of men into social
life; you united them together, first, by placing them near one another,
then by marriages, and lastly, by the communication of speech and
languages. You have been the inventress of laws; you have been our
instructress in morals and discipline; to you we fly for refuge; from
you we implore assistance; and as I formerly submitted to you in a great
degree, so now I surrender up myself entirely to you. For one day spent
well, and agreeably to your precepts, is preferable to an eternity of
error. Whose assistance, then, can be of more service to me than yours,
when you have bestowed on us tranquillity of life, and removed the fear
of death? But Philosophy is so far from being praised as much as she has
deserved by mankind, that she is wholly neglected by most men, and
actually evil spoken of by many. Can any person speak ill of the parent
of life, and dare to pollute himself thus with parricide, and be so
impiously
165ungrateful as to accuse her whom he ought to reverence, even
were he less able to appreciate the advantages which he might derive
from her? But this error, I imagine, and this darkness has spread itself
over the minds of ignorant men, from their not being able to look so far
back, and from their not imagining that those men by whom human life was
first improved were philosophers; for though we see philosophy to have
been of long standing, yet the name must be acknowledged to be but
modern.
III. But, indeed, who can dispute the antiquity of philosophy, either in
fact or name? For it acquired this excellent name from the ancients, by
the knowledge of the origin and causes of everything, both divine and
human. Thus those seven
ОЈбЅ№П†ОїО№, as they were considered and called by the
Greeks, have always been esteemed and called wise men by us; and thus
Lycurgus many ages before, in whose time, before the building of this
city, Homer is said to have lived, as well as Ulysses and Nestor in the
heroic ages, are all handed down to us by tradition as having really
been what they were called, wise men; nor would it have been said that
Atlas supported the heavens, or that Prometheus was bound to Caucasus,
nor would Cepheus, with his wife, his son-in-law, and his daughter have
been enrolled among the constellations, but that their more than human
knowledge of the heavenly bodies had transferred their names into an
erroneous fable. From whence all who occupied themselves in the
contemplation of nature were both considered and called wise men; and
that name of theirs continued to the age of Pythagoras, who is reported
to have gone to Phlius, as we find it stated by Heraclides Ponticus, a
very learned man, and a pupil of Plato, and to have discoursed very
learnedly and copiously on certain subjects with Leon, prince of the
Phliasii; and when Leon, admiring his ingenuity and eloquence, asked him
what art he particularly professed, his answer was, that he was
acquainted with no art, but that he was a philosopher. Leon, surprised
at the novelty of the name, inquired what he meant by the name of
philosopher, and in what philosophers differed from other men; on which
Pythagoras replied, “That the life of man seemed to him to resemble
those games which were celebrated with the
166greatest possible variety of
sports and the general concourse of all Greece. For as in those games
there were some persons whose object was glory and the honor of a crown,
to be attained by the performance of bodily exercises, so others were
led thither by the gain of buying and selling, and mere views of profit;
but there was likewise one class of persons, and they were by far the
best, whose aim was neither applause nor profit, but who came merely as
spectators through curiosity, to observe what was done, and to see in
what manner things were carried on there. And thus, said he, we come
from another life and nature unto this one, just as men come out of some
other city, to some much frequented mart; some being slaves to glory,
others to money; and there are some few who, taking no account of
anything else, earnestly look into the nature of things; and these men
call themselves studious of wisdom, that is, philosophers: and as there
it is the most reputable occupation of all to be a looker-on without
making any acquisition, so in life, the contemplating things, and
acquainting one’s self with them, greatly exceeds every other pursuit of
life.”
IV. Nor was Pythagoras the inventor only of the name, but he enlarged
also the thing itself, and, when he came into Italy after this
conversation at Phlius, he adorned that Greece, which is called Great
Greece, both privately and publicly, with the most excellent
institutions and arts; but of his school and system I shall, perhaps,
find another opportunity to speak. But numbers and motions, and the
beginning and end of all things, were the subjects of the ancient
philosophy down to Socrates, who was a pupil of Archelaus, who had been
the disciple of Anaxagoras. These made diligent inquiry into the
magnitude of the stars, their distances, courses, and all that relates
to the heavens. But Socrates was the first who brought down philosophy
from the heavens, placed it in cities, introduced it into families, and
obliged it to examine into life and morals, and good and evil. And his
different methods of discussing questions, together with the variety of
his topics, and the greatness of his abilities, being immortalized by
the memory and writings of Plato, gave rise to many sects of
philosophers of different sentiments, of all which I have principally
adhered
167to that one which, in my opinion, Socrates himself followed;
and argue so as to conceal my own opinion, while I deliver others from
their errors, and so discover what has the greatest appearance of
probability in every question. And the custom Carneades adopted with
great copiousness and acuteness, and I myself have often given in to it
on many occasions elsewhere, and in this manner, too, I disputed lately,
in my Tusculan villa; indeed, I have sent you a book of the four former
days’ discussions; but the fifth day, when we had seated ourselves as
before, what we were to dispute on was proposed thus:
V.
A. I do not think virtue can possibly be sufficient for a happy
life.
M. But my friend Brutus thinks so, whose judgment, with submission, I
greatly prefer to yours.
A. I make no doubt of it; but your regard for him is not the business
now: the question is now, what is the real character of that quality of
which I have declared my opinion. I wish you to dispute on that.
M. What! do you deny that virtue can possibly be sufficient for a
happy life?
A. It is what I entirely deny.
M. What! is not virtue sufficient to enable us to live as we ought,
honestly, commendably, or, in fine, to live well?
A. Certainly sufficient.
M. Can you, then, help calling any one miserable who lives ill? or
will you deny that any one who you allow lives well must inevitably live
happily?
A. Why may I not? for a man may be upright in his life, honest,
praiseworthy, even in the midst of torments, and therefore live well.
Provided you understand what I mean by well; for when I say well, I mean
with constancy, and dignity, and wisdom, and courage; for a man may
display all these qualities on the rack; but yet the rack is
inconsistent with a happy life.
M. What, then? is your happy life left on the outside of the prison,
while constancy, dignity, wisdom, and the other virtues, are surrendered
up to the executioner, and bear punishment and pain without reluctance?
A. You must look out for something new if you would
168do any good.
These things have very little effect on me, not merely from their being
common, but principally because, like certain light wines that will not
bear water, these arguments of the Stoics are pleasanter to taste than
to swallow. As when that assemblage of virtues is committed to the rack,
it raises so reverend a spectacle before our eyes that happiness seems
to hasten on towards them, and not to suffer them to be deserted by her.
But when you take your attention off from this picture and these images
of the virtues to the truth and the reality, what remains without
disguise is, the question whether any one can be happy in torment?
Wherefore let us now examine that point, and not be under any
apprehensions, lest the virtues should expostulate, and complain that
they are forsaken by happiness. For if prudence is connected with every
virtue, then prudence itself discovers this, that all good men are not
therefore happy; and she recollects many things of Marcus Atilius
55,
Quintus Cæpio
56, Marcus Aquilius
57; and prudence herself, if these
representations are more agreeable to you than the things themselves,
restrains happiness when it is endeavoring to throw itself into
torments, and denies that it has any connection with pain and torture.
VI.
M. I can easily bear with your behaving in this manner, though it
is not fair in you to prescribe to me how you would have me carry on
this discussion. But I ask you if I have effected anything or nothing in
the preceding days?
A. Yes; something was done, some little matter indeed.
M. But if that is the case, this question is settled, and almost put
an end to.
A. How so?
M. Because turbulent motions and violent agitations of
169the mind, when
it is raised and elated by a rash impulse, getting the better of reason,
leave no room for a happy life. For who that fears either pain or death,
the one of which is always present, the other always impending, can be
otherwise than miserable? Now, supposing the same person—which is often
the case—to be afraid of poverty, ignominy, infamy, or weakness, or
blindness, or, lastly, slavery, which doth not only befall individual
men, but often even the most powerful nations; now can any one under the
apprehension of these evils be happy? What shall we say of him who not
only dreads these evils as impending, but actually feels and bears them
at present? Let us unite in the same person banishment, mourning, the
loss of children; now, how can any one who is broken down and rendered
sick in body and mind by such affliction be otherwise than very
miserable indeed? What reason, again, can there be why a man should not
rightly enough be called miserable whom we see inflamed and raging with
lust, coveting everything with an insatiable desire, and, in proportion
as he derives more pleasure from anything, thirsting the more violently
after them? And as to a man vainly elated, exulting with an empty joy,
and boasting of himself without reason, is not he so much the more
miserable in proportion as he thinks himself happier? Therefore, as
these men are miserable, so, on the other hand, those are happy who are
alarmed by no fears, wasted by no griefs, provoked by no lusts, melted
by no languid pleasures that arise from vain and exulting joys. We look
on the sea as calm when not the least breath of air disturbs its waves;
and, in like manner, the placid and quiet state of the mind is
discovered when unmoved by any perturbation. Now, if there be any one
who holds the power of fortune, and everything human, everything that
can possibly befall any man, as supportable, so as to be out of the
reach of fear or anxiety, and if such a man covets nothing, and is
lifted up by no vain joy of mind, what can prevent his being happy? And
if these are the effects of virtue, why cannot virtue itself make men
happy?
VII.
A. But the other of these two propositions is undeniable, that
they who are under no apprehensions, who are
170noways uneasy, who covet
nothing, who are lifted up by no vain joy, are happy: and therefore I
grant you that. But as for the other, that is not now in a fit state for
discussion; for it has been proved by your former arguments that a wise
man is free from every perturbation of mind.
M. Doubtless, then, the dispute is over; for the question appears to
have been entirely exhausted.
A. I think, indeed, that that is almost the case.
M. But yet that is more usually the case with the mathematicians than
philosophers. For when the geometricians teach anything, if what they
have before taught relates to their present subject, they take that for
granted which has been already proved, and explain only what they had
not written on before. But the philosophers, whatever subject they have
in hand, get together everything that relates to it, notwithstanding
they may have dilated on it somewhere else. Were not that the case, why
should the Stoics say so much on that question, Whether virtue was
abundantly sufficient to a happy life? when it would have been answer
enough that they had before taught that nothing was good but what was
honorable; for, as this had been proved, the consequence must be that
virtue was sufficient to a happy life; and each premise may be made to
follow from the admission of the other, so that if it be admitted that
virtue is sufficient to secure a happy life, it may also be inferred
that nothing is good except what is honorable. They, however, do not
proceed in this manner; for they would separate books about what is
honorable, and what is the chief good; and when they have demonstrated
from the one that virtue has power enough to make life happy, yet they
treat this point separately; for everything, and especially a subject of
such great consequence, should be supported by arguments and
exhortations which belong to that alone. For you should have a care how
you imagine philosophy to have uttered anything more noble, or that she
has promised anything more fruitful or of greater consequence, for, good
Gods! doth she not engage that she will render him who submits to her
laws so accomplished as to be always armed against fortune, and to have
every assurance within himself of living well and happily—that he
shall, in short, be forever
171happy? But let us see what she will
perform? In the mean while, I look upon it as a great thing that she has
even made such a promise. For Xerxes, who was loaded with all the
rewards and gifts of fortune, not satisfied with his armies of horse and
foot, nor the multitude of his ships, nor his infinite treasure of gold,
offered a reward to any one who could find out a new pleasure; and yet,
when it was discovered, he was not satisfied with it; nor can there ever
be an end to lust. I wish we could engage any one by a reward to produce
something the better to establish us in this belief.
VIII.
A. I wish that, indeed, myself; but I want a little information.
For I allow that in what you have stated the one proposition is the
consequence of the other; that as, if what is honorable be the only
good, it must follow that a happy life is the effect of virtue: so that
if a happy life consists in virtue, nothing can be good but virtue. But
your friend Brutus, on the authority of Aristo and Antiochus, does not
see this; for he thinks the case would be the same even if there were
anything good besides virtue.
M. What, then? do you imagine that I am going to argue against Brutus?
A. You may do what you please; for it is not for me to prescribe what
you shall do.
M. How these things agree together shall be examined somewhere else;
for I frequently discussed that point with Antiochus, and lately with
Aristo, when, during the period of my command as general, I was lodging
with him at Athens. For to me it seemed that no one could possibly be
happy under any evil; but a wise man might be afflicted with evil, if
there are any things arising from body or fortune deserving the name of
evils. These things were said, which Antiochus has inserted in his books
in many places—that virtue itself was sufficient to make life happy,
but yet not perfectly happy; and that many things derive their names
from the predominant portion of them, though they do not include
everything, as strength, health, riches, honor, and glory: which
qualities are determined by their kind, not their number. Thus a happy
life is so called from its being so in a great degree, even though it
172should fall short in some point. To clear this up is not absolutely
necessary at present, though it seems to be said without any great
consistency; for I cannot imagine what is wanting to one that is happy
to make him happier, for if anything be wanting to him, he cannot be so
much as happy; and as to what they say, that everything is named and
estimated from its predominant portion, that may be admitted in some
things. But when they allow three kinds of evils—when any one is
oppressed with every imaginable evil of two kinds, being afflicted with
adverse fortune, and having at the same time his body worn out and
harassed with all sorts of pains—shall we say that such a one is but
little short of a happy life, to say nothing about the happiest possible
life?
IX. This is the point which Theophrastus was unable to maintain; for
after he had once laid down the position that stripes, torments,
tortures, the ruin of one’s country, banishment, the loss of children,
had great influence on men’s living miserably and unhappily, he durst
not any longer use any high and lofty expressions when he was so low and
abject in his opinion. How right he was is not the question; he
certainly was consistent. Therefore, I am not for objecting to
consequences where the premises are admitted. But this most elegant and
learned of all the philosophers is not taken to task very severely when
he asserts his three kinds of good; but he is attacked by every one for
that book which he wrote on a happy life, in which book he has many
arguments why one who is tortured and racked cannot be happy. For in
that book he is supposed to say that a man who is placed on the wheel
(that is a kind of torture in use among the Greeks) cannot attain to a
completely happy life. He nowhere, indeed, says so absolutely; but what
he says amounts to the same thing. Can I, then, find fault with him,
after having allowed that pains of the body are evils, that the ruin of
a man’s fortunes is an evil, if he should say that every good man is not
happy, when all those things which he reckons as evils may befall a good
man? The same Theophrastus is found fault with by all the books and
schools of the philosophers for commending that sentence in his
Callisthenes,
Fortune, not wisdom, rules the life of man.
173They say never did philosopher assert anything so languid. They are
right, indeed, in that; but I do not apprehend anything could be more
consistent, for if there are so many good things that depend on the
body, and so many foreign to it that depend on chance and fortune, is it
inconsistent to say that fortune, which governs everything, both what is
foreign and what belongs to the body, has greater power than counsel. Or
would we rather imitate Epicurus? who is often excellent in many things
which he speaks, but quite indifferent how consistent he may be, or how
much to the purpose he is speaking. He commends spare diet, and in that
he speaks as a philosopher; but it is for Socrates or Antisthenes to say
so, and not for one who confines all good to pleasure. He denies that
any one can live pleasantly unless he lives honestly, wisely, and
justly. Nothing is more dignified than this assertion, nothing more
becoming a philosopher, had he not measured this very expression of
living honestly, justly, and wisely by pleasure. What could be better
than to assert that fortune interferes but little with a wise man? But
does he talk thus, who, after he has said that pain is the greatest
evil, or the only evil, might himself be afflicted with the sharpest
pains all over his body, even at the time he is vaunting himself the
most against fortune? And this very thing, too, Metrodorus has said, but
in better language: “I have anticipated you, Fortune; I have caught you,
and cut off every access, so that you cannot possibly reach me.” This
would be excellent in the mouth of Aristo the Chian, or Zeno the Stoic,
who held nothing to be an evil but what was base; but for you,
Metrodorus, to anticipate the approaches of fortune, who confine all
that is good to your bowels and marrow—for you to say so, who define
the chief good by a strong constitution of body, and well-assured hope
of its continuance—for you to cut off every access of fortune! Why, you
may instantly be deprived of that good. Yet the simple are taken with
these propositions, and a vast crowd is led away by such sentences to
become their followers.
X. But it is the duty of one who would argue accurately to consider not
what is said, but what is said consistently. 174As in that very opinion
which we have adopted in this discussion, namely, that every good man is
always happy, it is clear what I mean by good men: I call those both
wise and good men who are provided and adorned with every virtue. Let us
see, then, who are to be called happy. I imagine, indeed, that those men
are to be called so who are possessed of good without any alloy of evil;
nor is there any other notion connected with the word that expresses
happiness but an absolute enjoyment of good without any evil. Virtue
cannot attain this, if there is anything good besides itself. For a
crowd of evils would present themselves, if we were to allow poverty,
obscurity, humility, solitude, the loss of friends, acute pains of the
body, the loss of health, weakness, blindness, the ruin of one’s
country, banishment, slavery, to be evils; for a wise man may be
afflicted by all these evils, numerous and important as they are, and
many others also may be added, for they are brought on by chance, which
may attack a wise man; but if these things are evils, who can maintain
that a wise man is always happy when all these evils may light on him at
the same time? I therefore do not easily agree with my friend Brutus,
nor with our common masters, nor those ancient ones, Aristotle,
Speusippus, Xenocrates, Polemon, who reckon all that I have mentioned
above as evils, and yet they say that a wise man is always happy; nor
can I allow them, because they are charmed with this beautiful and
illustrious title, which would very well become Pythagoras, Socrates,
and Plato, to persuade my mind that strength, health, beauty, riches,
honors, power, with the beauty of which they are ravished, are
contemptible, and that all those things which are the opposites of these
are not to be regarded. Then might they declare openly, with a loud
voice, that neither the attacks of fortune, nor the opinion of the
multitude, nor pain, nor poverty, occasions them any apprehensions; and
that they have everything within themselves, and that there is nothing
whatever which they consider as good but what is within their own power.
Nor can I by any means allow the same person who falls into the vulgar
opinion of good and evil to make use of these expressions, which can
only become 175a great and exalted man. Struck with which glory, up starts
Epicurus, who, with submission to the Gods, thinks a wise man always
happy. He is much charmed with the dignity of this opinion, but he never
would have owned that, had he attended to himself; for what is there
more inconsistent than for one who could say that pain was the greatest
or the only evil to think also that a wise man can possibly say in the
midst of his torture, How sweet is this! We are not, therefore, to form
our judgment of philosophers from detached sentences, but from their
consistency with themselves, and their ordinary manner of talking.
XI. A. You compel me to be of your opinion; but have a care that you
are not inconsistent yourself.
M. In what respect?
A. Because I have lately read your fourth book on Good and Evil: and
in that you appeared to me, while disputing against Cato, to be
endeavoring to show, which in my opinion means to prove, that Zeno and
the Peripatetics differ only about some new words; but if we allow that,
what reason can there be, if it follows from the arguments of Zeno that
virtue contains all that is necessary to a happy life, that the
Peripatetics should not be at liberty to say the same? For, in my
opinion, regard should be had to the thing, not to words.
M. What! you would convict me from my own words, and bring against me
what I had said or written elsewhere. You may act in that manner with
those who dispute by established rules. We live from hand to mouth, and
say anything that strikes our mind with probability, so that we are the
only people who are really at liberty. But, since I just now spoke of
consistency, I do not think the inquiry in this place is, if the opinion
of Zeno and his pupil Aristo be true that nothing is good but what is
honorable; but, admitting that, then, whether the whole of a happy life
can be rested on virtue alone. Wherefore, if we certainly grant Brutus
this, that a wise man is always happy, how consistent he is, is his own
business; for who, indeed, is more worthy than himself of the glory of
that opinion? Still, we may maintain that such a man is more happy than
any one else.
176XII. Though Zeno the Cittiæan, a stranger and an inconsiderable coiner
of words, appears to have insinuated himself into the old philosophy;
still, the prevalence of this opinion is due to the authority of Plato,
who often makes use of this expression, “That nothing but virtue can be
entitled to the name of good,” agreeably to what Socrates says in
Plato’s Gorgias; for it is there related that when some one asked him if
he did not think Archelaus the son of Perdiccas, who was then looked
upon as a most fortunate person, a very happy man, “I do not know,”
replied he, “for I never conversed with him.” “What! is there no other
way you can know it by?” “None at all.” “You cannot, then, pronounce of
the great king of the Persians whether he is happy or not?” “How can I,
when I do not know how learned or how good a man he is?” “What! do you
imagine that a happy life depends on that?” “My opinion entirely is,
that good men are happy, and the wicked miserable.” “Is Archelaus, then,
miserable?” “Certainly, if unjust.” Now, does it not appear to you that
he is here placing the whole of a happy life in virtue alone? But what
does the same man say in his funeral oration? “For,” saith he, “whoever
has everything that relates to a happy life so entirely dependent on
himself as not to be connected with the good or bad fortune of another,
and not to be affected by, or made in any degree uncertain by, what
befalls another; and whoever is such a one has acquired the best rule of
living; he is that moderate, that brave, that wise man, who submits to
the gain and loss of everything, and especially of his children, and
obeys that old precept; for he will never be too joyful or too sad,
because he depends entirely upon himself.”
XIII. From Plato, therefore, all my discourse shall be deduced, as if
from some sacred and hallowed fountain. Whence can I, then, more
properly begin than from Nature, the parent of all? For whatsoever she
produces (I am not speaking only of animals, but even of those things
which have sprung from the earth in such a manner as to rest on their
own roots) she designed it to be perfect in its respective kind. So that
among trees and vines, and those lower plants and trees which cannot
advance themselves 177high above the earth, some are evergreen, others are
stripped of their leaves in winter, and, warmed by the spring season,
put them out afresh, and there are none of them but what are so
quickened by a certain interior motion, and their own seeds enclosed in
every one, so as to yield flowers, fruit, or berries, that all may have
every perfection that belongs to it; provided no violence prevents it.
But the force of Nature itself may be more easily discovered in animals,
as she has bestowed sense on them. For some animals she has taught to
swim, and designed to be inhabitants of the water; others she has
enabled to fly, and has willed that they should enjoy the boundless air;
some others she has made to creep, others to walk. Again, of these very
animals, some are solitary, some gregarious, some wild, others tame,
some hidden and buried beneath the earth, and every one of these
maintains the law of nature, confining itself to what was bestowed on
it, and unable to change its manner of life. And as every animal has
from nature something that distinguishes it, which every one maintains
and never quits; so man has something far more excellent, though
everything is said to be excellent by comparison. But the human mind,
being derived from the divine reason, can be compared with nothing but
with the Deity itself, if I may be allowed the expression. This, then,
if it is improved, and when its perception is so preserved as not to be
blinded by errors, becomes a perfect understanding, that is to say,
absolute reason, which is the very same as virtue. And if everything is
happy which wants nothing, and is complete and perfect in its kind, and
that is the peculiar lot of virtue, certainly all who are possessed of
virtue are happy. And in this I agree with Brutus, and also with
Aristotle, Xenocrates, Speusippus, Polemon.
XIV. To me such are the only men who appear completely happy; for what
can he want to a complete happy life who relies on his own good
qualities, or how can he be happy who does not rely on them? But he who
makes a threefold division of goods must necessarily be diffident, for
how can he depend on having a sound body, or that his fortune shall
continue? But no one can be happy without an immovable, fixed, and
permanent good. What, 178then, is this opinion of theirs? So that I think
that saying of the Spartan may be applied to them, who, on some
merchant’s boasting before him that he had despatched ships to every
maritime coast, replied that a fortune which depended on ropes was not
very desirable. Can there be any doubt that whatever may be lost cannot
be properly classed in the number of those things which complete a happy
life? for of all that constitutes a happy life, nothing will admit of
withering, or growing old, or wearing out, or decaying; for whoever is
apprehensive of any loss of these things cannot be happy: the happy man
should be safe, well fenced, well fortified, out of the reach of all
annoyance, not like a man under trifling apprehensions, but free from
all such. As he is not called innocent who but slightly offends, but he
who offends not at all, so it is he alone who is to be considered
without fear who is free from all fear, not he who is but in little
fear. For what else is courage but an affection of mind that is ready to
undergo perils, and patient in the endurance of pain and labor without
any alloy of fear? Now, this certainly could not be the case if there
were anything else good but what depended on honesty alone. But how can
any one be in possession of that desirable and much-coveted security
(for I now call a freedom from anxiety a security, on which freedom a
happy life depends) who has, or may have, a multitude of evils attending
him? How can he be brave and undaunted, and hold everything as trifles
which can befall a man? for so a wise man should do, unless he be one
who thinks that everything depends on himself. Could the Lacedæmonians
without this, when Philip threatened to prevent all their attempts, have
asked him if he could prevent their killing themselves? Is it not
easier, then, to find one man of such a spirit as we are inquiring
after, than to meet with a whole city of such men? Now, if to this
courage I am speaking of we add temperance, that it may govern all our
feelings and agitations, what can be wanting to complete his happiness
who is secured by his courage from uneasiness and fear, and is prevented
from immoderate desires and immoderate insolence of joy by temperance? I
could easily show that virtue is able to 179produce these effects, but
that I have explained on the foregoing days.
XV. But as the perturbations of the mind make life miserable, and
tranquillity renders it happy; and as these perturbations are of two
sorts, grief and fear, proceeding from imagined evils, and as immoderate
joy and lust arise from a mistake about what is good, and as all these
feelings are in opposition to reason and counsel; when you see a man at
ease, quite free and disengaged from such troublesome commotions, which
are so much at variance with one another, can you hesitate to pronounce
such a one a happy man? Now, the wise man is always in such a
disposition; therefore the wise man is always happy. Besides, every good
is pleasant; whatever is pleasant may be boasted and talked of; whatever
may be boasted of is glorious; but whatever is glorious is certainly
laudable, and whatever is laudable doubtless, also, honorable: whatever,
then, is good is honorable (but the things which they reckon as goods
they themselves do not call honorable); therefore what is honorable
alone is good. Hence it follows that a happy life is comprised in
honesty alone. Such things, then, are not to be called or considered
goods, when a man may enjoy an abundance of them, and yet be most
miserable. Is there any doubt but that a man who enjoys the best health,
and who has strength and beauty, and his senses flourishing in their
utmost quickness and perfection—suppose him likewise, if you please,
nimble and active, nay, give him riches, honors, authority, power,
glory—now, I say, should this person, who is in possession of all
these, be unjust, intemperate, timid, stupid, or an idiot—could you
hesitate to call such a one miserable? What, then, are those goods in
the possession of which you may be very miserable? Let us see if a happy
life is not made up of parts of the same nature, as a heap implies a
quantity of grain of the same kind. And if this be once admitted,
happiness must be compounded of different good things, which alone are
honorable; if there is any mixture of things of another sort with these,
nothing honorable can proceed from such a composition: now, take away
honesty, and how can you imagine anything happy? For whatever is good is
desirable on that account; whatever is desirable 180must certainly be
approved of; whatever you approve of must be looked on as acceptable and
welcome. You must consequently impute dignity to this; and if so, it
must necessarily be laudable: therefore, everything that is laudable is
good. Hence it follows that what is honorable is the only good. And
should we not look upon it in this light, there will be a great many
things which we must call good.
XVI. I forbear to mention riches, which, as any one, let him be ever so
unworthy, may have them, I do not reckon among goods; for what is good
is not attainable by all. I pass over notoriety and popular fame, raised
by the united voice of knaves and fools. Even things which are absolute
nothings may be called goods; such as white teeth, handsome eyes, a good
complexion, and what was commended by Euryclea, when she was washing
Ulysses’s feet, the softness of his skin and the mildness of his
discourse. If you look on these as goods, what greater encomiums can the
gravity of a philosopher be entitled to than the wild opinion of the
vulgar and the thoughtless crowd? The Stoics give the name of excellent
and choice to what the others call good: they call them so, indeed; but
they do not allow them to complete a happy life. But these others think
that there is no life happy without them; or, admitting it to be happy,
they deny it to be the most happy. But our opinion is, that it is the
most happy; and we prove it from that conclusion of Socrates. For thus
that author of philosophy argued: that as the disposition of a man’s
mind is, so is the man; such as the man is, such will be his discourse;
his actions will correspond with his discourse, and his life with his
actions. But the disposition of a good man’s mind is laudable; the life,
therefore, of a good man is laudable; it is honorable, therefore,
because laudable; the unavoidable conclusion from which is that the life
of good men is happy. For, good Gods! did I not make it appear, by my
former arguments—or was I only amusing myself and killing time in what
I then said?—that the mind of a wise man was always free from every
hasty motion which I call a perturbation, and that the most undisturbed
peace always reigned in his breast? A man, then, who is temperate and
consistent, free from fear or 181grief, and uninfluenced by any immoderate
joy or desire, cannot be otherwise than happy; but a wise man is always
so, therefore he is always happy. Moreover, how can a good man avoid
referring all his actions and all his feelings to the one standard of
whether or not it is laudable? But he does refer everything to the
object of living happily: it follows, then, that a happy life is
laudable; but nothing is laudable without virtue: a happy life, then, is
the consequence of virtue. And this is the unavoidable conclusion to be
drawn from these arguments.
XVII. A wicked life has nothing which we ought to speak of or glory in;
nor has that life which is neither happy nor miserable. But there is a
kind of life that admits of being spoken of, and gloried in, and boasted
of, as Epaminondas saith,
The wings of Sparta’s pride my counsels clipp’d.
And Africanus boasts,
Who, from beyond Mæotis to the place
Where the sun rises, deeds like mine can trace?
If, then, there is such a thing as a happy life, it is to be gloried in,
spoken of, and commended by the person who enjoys it; for there is
nothing excepting that which can be spoken of or gloried in; and when
that is once admitted, you know what follows. Now, unless an honorable
life is a happy life, there must, of course, be something preferable to
a happy life; for that which is honorable all men will certainly grant
to be preferable to anything else. And thus there will be something
better than a happy life: but what can be more absurd than such an
assertion? What! when they grant vice to be effectual to the rendering
life miserable, must they not admit that there is a corresponding power
in virtue to make life happy? For contraries follow from contraries. And
here I ask what weight they think there is in the balance of Critolaus,
who having put the goods of the mind into one scale, and the goods of
the body and other external advantages into the other, thought the goods
of the mind outweighed the others so far that they would require the
whole earth and sea to equalize the scale.
182XVIII. What hinders Critolaus, then, or that gravest of philosophers,
Xenocrates (who raises virtue so high, and who lessens and depreciates
everything else), from not only placing a happy life, but the happiest
possible life, in virtue? And, indeed, if this were not the case, virtue
would be absolutely lost. For whoever is subject to grief must
necessarily be subject to fear too, for fear is an uneasy apprehension
of future grief; and whoever is subject to fear is liable to dread,
timidity, consternation, cowardice. Therefore, such a person may, some
time or other, be defeated, and not think himself concerned with that
precept of Atreus,
And let men so conduct themselves in life,
As to be always strangers to defeat.
But such a man, as I have said, will be defeated; and not only defeated,
but made a slave of. But we would have virtue always free, always
invincible; and were it not so, there would be an end of virtue. But if
virtue has in herself all that is necessary for a good life, she is
certainly sufficient for happiness: virtue is certainly sufficient, too,
for our living with courage; if with courage, then with a magnanimous
spirit, and indeed so as never to be under any fear, and thus to be
always invincible. Hence it follows that there can be nothing to be
repented of, no wants, no lets or hinderances. Thus all things will be
prosperous, perfect, and as you would have them, and, consequently,
happy; but virtue is sufficient for living with courage, and therefore
virtue is able by herself to make life happy. For as folly, even when
possessed of what it desires, never thinks it has acquired enough, so
wisdom is always satisfied with the present, and never repents on her
own account.
XIX. Look but on the single consulship of Lælius, and that, too, after
having been set aside (though when a wise and good man like him is
outvoted, the people are disappointed of a good consul, rather than be
disappointed by a vain people); but the point is, would you prefer, were
it in your power, to be once such a consul as Lælius, or be elected four
times, like Cinna? I have no doubt in the world what answer you will
make, and it is on that account I put the question to you.
183I would not ask every one this question; for some one perhaps might
answer that he would not only prefer four consulates to one, but even
one day of Cinna’s life to whole ages of many famous men. Lælius would
have suffered had he but touched any one with his finger; but Cinna
ordered the head of his colleague consul, Cn. Octavius, to be struck
off; and put to death P. Crassus58, and L. Cæsar59, those excellent
men, so renowned both at home and abroad; and even M. Antonius60, the
greatest orator whom I ever heard; and C. Cæsar, who seems to me to have
been the pattern of humanity, politeness, sweetness of temper, and wit.
Could he, then, be happy who occasioned the death of these men? So far
from it, that he seems to be miserable, not only for having performed
these actions, but also for acting in such a manner that it was lawful
for him to do it, though it is unlawful for any one to do wicked
actions; but this proceeds from inaccuracy, of speech, for we call
whatever a man is allowed to do lawful. Was not Marius happier, I pray
you, when he shared the glory of the victory gained over the Cimbrians
with his colleague Catulus (who was almost another Lælius; for I look
upon the two men as very like one another), than when, conqueror in the
civil war, he in a passion answered the friends of Catulus, who were
interceding for him, “Let him die?” And this answer he gave, not once
only, but often. But in such a case, he was happier who submitted to
that barbarous decree than he who issued it. And it is better to receive
an injury than to do one; and so it was better to advance a little to
meet that death that was making its approaches, as Catulus did, than,
like Marius, to sully the glory of six consulships, and disgrace his
latter days, by the death of such a man.
XX. Dionysius exercised his tyranny over the Syracusans thirty-eight
years, being but twenty-five years old 184when he seized on the
government. How beautiful and how wealthy a city did he oppress with
slavery! And yet we have it from good authority that he was remarkably
temperate in his manner of living, that he was very active and energetic
in carrying on business, but naturally mischievous and unjust; from
which description every one who diligently inquires into truth must
inevitably see that he was very miserable. Neither did he attain what he
so greatly desired, even when he was persuaded that he had unlimited
power; for, notwithstanding he was of a good family and reputable
parents (though that is contested by some authors), and had a very large
acquaintance of intimate friends and relations, and also some youths
attached to him by ties of love after the fashion of the Greeks, he
could not trust any one of them, but committed the guard of his person
to slaves, whom he had selected from rich men’s families and made free,
and to strangers and barbarians. And thus, through an unjust desire of
governing, he in a manner shut himself up in a prison. Besides, he would
not trust his throat to a barber, but had his daughters taught to shave;
so that these royal virgins were forced to descend to the base and
slavish employment of shaving the head and beard of their father. Nor
would he trust even them, when they were grown up, with a razor; but
contrived how they might burn off the hair of his head and beard with
red-hot nutshells. And as to his two wives, Aristomache, his
countrywoman, and Doris of Locris, he never visited them at night before
everything had been well searched and examined. And as he had surrounded
the place where his bed was with a broad ditch, and made a way over it
with a wooden bridge, he drew that bridge over after shutting his
bedchamber door. And as he did not dare to stand on the ordinary pulpits
from which they usually harangued the people, he generally addressed
them from a high tower. And it is said that when he was disposed to play
at ball—for he delighted much in it—and had pulled off his clothes, he
used to give his sword into the keeping of a young man whom he was very
fond of. On this, one of his intimates said pleasantly, “You certainly
trust your life with him;” and as the young man happened to smile at
this, he ordered them both to be slain, 185the one for showing how he
might be taken off, the other for approving of what had been said by
smiling. But he was so concerned at what he had done that nothing
affected him more during his whole life; for he had slain one to whom he
was extremely partial. Thus do weak men’s desires pull them different
ways, and while they indulge one, they act counter to another.
XXI. This tyrant, however, showed himself how happy he really was; for
once, when Damocles, one of his flatterers, was dilating in conversation
on his forces, his wealth, the greatness of his power, the plenty he
enjoyed, the grandeur of his royal palaces, and maintaining that no one
was ever happier, “Have you an inclination,” said he, “Damocles, as this
kind of life pleases you, to have a taste of it yourself, and to make a
trial of the good fortune that attends me?” And when he said that he
should like it extremely, Dionysius ordered him to be laid on a bed of
gold with the most beautiful covering, embroidered and wrought with the
most exquisite work, and he dressed out a great many sideboards with
silver and embossed gold. He then ordered some youths, distinguished for
their handsome persons, to wait at his table, and to observe his nod, in
order to serve him with what he wanted. There were ointments and
garlands; perfumes were burned; tables provided with the most exquisite
meats. Damocles thought himself very happy. In the midst of this
apparatus, Dionysius ordered a bright sword to be let down from the
ceiling, suspended by a single horse-hair, so as to hang over the head
of that happy man. After which he neither cast his eye on those handsome
waiters, nor on the well-wrought plate; nor touched any of the
provisions: presently the garlands fell to pieces. At last he entreated
the tyrant to give him leave to go, for that now he had no desire to be
happy61. Does not Dionysius, then, seem to have declared there can be
no happiness for one who is under constant apprehensions? But it was not
now in his power 186to return to justice, and restore his citizens their
rights and privileges; for, by the indiscretion of youth, he had engaged
in so many wrong steps and committed such extravagances, that, had he
attempted to have returned to a right way of thinking, he must have
endangered his life.
XXII. Yet, how desirous he was of friendship, though at the same time he
dreaded the treachery of friends, appears from the story of those two
Pythagoreans: one of these had been security for his friend, who was
condemned to die; the other, to release his security, presented himself
at the time appointed for his dying: “I wish,” said Dionysius,“ you
would admit me as the third in your friendship.” What misery was it for
him to be deprived of acquaintance, of company at his table, and of the
freedom of conversation! especially for one who was a man of learning,
and from his childhood acquainted with liberal arts, very fond of music,
and himself a tragic poet—how good a one is not to the purpose, for I
know not how it is, but in this way, more than any other, every one
thinks his own performances excellent. I never as yet knew any poet (and
I was very intimate with Aquinius), who did not appear to himself to be
very admirable. The case is this: you are pleased with your own works; I
like mine. But to return to Dionysius. He debarred himself from all
civil and polite conversation, and spent his life among fugitives,
bondmen, and barbarians; for he was persuaded that no one could be his
friend who was worthy of liberty, or had the least desire of being free.
XXIII. Shall I not, then, prefer the life of Plato and Archytas,
manifestly wise and learned men, to his, than which nothing can possibly
be more horrid, or miserable, or detestable?
I will present you with an humble and obscure mathematician of the same
city, called Archimedes, who lived many years after; whose tomb,
overgrown with shrubs and briers, I in my quæstorship discovered, when
the Syracusans knew nothing of it, and even denied that there was any
such thing remaining; for I remembered some verses, which I had been
informed were engraved on his monument, and these set forth that on the
top of the tomb 187there was placed a sphere with a cylinder. When I had
carefully examined all the monuments (for there are a great many tombs
at the gate Achradinæ), I observed a small column standing out a little
above the briers, with the figure of a sphere and a cylinder upon it;
whereupon I immediately said to the Syracusans—for there were some of
their principal men with me there—that I imagined that was what I was
inquiring for. Several men, being sent in with scythes, cleared the way,
and made an opening for us. When we could get at it, and were come near
to the front of the pedestal, I found the inscription, though the latter
parts of all the verses were effaced almost half away. Thus one of the
noblest cities of Greece, and one which at one time likewise had been
very celebrated for learning, had known nothing of the monument of its
greatest genius, if it had not been discovered to them by a native of
Arpinum. But to return to the subject from which I have been digressing.
Who is there in the least degree acquainted with the Muses, that is,
with liberal knowledge, or that deals at all in learning, who would not
choose to be this mathematician rather than that tyrant? If we look into
their methods of living and their employments, we shall find the mind of
the one strengthened and improved with tracing the deductions of reason,
amused with his own ingenuity, which is the one most delicious food of
the mind; the thoughts of the other engaged in continual murders and
injuries, in constant fears by night and by day. Now imagine a
Democritus, a Pythagoras, and an Anaxagoras; what kingdom, what riches,
would you prefer to their studies and amusements? For you must
necessarily look for that excellence which we are seeking for in that
which is the most perfect part of man; but what is there better in man
than a sagacious and good mind? The enjoyment, therefore, of that good
which proceeds from that sagacious mind can alone make us happy; but
virtue is the good of the mind: it follows, therefore, that a happy life
depends on virtue. Hence proceed all things that are beautiful,
honorable, and excellent, as I said above (but this point must, I think,
be treated of more at large), and they are well stored with joys. For,
as it is clear that a happy life consists in perpetual and unexhausted
188pleasures, it follows, too, that a happy life must arise from honesty.
XXIV. But that what I propose to demonstrate to you may not rest on mere
words only, I must set before you the picture of something, as it were,
living and moving in the world, that may dispose us more for the
improvement of the understanding and real knowledge. Let us, then, pitch
upon some man perfectly acquainted with the most excellent arts; let us
present him for awhile to our own thoughts, and figure him to our own
imaginations. In the first place, he must necessarily be of an
extraordinary capacity; for virtue is not easily connected with dull
minds. Secondly, he must have a great desire of discovering truth, from
whence will arise that threefold production of the mind; one of which
depends on knowing things, and explaining nature; the other, in defining
what we ought to desire and what to avoid; the third, in judging of
consequences and impossibilities, in which consists both subtlety in
disputing and also clearness of judgment. Now, with what pleasure must
the mind of a wise man be affected which continually dwells in the midst
of such cares and occupations as these, when he views the revolutions
and motions of the whole world, and sees those innumerable stars in the
heavens, which, though fixed in their places, have yet one motion in
common with the whole universe, and observes the seven other stars, some
higher, some lower, each maintaining their own course, while their
motions, though wandering, have certain defined and appointed spaces to
run through! the sight of which doubtless urged and encouraged those
ancient philosophers to exercise their investigating spirit on many
other things. Hence arose an inquiry after the beginnings, and, as it
were, seeds from which all things were produced and composed; what was
the origin of every kind of thing, whether animate or inanimate,
articulately speaking or mute; what occasioned their beginning and end,
and by what alteration and change one thing was converted into another;
whence the earth originated, and by what weights it was balanced; by
what caverns the seas were supplied; by what gravity all things being
carried down tend always to the middle of the world, which in any round
body is the lowest place.
189XXV. A mind employed on such subjects, and which night and day
contemplates them, contains in itself that precept of the Delphic God,
so as to “know itself,” and to perceive its connection with the divine
reason, from whence it is filled with an insatiable joy. For reflections
on the power and nature of the Gods raise in us a desire of imitating
their eternity. Nor does the mind, that sees the necessary dependences
and connections that one cause has with another, think it possible that
it should be itself confined to the shortness of this life. Those
causes, though they proceed from eternity to eternity, are governed by
reason and understanding. And he who beholds them and examines them, or
rather he whose view takes in all the parts and boundaries of things,
with what tranquillity of mind does he look on all human affairs, and on
all that is nearer him! Hence proceeds the knowledge of virtue; hence
arise the kinds and species of virtues; hence are discovered those
things which nature regards as the bounds and extremities of good and
evil; by this it is discovered to what all duties ought to be referred,
and which is the most eligible manner of life. And when these and
similar points have been investigated, the principal consequence which
is deduced from them, and that which is our main object in this
discussion, is the establishment of the point, that virtue is of itself
sufficient to a happy life.
The third qualification of our wise man is the next to be considered,
which goes through and spreads itself over every part of wisdom; it is
that whereby we define each particular thing, distinguish the genus from
its species, connect consequences, draw just conclusions, and
distinguish truth from falsehood, which is the very art and science of
disputing; which is not only of the greatest use in the examination of
what passes in the world, but is likewise the most rational
entertainment, and that which is most becoming to true wisdom. Such are
its effects in retirement. Now, let our wise man be considered as
protecting the republic; what can be more excellent than such a
character? By his prudence he will discover the true interests of his
fellow-citizens; by his justice he will be prevented from applying what
belongs to the public to his own use; and, in short, he will be ever
governed by all the 190virtues, which are many and various. To these let
us add the advantage of his friendships; in which the learned reckon not
only a natural harmony and agreement of sentiments throughout the
conduct of life, but the utmost pleasure and satisfaction in conversing
and passing our time constantly with one another. What can be wanting to
such a life as this to make it more happy than it is? Fortune herself
must yield to a life stored with such joys. Now, if it be a happiness to
rejoice in such goods of the mind, that is to say, in such virtues, and
if all wise men enjoy thoroughly these pleasures, it must necessarily be
granted that all such are happy.
XXVI. A. What, when in torments and on the rack?
M. Do you imagine I am speaking of him as laid on roses and violets?
Is it allowable even for Epicurus (who only puts on the appearance of
being a philosopher, and who himself assumed that name for himself) to
say (though, as matters stand, I commend him for his saying) that a wise
man might at all times cry out, though he be burned, tortured, cut to
pieces, “How little I regard it!” Shall this be said by one who defines
all evil as pain, and measures every good by pleasure; who could
ridicule whatever we call either honorable or base, and could declare of
us that we were employed about words, and uttering mere empty sounds;
and that nothing is to be regarded by us but as it is perceived to be
smooth or rough by the body? What! shall such a man as this, as I said,
whose understanding is little superior to the beasts’, be at liberty to
forget himself; and not only to despise fortune, when the whole of his
good and evil is in the power of fortune, but to say that he is happy in
the most racking torture, when he had actually declared pain to be not
only the greatest evil, but the only one? Nor did he take any trouble to
provide himself with those remedies which might have enabled him to bear
pain, such as firmness of mind, a shame of doing anything base,
exercise, and the habit of patience, precepts of courage, and a manly
hardiness; but he says that he supports himself on the single
recollection of past pleasures, as if any one, when the weather was so
hot as that he was scarcely able to bear it, should comfort himself by
recollecting that he was once in my country, 191Arpinum, where he was
surrounded on every side by cooling streams. For I do not apprehend how
past pleasures can allay present evils. But when he says that a wise man
is always happy who would have no right to say so if he were consistent
with himself, what may they not do who allow nothing to be desirable,
nothing to be looked on as good but what is honorable? Let, then, the
Peripatetics and Old Academics follow my example, and at length leave
off muttering to themselves; and openly and with a clear voice let them
be bold to say that a happy life may not be inconsistent with the
agonies of Phalaris’s bull.
XXVII. But to dismiss the subtleties of the Stoics, which I am sensible
I have employed more than was necessary, let us admit of three kinds of
goods; and let them really be kinds of goods, provided no regard is had
to the body and to external circumstances, as entitled to the
appellation of good in any other sense than because we are obliged to
use them: but let those other divine goods spread themselves far in
every direction, and reach the very heavens. Why, then, may I not call
him happy, nay, the happiest of men, who has attained them? Shall a wise
man be afraid of pain? which is, indeed, the greatest enemy to our
opinion. For I am persuaded that we are prepared and fortified
sufficiently, by the disputations of the foregoing days, against our own
death or that of our friends, against grief, and the other perturbations
of the mind. But pain seems to be the sharpest adversary of virtue; that
it is which menaces us with burning torches; that it is which threatens
to crush our fortitude, and greatness of mind, and patience. Shall
virtue, then, yield to this? Shall the happy life of a wise and
consistent man succumb to this? Good. Gods! how base would this be!
Spartan boys will bear to have their bodies torn by rods without
uttering a groan. I myself have seen at Lacedæmon troops of young men,
with incredible earnestness contending together with their hands and
feet, with their teeth and nails, nay, even ready to expire, rather than
own themselves conquered. Is any country of barbarians more uncivilized
or desolate than India? Yet they have among them some that are held for
wise men, who never wear any clothes all their life long, and who bear
the 192snow of Caucasus, and the piercing cold of winter, without any
pain; and who if they come in contact with fire endure being burned
without a groan. The women, too, in India, on the death of their
husbands have a regular contest, and apply to the judge to have it
determined which of them was best beloved by him; for it is customary
there for one man to have many wives. She in whose favor it is
determined exults greatly, and being attended by her relations, is laid
on the funeral pile with her husband; the others, who are postponed,
walk away very much dejected. Custom can never be superior to nature,
for nature is never to be got the better of. But our minds are infected
by sloth and idleness, and luxury, and languor, and indolence: we have
enervated them by opinions and bad customs. Who is there who is
unacquainted with the customs of the Egyptians? Their minds being
tainted by pernicious opinions, they are ready to bear any torture
rather than hurt an ibis, a snake, a cat, a dog, or a crocodile; and
should any one inadvertently have hurt any of these animals, he will
submit to any punishment. I am speaking of men only. As to the beasts,
do they not bear cold and hunger, running about in woods, and on
mountains and deserts? Will they not fight for their young ones till
they are wounded? Are they afraid of any attacks or blows? I mention not
what the ambitious will suffer for honor’s sake, or those who are
desirous of praise on account of glory, or lovers to gratify their lust.
Life is full of such instances.
XXVIII. But let us not dwell too much on these questions, but rather let
us return to our subject. I say, and say again, that happiness will
submit even to be tormented; and that in pursuit of justice, and
temperance, and still more especially and principally fortitude, and
greatness of soul, and patience, it will not stop short at sight of the
executioner; and when all other virtues proceed calmly to the torture,
that one will never halt, as I said, on the outside and threshold of the
prison; for what can be baser, what can carry a worse appearance, than
to be left alone, separated from those beautiful attendants? Not,
however, that this is by any means possible; for neither can the virtues
hold together without happiness, nor happiness 193without the virtues; so
that they will not suffer her to desert them, but will carry her along
with them, to whatever torments, to whatever pain they are led. For it
is the peculiar quality of a wise man to do nothing that he may repent
of, nothing against his inclination, but always to act nobly, with
constancy, gravity, and honesty; to depend on nothing as certainty; to
wonder at nothing, when it falls out, as if it appeared strange and
unexpected to him; to be independent of every one, and abide by his own
opinion. For my part, I cannot form an idea of anything happier than
this. The conclusion of the Stoics is indeed easy; for since they are
persuaded that the end of good is to live agreeably to nature, and to be
consistent with that—as a wise man should do so, not only because it is
his duty, but because it is in his power—it must, of course, follow
that whoever has the chief good in his power has his happiness so too.
And thus the life of a wise man is always happy. You have here what I
think may be confidently said of a happy life; and as things now stand,
very truly also, unless you can advance something better.
XXIX. A. Indeed I cannot; but I should be glad to prevail on you,
unless it is troublesome (as you are under no confinement from
obligations to any particular sect, but gather from all of them whatever
strikes you most as having the appearance of probability), as you just
now seemed to advise the Peripatetics and the Old Academy boldly to
speak out without reserve, “that wise men are always the happiest”—I
should be glad to hear how you think it consistent for them to say so,
when you have said so much against that opinion, and the conclusions of
the Stoics.
M. I will make use, then, of that liberty which no one has the
privilege of using in philosophy but those of our school, whose
discourses determine nothing, but take in everything, leaving them
unsupported by the authority of any particular person, to be judged of
by others, according to their weight. And as you seem desirous of
knowing how it is that, notwithstanding the different opinions of
philosophers with regard to the ends of goods, virtue has still
sufficient security for the effecting of a happy life—which security,
as we are informed, Carneades used indeed to dispute against; but he
disputed as against the 194Stoics, whose opinions he combated with great
zeal and vehemence. I, however, shall handle the question with more
temper; for if the Stoics have rightly settled the ends of goods, the
affair is at an end; for a wise man must necessarily be always happy.
But let us examine, if we can, the particular opinions of the others,
that so this excellent decision, if I may so call it, in favor of a
happy life, may be agreeable to the opinions and discipline of all.
XXX. These, then, are the opinions, as I think, that are held and
defended—the first four are simple ones: “that nothing is good but what
is honest,” according to the Stoics; “nothing good but pleasure,” as
Epicurus maintains; “nothing good but a freedom from pain,” as
Hieronymus62 asserts; “nothing good but an enjoyment of the principal,
or all, or the greatest goods of nature,” as Carneades maintained
against the Stoics—these are simple, the others are mixed propositions.
Then there are three kinds of goods: the greatest being those of the
mind; the next best those of the body; the third are external goods, as
the Peripatetics call them, and the Old Academics differ very little
from them. Dinomachus63 and Callipho64 have coupled pleasure with
honesty; but Diodorus65 the Peripatetic has joined indolence to
honesty. These are the opinions that have some footing; for those of
Aristo,66 Pyrrho,67 Herillus,68 and of some others, are quite out
of date. Now let us see what weight these men have in 195them, excepting the
Stoics, whose opinion I think I have sufficiently defended; and indeed I
have explained what the Peripatetics have to say; excepting that
Theophrastus, and those who followed him, dread and abhor pain in too
weak a manner. The others may go on to exaggerate the gravity and
dignity of virtue, as usual; and then, after they have extolled it to
the skies, with the usual extravagance of good orators, it is easy to
reduce the other topics to nothing by comparison, and to hold them up to
contempt. They who think that praise deserves to be sought after, even
at the expense of pain, are not at liberty to deny those men to be happy
who have obtained it. Though they may be under some evils, yet this name
of happy has a very wide application.
XXXI. For even as trading is said to be lucrative, and farming
advantageous, not because the one never meets with any loss, nor the
other with any damage from the inclemency of the weather, but because
they succeed in general; so life may be properly called happy, not from
its being entirely made up of good things, but because it abounds with
these to a great and considerable degree. By this way of reasoning,
then, a happy life may attend virtue even to the moment of execution;
nay, may descend with her into Phalaris’s bull, according to Aristotle,
Xenocrates, Speusippus, Polemon; and will not be gained over by any
allurements to forsake her. Of the same opinion will Calliphon and
Diodorus be; for they are both of them such friends to virtue as to
think that all things should be discarded and far removed that are
incompatible with it. The rest seem to be more hampered with these
doctrines, but yet they get clear of them; such as Epicurus, Hieronymus,
and whoever else thinks it worth while to defend the deserted Carneades:
for there is not one of them who does not think the mind to be judge of
those goods, and able sufficiently to instruct him how to despise what
has the appearance only of good or evil. For what seems to you to be the
case with Epicurus is the case also with Hieronymus and Carneades, and,
indeed, with all the rest of them; for who is there who is not
sufficiently prepared against death and pain? I will begin, with your
leave, with him whom we call soft and voluptuous. What! 196does he seem,
to you to be afraid of death or pain when he calls the day of his death
happy; and who, when he is afflicted by the greatest pains, silences
them all by recollecting arguments of his own discovering? And this is
not done in such a manner as to give room for imagining that he talks
thus wildly from some sudden impulse; but his opinion of death is, that
on the dissolution of the animal all sense is lost; and what is deprived
of sense is, as he thinks, what we have no concern at all with. And as
to pain, too, he has certain rules to follow then: if it be great, the
comfort is that it must be short; if it be of long continuance, then it
must be supportable. What, then? Do those grandiloquent gentlemen state
anything better than Epicurus in opposition to these two things which
distress us the most? And as to other things, do not Epicurus and the
rest of the philosophers seem sufficiently prepared? Who is there who
does not dread poverty? And yet no true philosopher ever can dread it.
XXXII. But with how little is this man himself satisfied! No one has
said more on frugality. For when a man is far removed from those things
which occasion a desire of money, from love, ambition, or other daily
extravagance, why should he be fond of money, or concern himself at all
about it? Could the Scythian Anacharsis69 disregard money, and shall
not our philosophers be able to do so? We are informed of an epistle of
his in these words: “Anacharsis to Hanno, greeting. My clothing is the
same as that with which the Scythians cover themselves; the hardness of
my feet supplies the want of shoes; the ground is my bed, hunger my
sauce, my food milk, cheese, and flesh. So you may come to me as to a
man in want of nothing. But as to those presents you take so much
pleasure in, you may dispose of them to your own citizens, or to the
immortal Gods.” And almost all philosophers, of all schools, excepting
those who are warped 197from right reason by a vicious disposition, might
have been of this same opinion. Socrates, when on one occasion he saw a
great quantity of gold and silver carried in a procession, cried out,
“How many things are there which I do not want!” Xenocrates, when some
ambassadors from Alexander had brought him fifty talents, which was a
very large sum of money in those times, especially at Athens, carried
the ambassadors to sup in the Academy, and placed just a sufficiency
before them, without any apparatus. When they asked him, the next day,
to whom he wished the money which they had for him to be paid: “What!”
said he, “did you not perceive by our slight repast of yesterday that I
had no occasion for money?” But when he perceived that they were
somewhat dejected, he accepted of thirty minas, that he might not seem
to treat with disrespect the king’s generosity. But Diogenes took a
greater liberty, like a Cynic, when Alexander asked him if he wanted
anything: “Just at present,” said he, “I wish that you would stand a
little out of the line between me and the sun,” for Alexander was
hindering him from sunning himself. And, indeed, this very man used to
maintain how much he surpassed the Persian king in his manner of life
and fortune; for that he himself was in want of nothing, while the other
never had enough; and that he had no inclination for those pleasures of
which the other could never get enough to satisfy himself; and that the
other could never obtain his.
XXXIII. You see, I imagine, how Epicurus has divided his kinds of
desires, not very acutely perhaps, but yet usefully: saying that they
are “partly natural and necessary; partly natural, but not necessary;
partly neither. That those which are necessary may be supplied almost
for nothing; for that the things which nature requires are easily
obtained.” As to the second kind of desires, his opinion is that any one
may easily either enjoy or go without them. And with regard to the
third, since they are utterly frivolous, being neither allied to
necessity nor nature, he thinks that they should be entirely rooted out.
On this topic a great many arguments are adduced by the Epicureans; and
those pleasures which they do not despise in a body, they disparage one
by one, and seem rather 198for lessening the number of them; for as to
wanton pleasures, on which subject they say a great deal, these, say
they, are easy, common, and within any one’s reach; and they think that
if nature requires them, they are not to be estimated by birth,
condition, or rank, but by shape, age, and person: and that it is by no
means difficult to refrain from them, should health, duty, or reputation
require it; but that pleasures of this kind may be desirable, where they
are attended with no inconvenience, but can never be of any use. And the
assertions which Epicurus makes with respect to the whole of pleasure
are such as show his opinion to be that pleasure is always desirable,
and to be pursued merely because it is pleasure; and for the same reason
pain is to be avoided, because it is pain. So that a wise man will
always adopt such a system of counterbalancing as to do himself the
justice to avoid pleasure, should pain ensue from it in too great a
proportion; and will submit to pain, provided the effects of it are to
produce a greater pleasure: so that all pleasurable things, though the
corporeal senses are the judges of them, are still to be referred to the
mind, on which account the body rejoices while it perceives a present
pleasure; but that the mind not only perceives the present as well as
the body, but foresees it while it is coming, and even when it is past
will not let it quite slip away. So that a wise man enjoys a continual
series of pleasures, uniting the expectation of future pleasure to the
recollection of what he has already tasted. The like notions are applied
by them to high living; and the magnificence and expensiveness of
entertainments are deprecated, because nature is satisfied at a small
expense.
XXXIV. For who does not see this, that an appetite is the best sauce?
When Darius, in his flight from the enemy, had drunk some water which
was muddy and tainted with dead bodies, he declared that he had never
drunk anything more pleasant; the fact was, that he had never drunk
before when he was thirsty. Nor had Ptolemy ever eaten when he was
hungry; for as he was travelling over Egypt, his company not keeping up
with him, he had some coarse bread presented him in a cottage, upon
which he said, “Nothing ever seemed to him pleasanter 199than that bread.”
They relate, too, of Socrates, that, once when he was walking very fast
till the evening, on his being asked why he did so, his reply was that
he was purchasing an appetite by walking, that he might sup the better.
And do we not see what the Lacedæmonians provide in their Phiditia?
where the tyrant Dionysius supped, but told them he did not at all like
that black broth, which was their principal dish; on which he who
dressed it said, “It was no wonder, for it wanted seasoning.” Dionysius
asked what that seasoning was; to which it was replied, “Fatigue in
hunting, sweating, a race on the banks of Eurotas, hunger and thirst,”
for these are the seasonings to the Lacedæmonian banquets. And this may
not only be conceived from the custom of men, but from the beasts, who
are satisfied with anything that is thrown before them, provided it is
not unnatural, and they seek no farther. Some entire cities, taught by
custom, delight in parsimony, as I said but just now of the
Lacedæmonians. Xenophon has given an account of the Persian diet, who
never, as he saith, use anything but cresses with their bread; not but
that, should nature require anything more agreeable, many things might
be easily supplied by the ground, and plants in great abundance, and of
incomparable sweetness. Add to this strength and health, as the
consequence of this abstemious way of living. Now, compare with this
those who sweat and belch, being crammed with eating, like fatted oxen;
then will you perceive that they who pursue pleasure most attain it
least; and that the pleasure of eating lies not in satiety, but
appetite.
XXXV. They report of Timotheus, a famous man at Athens, and the head of
the city, that having supped with Plato, and being extremely delighted
with his entertainment, on seeing him the next day, he said, “Your
suppers are not only agreeable while I partake of them, but the next day
also.” Besides, the understanding is impaired when we are full with
overeating and drinking. There is an excellent epistle of Plato to
Dion’s relations, in which there occurs as nearly as possible these
words: “When I came there, that happy life so much talked of, devoted to
Italian and Syracusan entertainments, was noways agreeable to me; to be
crammed twice a day, and never to 200have the night to yourself, and the
other things which are the accompaniments of this kind of life, by which
a man will never be made the wiser, but will be rendered much less
temperate; for it must be an extraordinary disposition that can be
temperate in such circumstances.” How, then, can a life be pleasant
without prudence and temperance? Hence you discover the mistake of
Sardanapalus, the wealthiest king of the Assyrians, who ordered it to be
engraved on his tomb,
I still have what in food I did exhaust;
But what I left, though excellent, is lost.
“What less than this,” says Aristotle, “could be inscribed on the tomb,
not of a king, but an ox?” He said that he possessed those things when
dead, which, in his lifetime, he could have no longer than while he was
enjoying them. Why, then, are riches desired? And wherein doth poverty
prevent us from being happy? In the want, I imagine, of statues,
pictures, and diversions. But if any one is delighted with these things,
have not the poor people the enjoyment of them more than they who are
the owners of them in the greatest abundance? For we have great numbers
of them displayed publicly in our city. And whatever store of them
private people have, they cannot have a great number, and they but
seldom see them, only when they go to their country seats; and some of
them must be stung to the heart when they consider how they came by
them. The day would fail me, should I be inclined to defend the cause of
poverty. The thing is manifest; and nature daily informs us how few
things there are, and how trifling they are, of which she really stands
in need.
XXXVI. Let us inquire, then, if obscurity, the want of power, or even
the being unpopular, can prevent a wise man from being happy. Observe if
popular favor, and this glory which they are so fond of, be not attended
with more uneasiness than pleasure. Our friend Demosthenes was certainly
very weak in declaring himself pleased with the whisper of a woman who
was carrying water, as is the custom in Greece, and who whispered to
another, “That is he—that is Demosthenes.” What could be weaker than
201this? and yet what an orator he was! But although he had learned to
speak to others, he had conversed but little with himself. We may
perceive, therefore, that popular glory is not desirable of itself; nor
is obscurity to be dreaded. “I came to Athens,” saith Democritus, “and
there was no one there that knew me:” this was a moderate and grave man
who could glory in his obscurity. Shall musicians compose their tunes to
their own tastes? and shall a philosopher, master of a much better art,
seek to ascertain, not what is most true, but what will please the
people? Can anything be more absurd than to despise the vulgar as mere
unpolished mechanics, taken singly, and to think them of consequence
when collected into a body? These wise men would contemn our ambitious
pursuits and our vanities, and would reject all the honors which the
people could voluntarily offer to them; but we know not how to despise
them till we begin to repent of having accepted them. There is an
anecdote related by Heraclitus, the natural philosopher, of Hermodorus,
the chief of the Ephesians, that he said “that all the Ephesians ought
to be punished with death for saying, when they had expelled Hermodorus
out of their city, that they would have no one among them better than
another; but that if there were any such, he might go elsewhere to some
other people.” Is not this the case with the people everywhere? Do they
not hate every virtue that distinguishes itself? What! was not Aristides
(I had rather instance in the Greeks than ourselves) banished his
country for being eminently just? What troubles, then, are they free
from who have no connection whatever with the people? What is more
agreeable than a learned retirement? I speak of that learning which
makes us acquainted with the boundless extent of nature and the
universe, and which even while we remain in this world discovers to us
both heaven, earth, and sea.
XXXVII. If, then, honor and riches have no value, what is there else to
be afraid of? Banishment, I suppose; which is looked on as the greatest
evil. Now, if the evil of banishment proceeds not from ourselves, but
from the froward disposition of the people, I have just now declared how
contemptible it is. But if to leave one’s country be miserable,
202the
provinces are full of miserable men, very few of the settlers in which
ever return to their country again. But exiles are deprived of their
property! What, then! has there not been enough said on bearing poverty?
But with regard to banishment, if we examine the nature of things, not
the ignominy of the name, how little does it differ from constant
travelling! in which some of the most famous philosophers have spent
their whole life, as Xenocrates, Crantor, Arcesilas, Lacydes, Aristotle,
Theophrastus, Zeno, Cleanthes, Chrysippus, Antipater, Carneades,
Panætius, Clitomachus, Philo, Antiochus, Posidonius, and innumerable
others, who from their first setting-out never returned home again.
Now, what ignominy can a wise man be affected with (for it is of such a
one that I am speaking) who can be guilty of nothing which deserves it?
for there is no occasion to comfort one who is banished for his deserts.
Lastly, they can easily reconcile themselves to every accident who
measure all their objects and pursuits in life by the standard of
pleasure; so that in whatever place that is supplied, there they may
live happily. Thus what Teucer said may be applied to every case:
“Wherever I am happy is my country.”
Socrates, indeed, when he was asked where he belonged to, replied, “The
world;” for he looked upon himself as a citizen and inhabitant of the
whole world. How was it with T. Altibutius? Did he not follow his
philosophical studies with the greatest satisfaction at Athens, although
he was banished? which, however, would not have happened to him if he
had obeyed the laws of Epicurus and lived peaceably in the republic. In
what was Epicurus happier, living in his own country, than Metrodorus,
who lived at Athens? Or did Plato’s happiness exceed that of Xenocrates,
or Polemo, or Arcesilas? Or is that city to be valued much that banishes
all her good and wise men? Demaratus, the father of our King Tarquin,
not being able to bear the tyrant Cypselus, fled from Corinth to
Tarquinii, settled there, and had children. Was it, then, an unwise act
in him to prefer the liberty of banishment to slavery at home?
XXXVIII. Besides the emotions of the mind, all griefs
203and anxieties are
assuaged by forgetting them, and turning our thoughts to pleasure.
Therefore, it was not without reason that Epicurus presumed to say that
a wise man abounds with good things, because he may always have his
pleasures; from whence it follows, as he thinks, that that point is
gained which is the subject of our present inquiry, that a wise man is
always happy. What! though he should be deprived of the senses of seeing
and hearing? Yes; for he holds those things very cheap. For, in the
first place, what are the pleasures of which we are deprived by that
dreadful thing, blindness? For though they allow other pleasures to be
confined to the senses, yet the things which are perceived by the sight
do not depend wholly on the pleasure the eyes receive; as is the case
when we taste, smell, touch, or hear; for, in respect of all these
senses, the organs themselves are the seat of pleasure; but it is not so
with the eyes. For it is the mind which is entertained by what we see;
but the mind may be entertained in many ways, even though we could not
see at all. I am speaking of a learned and a wise man, with whom to
think is to live. But thinking in the case of a wise man does not
altogether require the use of his eyes in his investigations; for if
night does not strip him of his happiness, why should blindness, which
resembles night, have that effect? For the reply of Antipater the
Cyrenaic to some women who bewailed his being blind, though it is a
little too obscene, is not without its significance. “What do you mean?”
saith he; “do you think the night can furnish no pleasure?” And we find
by his magistracies and his actions that old Appius,
70 too, who was
blind for many years, was not prevented from doing whatever was required
of him with respect either to the republic or his own affairs. It is
said that C. Drusus’s house was crowded with clients. When they whose
business it was could not see how to conduct themselves, they applied to
a blind guide.
XXXIX. When I was a boy, Cn. Aufidius, a blind man,
204who had served the
office of prætor, not only gave his opinion in the Senate, and was ready
to assist his friends, but wrote a Greek history, and had a considerable
acquaintance with literature. Diodorus the Stoic was blind, and lived
many years at my house. He, indeed, which is scarcely credible, besides
applying himself more than usual to philosophy, and playing on the
flute, agreeably to the custom of the Pythagoreans, and having books
read to him night and day, in all which he did not want eyes, contrived
to teach geometry, which, one would think, could hardly be done without
the assistance of eyes, telling his scholars how and where to draw every
line. They relate of Asclepiades, a native of Eretria, and no obscure
philosopher, when some one asked him what inconvenience he suffered from
his blindness, that his reply was, “He was at the expense of another
servant.” So that, as the most extreme poverty may be borne if you
please, as is daily the case with some in Greece, so blindness may
easily be borne, provided you have the support of good health in other
respects. Democritus was so blind he could not distinguish white from
black; but he knew the difference between good and evil, just and
unjust, honorable and base, the useful and useless, great and small.
Thus one may live happily without distinguishing colors; but without
acquainting yourself with things, you cannot; and this man was of
opinion that the intense application of the mind was taken off by the
objects that presented themselves to the eye; and while others often
could not see what was before their feet, he travelled through all
infinity. It is reported also that Homer
71 was blind, but we observe
205his painting as well as his poetry. What country, what coast, what part
of Greece, what military attacks, what dispositions of battle, what
array, what ship, what motions of men and animals, can be mentioned
which he has not described in such a manner as to enable us to see what
he could not see himself? What, then! can we imagine that Homer, or any
other learned man, has ever been in want of pleasure and entertainment
for his mind? Were it not so, would Anaxagoras, or this very Democritus,
have left their estates and patrimonies, and given themselves up to the
pursuit of acquiring this divine pleasure? It is thus that the poets who
have represented Tiresias the Augur as a wise man and blind never
exhibit him as bewailing his blindness. And Homer, too, after he had
described Polyphemus as a monster and a wild man, represents him talking
with his ram, and speaking of his good fortune, inasmuch as he could go
wherever he pleased and touch what he would. And so far he was right,
for that Cyclops was a being of not much more understanding than his
ram.
XL. Now, as to the evil of being deaf. M. Crassus was a little thick of
hearing; but it was more uneasiness to him that he heard himself ill
spoken of, though, in my opinion, he did not deserve it. Our Epicureans
cannot understand Greek, nor the Greeks Latin: now, they are deaf
reciprocally as to each other’s language, and we are all truly deaf with
regard to those innumerable languages which we do not understand. They
do not hear the voice of the harper; but, then, they do not hear the
grating of a saw when it is setting, or the grunting of a hog when his
206throat is being cut, nor the roaring of the sea when they are desirous
of rest. And if they should chance to be fond of singing, they ought, in
the first place, to consider that many wise men lived happily before
music was discovered; besides, they may have more pleasure in reading
verses than in hearing them sung. Then, as I before referred the blind
to the pleasures of hearing, so I may the deaf to the pleasures of
sight: moreover, whoever can converse with himself doth not need the
conversation of another. But suppose all these misfortunes to meet in
one person: suppose him blind and deaf—let him be afflicted with the
sharpest pains of body, which, in the first place, generally of
themselves make an end of him; still, should they continue so long, and
the pain be so exquisite, that we should be unable to assign any reason
for our being so afflicted—still, why, good Gods! should we be under
any difficulty? For there is a retreat at hand: death is that retreat—a
shelter where we shall forever be insensible. Theodorus said to
Lysimachus, who threatened him with death, “It is a great matter,
indeed, for you to have acquired the power of a Spanish fly!” When
Perses entreated Paulus not to lead him in triumph, “That is a matter
which you have in your own power,” said Paulus. I said many things about
death in our first day’s disputation, when death was the subject; and
not a little the next day, when I treated of pain; which things if you
recollect, there can be no danger of your looking upon death as
undesirable, or, at least, it will not be dreadful.
That custom which is common among the Grecians at their banquets should,
in my opinion, be observed in life: Drink, say they, or leave the
company; and rightly enough; for a guest should either enjoy the
pleasure of drinking with others, or else not stay till he meets with
affronts from those that are in liquor. Thus, those injuries of fortune
which you cannot bear you should flee from.
XLI. This is the very same which is said by Epicurus and Hieronymus.
Now, if those philosophers, whose opinion it is that virtue has no power
of itself, and who say that the conduct which we denominate honorable
and laudable is really nothing, and is only an empty circumstance
207set
off with an unmeaning sound, can nevertheless maintain that a wise man
is always happy, what, think you, may be done by the Socratic and
Platonic philosophers? Some of these allow such superiority to the goods
of the mind as quite to eclipse what concerns the body and all external
circumstances. But others do not admit these to be goods; they make
everything depend on the mind: whose disputes Carneades used, as a sort
of honorary arbitrator, to determine. For, as what seemed goods to the
Peripatetics were allowed to be advantages by the Stoics, and as the
Peripatetics allowed no more to riches, good health; and other things of
that sort than the Stoics, when these things were considered according
to their reality, and not by mere names, his opinion was that there was
no ground for disagreeing. Therefore, let the philosophers of other
schools see how they can establish this point also. It is very agreeable
to me that they make some professions worthy of being uttered by the
mouth of a philosopher with regard to a wise man’s having always the
means of living happily.
XLII. But as we are to depart in the morning, let us remember these five
days’ discussions; though, indeed, I think I shall commit them to
writing: for how can I better employ the leisure which I have, of
whatever kind it is, and whatever it be owing to? And I will send these
five books also to my friend Brutus, by whom I was not only incited to
write on philosophy, but, I may say, provoked. And by so doing it is not
easy to say what service I may be of to others. At all events, in my own
various and acute afflictions, which surround me on all sides, I cannot
find any better comfort for myself.
209THE NATURE OF THE GODS.
BOOK I.
I.
There are many things in philosophy, my dear Brutus, which are not as
yet fully explained to us, and particularly (as you very well know) that
most obscure and difficult question concerning the Nature of the Gods,
so extremely necessary both towards a knowledge of the human mind and
the practice of true religion: concerning which the opinions of men are
so various, and so different from each other, as to lead strongly to the
inference that ignorance
72 is the cause, or origin, of philosophy, and
that the Academic philosophers have been prudent in refusing their
assent to things uncertain: for what is more unbecoming to a wise man
than to judge rashly? or what rashness is so unworthy of the gravity and
stability of a philosopher as either to maintain false opinions, or,
without the least hesitation, to support and defend what he has not
thoroughly examined and does not clearly comprehend?
In the question now before us, the greater part of mankind have united
to acknowledge that which is most probable, and which we are all by
nature led to suppose, namely, that there are Gods. Protagoras
73
doubted whether there were any. Diagoras the Melian and Theodorus of
Cyrene entirely believed there were no such beings. But they who have
affirmed that there are Gods, have expressed such a variety of
sentiments on the subject, and the disagreement between them is so
great, that it would be
210tiresome to enumerate their opinions; for they
give us many statements respecting the forms of the Gods, and their
places of abode, and the employment of their lives. And these are
matters on which the philosophers differ with the most exceeding
earnestness. But the most considerable part of the dispute is, whether
they are wholly inactive, totally unemployed, and free from all care and
administration of affairs; or, on the contrary, whether all things were
made and constituted by them from the beginning; and whether they will
continue to be actuated and governed by them to eternity. This is one of
the greatest points in debate; and unless this is decided, mankind must
necessarily remain in the greatest of errors, and ignorant of what is
most important to be known.
II. For there are some philosophers, both ancient and modern, who have
conceived that the Gods take not the least cognizance of human affairs.
But if their doctrine be true, of what avail is piety, sanctity, or
religion? for these are feelings and marks of devotion which are offered
to the Gods by men with uprightness and holiness, on the ground that men
are the objects of the attention of the Gods, and that many benefits are
conferred by the immortal Gods on the human race. But if the Gods have
neither the power nor the inclination to help us; if they take no care
of us, and pay no regard to our actions; and if there is no single
advantage which can possibly accrue to the life of man; then what reason
can we have to pay any adoration, or any honors, or to prefer any
prayers to them? Piety, like the other virtues, cannot have any
connection with vain show or dissimulation; and without piety, neither
sanctity nor religion can be supported; the total subversion of which
must be attended with great confusion and disturbance in life.
I do not even know, if we cast off piety towards the Gods, but that
faith, and all the associations of human life, and that most excellent
of all virtues, justice, may perish with it.
There are other philosophers, and those, too, very great and illustrious
men, who conceive the whole world to be directed and governed by the
will and wisdom of the Gods; nor do they stop here, but conceive
likewise that the Deities
211consult and provide for the preservation of
mankind. For they think that the fruits, and the produce of the earth,
and the seasons, and the variety of weather, and the change of climates,
by which all the productions of the earth are brought to maturity, are
designed by the immortal Gods for the use of man. They instance many
other things, which shall be related in these books; and which would
almost induce us to believe that the immortal Gods had made them all
expressly and solely for the benefit and advantage of men. Against these
opinions Carneades has advanced so much that what he has said should
excite a desire in men who are not naturally slothful to search after
truth; for there is no subject on which the learned as well as the
unlearned differ so strenuously as in this; and since their opinions are
so various, and so repugnant one to another, it is possible that none of
them may be, and absolutely impossible that more than one should be,
right.
III. Now, in a cause like this, I may be able to pacify well-meaning
opposers, and to confute invidious censurers, so as to induce the latter
to repent of their unreasonable contradiction, and the former to be glad
to learn; for they who admonish one in a friendly spirit should be
instructed, they who attack one like enemies should be repelled. But I
observe that the several books which I have lately published
74 have
occasioned much noise and various discourse about them; some people
wondering what the reason has been why I have applied myself so suddenly
to the study of philosophy, and others desirous of knowing what my
opinion is on such subjects. I likewise perceive that many people wonder
at my following that philosophy
75 chiefly which seems to take away the
light, and to bury and envelop things in a kind of artificial night, and
that I should so unexpectedly have taken up the defence of a school that
has been long neglected and forsaken. But it is a mistake to suppose
that this application to philosophical studies has been sudden on my
part. I have applied
212myself to them from my youth, at no small expense
of time and trouble; and I have been in the habit of philosophizing a
great deal when I least seemed to think about it; for the truth of which
I appeal to my orations, which are filled with quotations from
philosophers, and to my intimacy with those very learned men who
frequented my house and conversed daily with me, particularly Diodorus,
Philo, Antiochus, and Posidonius,
76 under whom I was bred; and if all
the precepts of philosophy are to have reference to the conduct of life,
I am inclined to think that I have advanced, both in public and private
affairs, only such principles as may be supported by reason and
authority.
IV. But if any one should ask what has induced me, in the decline of
life, to write on these subjects, nothing is more easily answered; for
when I found myself entirely disengaged from business, and the
commonwealth reduced to the necessity of being governed by the direction
and care of one man,
77 I thought it becoming, for the sake of the
public, to instruct my countrymen in philosophy, and that it would be of
importance, and much to the honor and commendation of our city, to have
such great and excellent subjects introduced in the Latin tongue. I the
less repent of my undertaking, since I plainly see that I have excited
in many a desire, not only of learning, but of writing; for we have had
several Romans well grounded in the learning of the Greeks who were
unable to communicate to their countrymen what they had learned, because
they looked upon it as impossible to express that in Latin which they
had received from the Greeks. In this point I think I have succeeded so
well that what I have done is not, even in copiousness of expression,
inferior to that language.
Another inducement to it was a melancholy disposition of mind, and the
great and heavy oppression of fortune that was upon me; from which, if I
could have found any surer remedy, I would not have sought relief in
this pursuit. But I could procure ease by no means better than by not
only applying myself to books, but by devoting myself
213to the
examination of the whole body of philosophy. And every part and branch
of this is readily discovered when every question is propounded in
writing; for there is such an admirable continuation and series of
things that each seems connected with the other, and all appear linked
together and united.
V. Now, those men who desire to know my own private opinion on every
particular subject have more curiosity than is necessary. For the force
of reason in disputation is to be sought after rather than authority,
since the authority of the teacher is often a disadvantage to those who
are willing to learn; as they refuse to use their own judgment, and rely
implicitly on him whom they make choice of for a preceptor. Nor could I
ever approve this custom of the Pythagoreans, who, when they affirmed
anything in disputation, and were asked why it was so, used to give this
answer: “He himself has said it;” and this “he himself,” it seems, was
Pythagoras. Such was the force of prejudice and opinion that his
authority was to prevail even without argument or reason.
They who wonder at my being a follower of this sect in particular may
find a satisfactory answer in my four books of Academical Questions. But
I deny that I have undertaken the protection of what is neglected and
forsaken; for the opinions of men do not die with them, though they may
perhaps want the author’s explanation. This manner of philosophizing, of
disputing all things and assuming nothing certainly, was begun by
Socrates, revived by Arcesilaus, confirmed by Carneades, and has
descended, with all its power, even to the present age; but I am
informed that it is now almost exploded even in Greece. However, I do
not impute that to any fault in the institution of the Academy, but to
the negligence of mankind. If it is difficult to know all the doctrines
of any one sect, how much more is it to know those of every sect! which,
however, must necessarily be known to those who resolve, for the sake of
discovering truth, to dispute for or against all philosophers without
partiality.
I do not profess myself to be master of this difficult and noble
faculty; but I do assert that I have endeavored to make myself so; and
it is impossible that they who choose
214this manner of philosophizing
should not meet at least with something worthy their pursuit. I have
spoken more fully on this head in another place. But as some are too
slow of apprehension, and some too careless, men stand in perpetual need
of caution. For we are not people who believe that there is nothing
whatever which is true; but we say that some falsehoods are so blended
with all truths, and have so great a resemblance to them, that there is
no certain rule for judging of or assenting to propositions; from which
this maxim also follows, that many things are probable, which, though
they are not evident to the senses, have still so persuasive and
beautiful an aspect that a wise man chooses to direct his conduct by
them.
VI. Now, to free myself from the reproach of partiality, I propose to
lay before you the opinions of various philosophers concerning the
nature of the Gods, by which means all men may judge which of them are
consistent with truth; and if all agree together, or if any one shall be
found to have discovered what may be absolutely called truth, I will
then give up the Academy as vain and arrogant. So I may cry out, in the
words of Statius, in the Synephebi,
Ye Gods, I call upon, require, pray, beseech, entreat, and implore
the attention of my countrymen all, both young and old;
yet not on so trifling an occasion as when the person in the play
complains that,
In this city we have discovered a most flagrant iniquity: here is a
professed courtesan, who refuses money from her lover;
but that they may attend, know, and consider what sentiments they ought
to preserve concerning religion, piety, sanctity, ceremonies, faith,
oaths, temples, shrines, and solemn sacrifices; what they ought to think
of the auspices over which I preside;78 for all these have relation to
the present question. The manifest disagreement among the most learned
on this subject creates doubts in those who imagine they have some
certain knowledge of the subject.
Which fact I have often taken notice of elsewhere, and 215I did so more
especially at the discussion that was held at my friend C. Cotta’s
concerning the immortal Gods, and which was carried on with the greatest
care, accuracy, and precision; for coming to him at the time of the
Latin holidays,79 according to his own invitation and message from
him, I found him sitting in his study,80 and in a discourse with C.
Velleius, the senator, who was then reputed by the Epicureans the ablest
of our countrymen. Q. Lucilius Balbus was likewise there, a great
proficient in the doctrine of the Stoics, and esteemed equal to the most
eminent of the Greeks in that part of knowledge. As soon as Cotta saw
me, You are come, says he, very seasonably; for I am having a dispute
with Velleius on an important subject, which, considering the nature of
your studies, is not improper for you to join in.
VII. Indeed, says I, I think I am come very seasonably, as you say; for
here are three chiefs of three principal sects met together. If M.
Piso81 was present, no sect of philosophy that is in any esteem would
want an advocate. If Antiochus’s book, replies Cotta, which he lately
sent to Balbus, says true, you have no occasion to wish for your friend
Piso; for Antiochus is of the opinion that the Stoics do not differ from
the Peripatetics in fact, though they do in words; and I should be glad
to know what you think of that book, Balbus. I? says he. I wonder that
Antiochus, a man of the clearest apprehension, should not see what a
vast difference there is between the Stoics, who distinguish the honest
and the profitable, not only in name, but absolutely in kind, and the
Peripatetics, who blend the honest with the profitable in such a manner
that they differ only in degrees and proportion, and not in kind. This
is not a little difference in words, but a great one in things; 216but of
this hereafter. Now, if you think fit, let us return to what we began
with.
With all my heart, says Cotta. But that this visitor (looking at me),
who is just come in, may not be ignorant of what we are upon, I will
inform him that we were discoursing on the nature of the Gods;
concerning which, as it is a subject that always appeared very obscure
to me, I prevailed on Velleius to give us the sentiments of Epicurus.
Therefore, continues he, if it is not troublesome, Velleius, repeat what
you have already stated to us. I will, says he, though this new-comer
will be no advocate for me, but for you; for you have both, adds he,
with a smile, learned from the same Philo to be certain of nothing.82
What we have learned from him, replied I, Cotta will discover; but I
would not have you think I am come as an assistant to him, but as an
auditor, with an impartial and unbiassed mind, and not bound by any
obligation to defend any particular principle, whether I like or dislike
it.
VIII. After this, Velleius, with the confidence peculiar to his sect,
dreading nothing so much as to seem to doubt of anything, began as if he
had just then descended from the council of the Gods, and Epicurus’s
intervals of worlds. Do not attend, says he, to these idle and imaginary
tales; nor to the operator and builder of the World, the God of Plato’s
Timæus; nor to the old prophetic dame, the Πρόνοια of the Stoics, which
the Latins call Providence; nor to that round, that burning, revolving
deity, the World, endowed with sense and understanding; the prodigies
and wonders, not of inquisitive philosophers, but of dreamers!
For with what eyes of the mind was your Plato able to see that workhouse
of such stupendous toil, in which he makes the world to be modelled and
built by God? What materials, what tools, what bars, what machines, what
servants, were employed in so vast a work? How could the air, fire,
water, and earth pay obedience and submit to the will of the architect?
>From whence arose those five forms,83 of which the rest were composed,
so aptly contributing to frame the mind and produce the senses? It 217is
tedious to go through all, as they are of such a sort that they look
more like things to be desired than to be discovered.
But, what is more remarkable, he gives us a world which has been not
only created, but, if I may so say, in a manner formed with hands, and
yet he says it is eternal. Do you conceive him to have the least skill
in natural philosophy who is capable of thinking anything to be
everlasting that had a beginning? For what can possibly ever have been
put together which cannot be dissolved again? Or what is there that had
a beginning which will not have an end? If your Providence, Lucilius, is
the same as Plato’s God, I ask you, as before, who were the assistants,
what were the engines, what was the plan and preparation of the whole
work? If it is not the same, then why did she make the world mortal, and
not everlasting, like Plato’s God?
IX. But I would demand of you both, why these world-builders started up
so suddenly, and lay dormant for so many ages? For we are not to
conclude that, if there was no world, there were therefore no ages. I do
not now speak of such ages as are finished by a certain number of days
and nights in annual courses; for I acknowledge that those could not be
without the revolution of the world; but there was a certain eternity
from infinite time, not measured by any circumscription of seasons; but
how that was in space we cannot understand, because we cannot possibly
have even the slightest idea of time before time was. I desire,
therefore, to know, Balbus, why this Providence of yours was idle for
such an immense space of time? Did she avoid labor? But that could have
no effect on the Deity; nor could there be any labor, since all nature,
air, fire, earth, and water would obey the divine essence. What was it
that incited the Deity to act the part of an Г¦dile, to illuminate and
decorate the world? If it was in order that God might be the better
accommodated in his habitation, then he must have been dwelling an
infinite length of time before in darkness as in a dungeon. But do we
imagine that he was afterward delighted with that variety with which we
see the heaven and earth adorned? What entertainment could that be to
the Deity? If it was any, he would not have been without it so long.
218Or were these things made, as you almost assert, by God for the sake of
men? Was it for the wise? If so, then this great design was adopted for
the sake of a very small number. Or for the sake of fools? First of all,
there was no reason why God should consult the advantage of the wicked;
and, further, what could be his object in doing so, since all fools are,
without doubt, the most miserable of men, chiefly because they are
fools? For what can we pronounce more deplorable than folly? Besides,
there are many inconveniences in life which the wise can learn to think
lightly of by dwelling rather on the advantages which they receive; but
which fools are unable to avoid when they are coming, or to bear when
they are come.
X. They who affirm the world to be an animated and intelligent being
have by no means discovered the nature of the mind, nor are able to
conceive in what form that essence can exist; but of that I shall speak
more hereafter. At present I must express my surprise at the weakness of
those who endeavor to make it out to be not only animated and immortal,
but likewise happy, and round, because Plato says that is the most
beautiful form; whereas I think a cylinder, a square, a cone, or a
pyramid more beautiful. But what life do they attribute to that round
Deity? Truly it is a being whirled about with a celerity to which
nothing can be even conceived by the imagination as equal; nor can I
imagine how a settled mind and happy life can consist in such motion,
the least degree of which would be troublesome to us. Why, therefore,
should it not be considered troublesome also to the Deity? For the earth
itself, as it is part of the world, is part also of the Deity. We see
vast tracts of land barren and uninhabitable; some, because they are
scorched by the too near approach of the sun; others, because they are
bound up with frost and snow, through the great distance which the sun
is from them. Therefore, if the world is a Deity, as these are parts of
the world, some of the Deity’s limbs must be said to be scorched, and
some frozen.
These are your doctrines, Lucilius; but what those of others are I will
endeavor to ascertain by tracing them back from the earliest of ancient
philosophers. Thales 219the Milesian, who first inquired after such
subjects, asserted water to be the origin of things, and that God was
that mind which formed all things from water. If the Gods can exist
without corporeal sense, and if there can be a mind without a body, why
did he annex a mind to water?
It was Anaximander’s opinion that the Gods were born; that after a great
length of time they died; and that they are innumerable worlds. But what
conception can we possibly have of a Deity who is not eternal?
Anaximenes, after him, taught that the air is God, and that he was
generated, and that he is immense, infinite, and always in motion; as if
air, which has no form, could possibly be God; for the Deity must
necessarily be not only of some form or other, but of the most beautiful
form. Besides, is not everything that had a beginning subject to
mortality?
XI. Anaxagoras, who received his learning from Anaximenes, was the first
who affirmed the system and disposition of all things to be contrived
and perfected by the power and reason of an infinite mind; in which
infinity he did not perceive that there could be no conjunction of sense
and motion, nor any sense in the least degree, where nature herself
could feel no impulse. If he would have this mind to be a sort of
animal, then there must be some more internal principle from whence that
animal should receive its appellation. But what can be more internal
than the mind? Let it, therefore, be clothed with an external body. But
this is not agreeable to his doctrine; but we are utterly unable to
conceive how a pure simple mind can exist without any substance annexed
to it.
Alcmæon of Crotona, in attributing a divinity to the sun, the moon, and
the rest of the stars, and also to the mind, did not perceive that he
was ascribing immortality to mortal beings.
Pythagoras, who supposed the Deity to be one soul, mixing with and
pervading all nature, from which our souls are taken, did not consider
that the Deity himself must, in consequence of this doctrine, be maimed
and torn with the rending every human soul from it; nor that, when the
human mind is afflicted (as is the case in many instances), that part of
the Deity must likewise be afflicted, 220which cannot be. If the human
mind were a Deity, how could it be ignorant of any thing? Besides, how
could that Deity, if it is nothing but soul, be mixed with, or infused
into, the world?
Then Xenophanes, who said that everything in the world which had any
existence, with the addition of intellect, was God, is as liable to
exception as the rest, especially in relation to the infinity of it, in
which there can be nothing sentient, nothing composite.
Parmenides formed a conceit to himself of something circular like a
crown. (He names it Stephane.) It is an orb of constant light and heat
around the heavens; this he calls God; in which there is no room to
imagine any divine form or sense. And he uttered many other absurdities
on the same subject; for he ascribed a divinity to war, to discord, to
lust, and other passions of the same kind, which are destroyed by
disease, or sleep, or oblivion, or age. The same honor he gives to the
stars; but I shall forbear making any objections to his system here,
having already done it in another place.
XII. Empedocles, who erred in many things, is most grossly mistaken in
his notion of the Gods. He lays down four natures84 as divine, from
which he thinks that all things were made. Yet it is evident that they
have a beginning, that they decay, and that they are void of all sense.
Protagoras did not seem to have any idea of the real nature of the Gods;
for he acknowledged that he was altogether ignorant whether there are or
are not any, or what they are.
What shall I say of Democritus, who classes our images of objects, and
their orbs, in the number of the Gods; as he does that principle through
which those images appear and have their influence? He deifies likewise
our knowledge and understanding. Is he not involved in a very great
error? And because nothing continues always in the same state, he denies
that anything is everlasting, does he not thereby entirely destroy the
Deity, and make it impossible to form any opinion of him?
221Diogenes of Apollonia looks upon the air to be a Deity. But what sense
can the air have? or what divine form can be attributed to it?
It would be tedious to show the uncertainty of Plato’s opinion; for, in
his Timæus, he denies the propriety of asserting that there is one great
father or creator of the world; and, in his book of Laws, he thinks we
ought not to make too strict an inquiry into the nature of the Deity.
And as for his statement when he asserts that God is a being without any
body—what the Greeks call ἀσώματος—it is certainly quite
unintelligible how that theory can possibly be true; for such a God must
then necessarily be destitute of sense, prudence, and pleasure; all
which things are comprehended in our notion of the Gods. He likewise
asserts in his Timæus, and in his Laws, that the world, the heavens, the
stars, the mind, and those Gods which are delivered down to us from our
ancestors, constitute the Deity. These opinions, taken separately, are
apparently false; and, together, are directly inconsistent with each
other.
Xenophon has committed almost the same mistakes, but in fewer words. In
those sayings which he has related of Socrates, he introduces him
disputing the lawfulness of inquiring into the form of the Deity, and
makes him assert the sun and the mind to be Deities: he represents him
likewise as affirming the being of one God only, and at another time of
many; which are errors of almost the same kind which I before took
notice of in Plato.
XIII. Antisthenes, in his book called the Natural Philosopher, says that
there are many national and one natural Deity; but by this saying he
destroys the power and nature of the Gods. Speusippus is not much less
in the wrong; who, following his uncle Plato, says that a certain
incorporeal power governs everything; by which he endeavors to root out
of our minds the knowledge of the Gods.
Aristotle, in his third book of Philosophy, confounds many things
together, as the rest have done; but he does not differ from his master
Plato. At one time he attributes all divinity to the mind, at another he
asserts that the world is God. Soon afterward he makes some other
essence 222preside over the world, and gives it those faculties by which,
with certain revolutions, he may govern and preserve the motion of it.
Then he asserts the heat of the firmament to be God; not perceiving the
firmament to be part of the world, which in another place he had
described as God. How can that divine sense of the firmament be
preserved in so rapid a motion? And where do the multitude of Gods
dwell, if heaven itself is a Deity? But when this philosopher says that
God is without a body, he makes him an irrational and insensible being.
Besides, how can the world move itself, if it wants a body? Or how, if
it is in perpetual self-motion, can it be easy and happy?
Xenocrates, his fellow-pupil, does not appear much wiser on this head,
for in his books concerning the nature of the Gods no divine form is
described; but he says the number of them is eight. Five are moving
planets;85 the sixth is contained in all the fixed stars; which,
dispersed, are so many several members, but, considered together, are
one single Deity; the seventh is the sun; and the eighth the moon. But
in what sense they can possibly be happy is not easy to be understood.
From the same school of Plato, Heraclides of Pontus stuffed his books
with puerile tales. Sometimes he thinks the world a Deity, at other
times the mind. He attributes divinity likewise to the wandering stars.
He deprives the Deity of sense, and makes his form mutable; and, in the
same book again, he makes earth and heaven Deities.
The unsteadiness of Theophrastus is equally intolerable. At one time he
attributes a divine prerogative to the mind; at another, to the
firmament; at another, to the stars and celestial constellations.
Nor is his disciple Strato, who is called the naturalist, any more
worthy to be regarded; for he thinks that the divine power is diffused
through nature, which is the cause of birth, increase, and diminution,
but that it has no sense nor form.
XIV. Zeno (to come to your sect, Balbus) thinks the law of nature to be
the divinity, and that it has the power 223to force us to what is right,
and to restrain us from what is wrong. How this law can be an animated
being I cannot conceive; but that God is so we would certainly maintain.
The same person says, in another place, that the sky is God; but can we
possibly conceive that God is a being insensible, deaf to our prayers,
our wishes, and our vows, and wholly unconnected with us? In other books
he thinks there is a certain rational essence pervading all nature,
indued with divine efficacy. He attributes the same power to the stars,
to the years, to the months, and to the seasons. In his interpretation
of Hesiod’s Theogony,86 he entirely destroys the established notions
of the Gods; for he excludes Jupiter, Juno, and Vesta, and those
esteemed divine, from the number of them; but his doctrine is that these
are names which by some kind of allusion are given to mute and inanimate
beings. The sentiments of his disciple Aristo are not less erroneous. He
thought it impossible to conceive the form of the Deity, and asserts
that the Gods are destitute of sense; and he is entirely dubious whether
the Deity is an animated being or not.
Cleanthes, who next comes under my notice, a disciple of Zeno at the
same time with Aristo, in one place says that the world is God; in
another, he attributes divinity to the mind and spirit of universal
nature; then he asserts that the most remote, the highest, the
all-surrounding, the all-enclosing and embracing heat, which is called
the sky, is most certainly the Deity. In the books he wrote against
pleasure, in which he seems to be raving, he imagines the Gods to have a
certain form and shape; then he ascribes all divinity to the stars; and,
lastly, he thinks nothing more divine than reason. So that this God,
whom we know mentally and in the speculations of our minds, from which
traces we receive our impression, has at last actually no visible form
at all.
XV. Persæus, another disciple of Zeno, says that they who have made
discoveries advantageous to the life of man should be esteemed as Gods;
and the very things, he says, which are healthful and beneficial have
derived their names from those of the Gods; so that he thinks it not
sufficient to call them the discoveries of Gods, but he urges that they
224themselves should be deemed divine. What can be more absurd than to
ascribe divine honors to sordid and deformed things; or to place among
the Gods men who are dead and mixed with the dust, to whose memory all
the respect that could be paid would be but mourning for their loss?
Chrysippus, who is looked upon as the most subtle interpreter of the
dreams of the Stoics, has mustered up a numerous band of unknown Gods;
and so unknown that we are not able to form any idea about them, though
our mind seems capable of framing any image to itself in its thoughts.
For he says that the divine power is placed in reason, and in the spirit
and mind of universal nature; that the world, with a universal effusion
of its spirit, is God; that the superior part of that spirit, which is
the mind and reason, is the great principle of nature, containing and
preserving the chain of all things; that the divinity is the power of
fate, and the necessity of future events. He deifies fire also, and what
I before called the ethereal spirit, and those elements which naturally
proceed from it—water, earth, and air. He attributes divinity to the
sun, moon, stars, and universal space, the grand container of all
things, and to those men likewise who have obtained immortality. He
maintains the sky to be what men call Jupiter; the air, which pervades
the sea, to be Neptune; and the earth, Ceres. In like manner he goes
through the names of the other Deities. He says that Jupiter is that
immutable and eternal law which guides and directs us in our manners;
and this he calls fatal necessity, the everlasting verity of future
events. But none of these are of such a nature as to seem to carry any
indication of divine virtue in them. These are the doctrines contained
in his first book of the Nature of the Gods. In the second, he endeavors
to accommodate the fables of Orpheus, Musæus, Hesiod, and Homer to what
he has advanced in the first, in order that the most ancient poets, who
never dreamed of these things, may seem to have been Stoics. Diogenes
the Babylonian was a follower of the doctrine of Chrysippus; and in that
book which he wrote, entitled “A Treatise concerning Minerva,” he
separates the account of Jupiter’s bringing-forth, and the birth of that
virgin, from the fabulous, and reduces it to a natural construction.
225XVI. Thus far have I been rather exposing the dreams of dotards than
giving the opinions of philosophers. Not much more absurd than these are
the fables of the poets, who owe all their power of doing harm to the
sweetness of their language; who have represented the Gods as enraged
with anger and inflamed with lust; who have brought before our eyes
their wars, battles, combats, wounds; their hatreds, dissensions,
discords, births, deaths, complaints, and lamentations; their
indulgences in all kinds of intemperance; their adulteries; their
chains; their amours with mortals, and mortals begotten by immortals. To
these idle and ridiculous flights of the poets we may add the prodigious
stories invented by the Magi, and by the Egyptians also, which were of
the same nature, together with the extravagant notions of the multitude
at all times, who, from total ignorance of the truth, are always
fluctuating in uncertainty.
Now, whoever reflects on the rashness and absurdity of these tenets must
inevitably entertain the highest respect and veneration for Epicurus,
and perhaps even rank him in the number of those beings who are the
subject of this dispute; for he alone first founded the idea of the
existence of the Gods on the impression which nature herself hath made
on the minds of all men. For what nation, what people are there, who
have not, without any learning, a natural idea, or prenotion, of a
Deity? Epicurus calls this ПЂПЃбЅ№О»О·П€О№П‚; that is, an antecedent conception
of the fact in the mind, without which nothing can be understood,
inquired after, or discoursed on; the force and advantage of which
reasoning we receive from that celestial volume of Epicurus concerning
the Rule and Judgment of Things.
XVII. Here, then, you see the foundation of this question clearly laid;
for since it is the constant and universal opinion of mankind,
independent of education, custom, or law, that there are Gods, it must
necessarily follow that this knowledge is implanted in our minds, or,
rather, innate in us. That opinion respecting which there is a general
agreement in universal nature must infallibly be true; therefore it must
be allowed that there are Gods; for in this we have the concurrence, not
only of almost all philosophers, but likewise of the ignorant and
illiterate. It 226must be also confessed that the point is established
that we have naturally this idea, as I said before, or prenotion, of the
existence of the Gods. As new things require new names, so that
prenotion was called ПЂПЃбЅ№О»О·П€О№П‚ by Epicurus; an appellation never used
before. On the same principle of reasoning, we think that the Gods are
happy and immortal; for that nature which hath assured us that there are
Gods has likewise imprinted in our minds the knowledge of their
immortality and felicity; and if so, what Epicurus hath declared in
these words is true: “That which is eternally happy cannot be burdened
with any labor itself, nor can it impose any labor on another; nor can
it be influenced by resentment or favor: because things which are liable
to such feelings must be weak and frail.” We have said enough to prove
that we should worship the Gods with piety, and without superstition, if
that were the only question.
For the superior and excellent nature of the Gods requires a pious
adoration from men, because it is possessed of immortality and the most
exalted felicity; for whatever excels has a right to veneration, and all
fear of the power and anger of the Gods should be banished; for we must
understand that anger and affection are inconsistent with the nature of
a happy and immortal being. These apprehensions being removed, no dread
of the superior powers remains. To confirm this opinion, our curiosity
leads us to inquire into the form and life and action of the intellect
and spirit of the Deity.
XVIII. With regard to his form, we are directed partly by nature and
partly by reason. All men are told by nature that none but a human form
can be ascribed to the Gods; for under what other image did it ever
appear to any one either sleeping or waking? and, without having
recourse to our first notions,87 reason itself declares the same; for
as it is easy to conceive that the most excellent nature, either because
of its happiness or immortality, should be the most beautiful, what
composition of limbs, what conformation of lineaments, what form, what
aspect, can be more beautiful than the human? Your sect, Lucilius (not
like my friend Cotta, who sometimes says one 227thing and sometimes
another), when they represent the divine art and workmanship in the
human body, are used to describe how very completely each member is
formed, not only for convenience, but also for beauty. Therefore, if the
human form excels that of all other animal beings, as God himself is an
animated being, he must surely be of that form which is the most
beautiful. Besides, the Gods are granted to be perfectly happy; and
nobody can be happy without virtue, nor can virtue exist where reason is
not; and reason can reside in none but the human form; the Gods,
therefore, must be acknowledged to be of human form; yet that form is
not body, but something like body; nor does it contain any blood, but
something like blood. Though these distinctions were more acutely
devised and more artfully expressed by Epicurus than any common capacity
can comprehend; yet, depending on your understanding, I shall be more
brief on the subject than otherwise I should be. Epicurus, who not only
discovered and understood the occult and almost hidden secrets of
nature, but explained them with ease, teaches that the power and nature
of the Gods is not to be discerned by the senses, but by the mind; nor
are they to be considered as bodies of any solidity, or reducible to
number, like those things which, because of their firmness, he calls
ОЈП„ОµПЃбЅіОјОЅО№О±;88 but as images, perceived by similitude and transition. As
infinite kinds of those images result from innumerable individuals, and
centre in the Gods, our minds and understanding are directed towards and
fixed with the greatest delight on them, in order to comprehend what
that happy and eternal essence is.
XIX. Surely the mighty power of the Infinite Being is most worthy our
great and earnest contemplation; the nature of which we must necessarily
understand to be such that everything in it is made to correspond
completely to some other answering part. This is called by Epicurus
бј°ПѓОїОЅОїОјбЅ·О±; that is to say, an equal distribution or even disposition of
things. From hence he draws this inference, 228that, as there is such a
vast multitude of mortals, there cannot be a less number of immortals;
and if those which perish are innumerable, those which are preserved
ought also to be countless. Your sect, Balbus, frequently ask us how the
Gods live, and how they pass their time? Their life is the most happy,
and the most abounding with all kinds of blessings, which can be
conceived. They do nothing. They are embarrassed with no business; nor
do they perform any work. They rejoice in the possession of their own
wisdom and virtue. They are satisfied that they shall ever enjoy the
fulness of eternal pleasures.
XX. Such a Deity may properly be called happy; but yours is a most
laborious God. For let us suppose the world a Deity—what can be a more
uneasy state than, without the least cessation, to be whirled about the
axle-tree of heaven with a surprising celerity? But nothing can be happy
that is not at ease. Or let us suppose a Deity residing in the world,
who directs and governs it, who preserves the courses of the stars, the
changes of the seasons, and the vicissitudes and orders of things,
surveying the earth and the sea, and accommodating them to the advantage
and necessities of man. Truly this Deity is embarrassed with a very
troublesome and laborious office. We make a happy life to consist in a
tranquillity of mind, a perfect freedom from care, and an exemption from
all employment. The philosopher from whom we received all our knowledge
has taught us that the world was made by nature; that there was no
occasion for a workhouse to frame it in; and that, though you deny the
possibility of such a work without divine skill, it is so easy to her,
that she has made, does make, and will make innumerable worlds. But,
because you do not conceive that nature is able to produce such effects
without some rational aid, you are forced, like the tragic poets, when
you cannot wind up your argument in any other way, to have recourse to a
Deity, whose assistance you would not seek, if you could view that vast
and unbounded magnitude of regions in all parts; where the mind,
extending and spreading itself, travels so far and wide that it can find
no end, no extremity to stop at. In this immensity of breadth, length,
and height, a most boundless company of innumerable atoms 229are
fluttering about, which, notwithstanding the interposition of a void
space, meet and cohere, and continue clinging to one another; and by
this union these modifications and forms of things arise, which, in your
opinions, could not possibly be made without the help of bellows and
anvils. Thus you have imposed on us an eternal master, whom we must
dread day and night. For who can be free from fear of a Deity who
foresees, regards, and takes notice of everything; one who thinks all
things his own; a curious, ever-busy God?
Hence first arose your О•бј±ОјО±ПЃОјбЅіОЅО·, as you call it, your fatal necessity;
so that, whatever happens, you affirm that it flows from an eternal
chain and continuance of causes. Of what value is this philosophy,
which, like old women and illiterate men, attributes everything to fate?
Then follows your ОјО±ОЅП„О№ОєбЅґ, in Latin called divinatio, divination;
which, if we would listen to you, would plunge us into such superstition
that we should fall down and worship your inspectors into sacrifices,
your augurs, your soothsayers, your prophets, and your fortune-tellers.
Epicurus having freed us from these terrors and restored us to liberty,
we have no dread of those beings whom we have reason to think entirely
free from all trouble themselves, and who do not impose any on others.
We pay our adoration, indeed, with piety and reverence to that essence
which is above all excellence and perfection. But I fear my zeal for
this doctrine has made me too prolix. However, I could not easily leave
so eminent and important a subject unfinished, though I must confess I
should rather endeavor to hear than speak so long.
XXI. Cotta, with his usual courtesy, then began. Velleius, says he, were
it not for something which you have advanced, I should have remained
silent; for I have often observed, as I did just now upon hearing you,
that I cannot so easily conceive why a proposition is true as why it is
false. Should you ask me what I take the nature of the Gods to be, I
should perhaps make no answer. But if you should ask whether I think it
to be of that nature which you have described, I should answer that I
was as far as possible from agreeing with you. However, before I enter
on the subject of your discourse and what you 230have advanced upon it, I
will give you my opinion of yourself. Your intimate friend, L. Crassus,
has been often heard by me to say that you were beyond all question
superior to all our learned Romans; and that few Epicureans in Greece
were to be compared to you. But as I knew what a wonderful esteem he had
for you, I imagined that might make him the more lavish in commendation
of you. Now, however, though I do not choose to praise any one when
present, yet I must confess that I think you have delivered your
thoughts clearly on an obscure and very intricate subject; that you are
not only copious in your sentiments, but more elegant in your language
than your sect generally are. When I was at Athens, I went often to hear
Zeno, by the advice of Philo, who used to call him the chief of the
Epicureans; partly, probably, in order to judge more easily how
completely those principles could be refuted after I had heard them
stated by the most learned of the Epicureans. And, indeed, he did not
speak in any ordinary manner; but, like you, with clearness, gravity,
and elegance; yet what frequently gave me great uneasiness when I heard
him, as it did while I attended to you, was to see so excellent a genius
falling into such frivolous (excuse my freedom), not to say foolish,
doctrines. However, I shall not at present offer anything better; for,
as I said before, we can in most subjects, especially in physics, sooner
discover what is not true than what is.
XXII. If you should ask me what God is, or what his character and nature
are, I should follow the example of Simonides, who, when Hiero the
tyrant proposed the same question to him, desired a day to consider of
it. When he required his answer the next day, Simonides begged two days
more; and as he kept constantly desiring double the number which he had
required before instead of giving his answer, Hiero, with surprise,
asked him his meaning in doing so: “Because,” says he, “the longer I
meditate on it, the more obscure it appears to me.” Simonides, who was
not only a delightful poet, but reputed a wise and learned man in other
branches of knowledge, found, I suppose, so many acute and refined
arguments occurring to him, that he was doubtful which was the truest,
and therefore despaired of discovering any truth.
231But does your Epicurus (for I had rather contend with him than with
you) say anything that is worthy the name of philosophy, or even of
common-sense?
In the question concerning the nature of the Gods, his first inquiry is,
whether there are Gods or not. It would be dangerous, I believe, to take
the negative side before a public auditory; but it is very safe in a
discourse of this kind, and in this company. I, who am a priest, and who
think that religions and ceremonies ought sacredly to be maintained, am
certainly desirous to have the existence of the Gods, which is the
principal point in debate, not only fixed in opinion, but proved to a
demonstration; for many notions flow into and disturb the mind which
sometimes seem to convince us that there are none. But see how candidly
I will behave to you: as I shall not touch upon those tenets you hold in
common with other philosophers, consequently I shall not dispute the
existence of the Gods, for that doctrine is agreeable to almost all men,
and to myself in particular; but I am still at liberty to find fault
with the reasons you give for it, which I think are very insufficient.
XXIII. You have said that the general assent of men of all nations and
all degrees is an argument strong enough to induce us to acknowledge the
being of the Gods. This is not only a weak, but a false, argument; for,
first of all, how do you know the opinions of all nations? I really
believe there are many people so savage that they have no thoughts of a
Deity. What think you of Diagoras, who was called the atheist; and of
Theodorus after him? Did not they plainly deny the very essence of a
Deity? Protagoras of Abdera, whom you just now mentioned, the greatest
sophist of his age, was banished by order of the Athenians from their
city and territories, and his books were publicly burned, because these
words were in the beginning of his treatise concerning the Gods: “I am
unable to arrive at any knowledge whether there are, or are not, any
Gods.” This treatment of him, I imagine, restrained many from professing
their disbelief of a Deity, since the doubt of it only could not escape
punishment. What shall we say of the sacrilegious, the impious, and the
perjured? If Tubulus Lucius, Lupus, or Carbo the son of 232Neptune, as
Lucilius says, had believed that there were Gods, would either of them
have carried his perjuries and impieties to such excess? Your reasoning,
therefore, to confirm your assertion is not so conclusive as you think
it is. But as this is the manner in which other philosophers have argued
on the same subject, I will take no further notice of it at present; I
rather choose to proceed to what is properly your own.
I allow that there are Gods. Instruct me, then, concerning their origin;
inform me where they are, what sort of body, what mind, they have, and
what is their course of life; for these I am desirous of knowing. You
attribute the most absolute power and efficacy to atoms. Out of them you
pretend that everything is made. But there are no atoms, for there is
nothing without body; every place is occupied by body, therefore there
can be no such thing as a vacuum or an atom.
XXIV. I advance these principles of the naturalists without knowing
whether they are true or false; yet they are more like truth than those
statements of yours; for they are the absurdities in which Democritus,
or before him Leucippus, used to indulge, saying that there are certain
light corpuscles—some smooth, some rough, some round, some square, some
crooked and bent as bows—which by a fortuitous concourse made heaven
and earth, without the influence of any natural power. This opinion, C.
Velleius, you have brought down to these our times; and you would sooner
be deprived of the greatest advantages of life than of that authority;
for before you were acquainted with those tenets, you thought that you
ought to profess yourself an Epicurean; so that it was necessary that
you should either embrace these absurdities or lose the philosophical
character which you had taken upon you; and what could bribe you to
renounce the Epicurean opinion? Nothing, you say, can prevail on you to
forsake the truth and the sure means of a happy life. But is that the
truth? for I shall not contest your happy life, which you think the
Deity himself does not enjoy unless he languishes in idleness. But where
is truth? Is it in your innumerable worlds, some of which are rising,
some falling, at every moment of time? Or is it in your atomical
corpuscles, 233which form such excellent works without the direction of
any natural power or reason? But I was forgetting my liberality, which I
had promised to exert in your case, and exceeding the bounds which I at
first proposed to myself. Granting, then, everything to be made of
atoms, what advantage is that to your argument? For we are searching
after the nature of the Gods; and allowing them to be made of atoms,
they cannot be eternal, because whatever is made of atoms must have had
a beginning: if so, there were no Gods till there was this beginning;
and if the Gods have had a beginning, they must necessarily have an end,
as you have before contended when you were discussing Plato’s world.
Where, then, is your beatitude and immortality, in which two words you
say that God is expressed, the endeavor to prove which reduces you to
the greatest perplexities? For you said that God had no body, but
something like body; and no blood, but something like blood.
XXV. It is a frequent practice among you, when you assert anything that
has no resemblance to truth, and wish to avoid reprehension, to advance
something else which is absolutely and utterly impossible, in order that
it may seem to your adversaries better to grant that point which has
been a matter of doubt than to keep on pertinaciously contradicting you
on every point: like Epicurus, who, when he found that if his atoms were
allowed to descend by their own weight, our actions could not be in our
own power, because their motions would be certain and necessary,
invented an expedient, which escaped Democritus, to avoid necessity. He
says that when the atoms descend by their own weight and gravity, they
move a little obliquely. Surely, to make such an assertion as this is
what one ought more to be ashamed of than the acknowledging ourselves
unable to defend the proposition. His practice is the same against the
logicians, who say that in all propositions in which yes or no is
required, one of them must be true; he was afraid that if this were
granted, then, in such a proposition as “Epicurus will be alive or dead
to-morrow,” either one or the other must necessarily be admitted;
therefore he absolutely denied the necessity of yes or no. Can anything
234show stupidity in a greater degree? Zeno,89 being pressed by
Arcesilas, who pronounced all things to be false which are perceived by
the senses, said that some things were false, but not all. Epicurus was
afraid that if any one thing seen should be false, nothing could be
true; and therefore he asserted all the senses to be infallible
directors of truth. Nothing can be more rash than this; for by
endeavoring to repel a light stroke, he receives a heavy blow. On the
subject of the nature of the Gods, he falls into the same errors. While
he would avoid the concretion of individual bodies, lest death and
dissolution should be the consequence, he denies that the Gods have
body, but says they have something like body; and says they have no
blood, but something like blood.
XXVI. It seems an unaccountable thing how one soothsayer can refrain
from laughing when he sees another. It is yet a greater wonder that you
can refrain from laughing among yourselves. It is no body, but something
like body! I could understand this if it were applied to statues made of
wax or clay; but in regard to the Deity, I am not able to discover what
is meant by a quasi-body or quasi-blood. Nor indeed are you, Velleius,
though you will not confess so much. For those precepts are delivered to
you as dictates which Epicurus carelessly blundered out; for he boasted,
as we see in his writings, that he had no instructor, which I could
easily believe without his public declaration of it, for the same reason
that I could believe the master of a very bad edifice if he were to
boast that he had no architect but himself: for there is nothing of the
Academy, nothing of the Lyceum, in his doctrine; nothing but
puerilities. He might have been a pupil of Xenocrates. O ye immortal
Gods, what a teacher was he! And there are those who believe that he
actually was his pupil; but he says otherwise, and I shall give more
credit to his word than to another’s. He confesses that he was a pupil
of a certain disciple of Plato, one Pamphilus, at Samos; for he lived
there when he was young, with his father and his brothers. His father,
Neocles, was a farmer in those parts; 235but as the farm, I suppose, was
not sufficient to maintain him, he turned school-master; yet Epicurus
treats this Platonic philosopher with wonderful contempt, so fearful was
he that it should be thought he had ever had any instruction. But it is
well known he had been a pupil of Nausiphanes, the follower of
Democritus; and since he could not deny it, he loaded him with insults
in abundance. If he never heard a lecture on these Democritean
principles, what lectures did he ever hear? What is there in Epicurus’s
physics that is not taken from Democritus? For though he altered some
things, as what I mentioned before of the oblique motions of the atoms,
yet most of his doctrines are the same; his atoms—his vacuum—his
images—infinity of space—innumerable worlds, their rise and decay—and
almost every part of natural learning that he treats of.
Now, do you understand what is meant by quasi-body and quasi-blood? For
I not only acknowledge that you are a better judge of it than I am, but
I can bear it without envy. If any sentiments, indeed, are communicated
without obscurity, what is there that Velleius can understand and Cotta
not? I know what body is, and what blood is; but I cannot possibly find
out the meaning of quasi-body and quasi-blood. Not that you
intentionally conceal your principles from me, as Pythagoras did his
from those who were not his disciples; or that you are intentionally
obscure, like Heraclitus. But the truth is (which I may venture to say
in this company), you do not understand them yourself.
XXVII. This, I perceive, is what you contend for, that the Gods have a
certain figure that has nothing concrete, nothing solid, nothing of
express substance, nothing prominent in it; but that it is pure, smooth,
and transparent. Let us suppose the same with the Venus of Cos, which is
not a body, but the representation of a body; nor is the red, which is
drawn there and mixed with the white, real blood, but a certain
resemblance of blood; so in Epicurus’s Deity there is no real substance,
but the resemblance of substance.
Let me take for granted that which is perfectly unintelligible; then
tell me what are the lineaments and figures 236of these sketched-out
Deities. Here you have plenty of arguments by which you would show the
Gods to be in human form. The first is, that our minds are so
anticipated and prepossessed, that whenever we think of a Deity the
human shape occurs to us. The next is, that as the divine nature excels
all things, so it ought to be of the most beautiful form, and there is
no form more beautiful than the human; and the third is, that reason
cannot reside in any other shape.
First, let us consider each argument separately. You seem to me to
assume a principle, despotically I may say, that has no manner of
probability in it. Who was ever so blind, in contemplating these
subjects, as not to see that the Gods were represented in human form,
either by the particular advice of wise men, who thought by those means
the more easily to turn the minds of the ignorant from a depravity of
manners to the worship of the Gods; or through superstition, which was
the cause of their believing that when they were paying adoration to
these images they were approaching the Gods themselves. These conceits
were not a little improved by the poets, painters, and artificers; for
it would not have been very easy to represent the Gods planning and
executing any work in another form, and perhaps this opinion arose from
the idea which mankind have of their own beauty. But do not you, who are
so great an adept in physics, see what a soothing flatterer, what a sort
of procuress, nature is to herself? Do you think there is any creature
on the land or in the sea that is not highly delighted with its own
form? If it were not so, why would not a bull become enamored of a mare,
or a horse of a cow? Do you believe an eagle, a lion, or a dolphin
prefers any shape to its own? If nature, therefore, has instructed us in
the same manner, that nothing is more beautiful than man, what wonder is
it that we, for that reason, should imagine the Gods are of the human
form? Do you suppose if beasts were endowed with reason that every one
would not give the prize of beauty to his own species?
XXVIII. Yet, by Hercules (I speak as I think)! though I am fond enough
of myself, I dare not say that I excel in beauty that bull which carried
Europa. For the question 237here is not concerning our genius and
elocution, but our species and figure. If we could make and assume to
ourselves any form, would you be unwilling to resemble the sea-triton as
he is painted supported swimming on sea-monsters whose bodies are partly
human? Here I touch on a difficult point; for so great is the force of
nature that there is no man who would not choose to be like a man, nor,
indeed, any ant that would not be like an ant. But like what man? For
how few can pretend to beauty! When I was at Athens, the whole flock of
youths afforded scarcely one. You laugh, I see; but what I tell you is
the truth. Nay, to us who, after the examples of ancient philosophers,
delight in boys, defects are often pleasing. Alcæus was charmed with a
wart on a boy’s knuckle; but a wart is a blemish on the body; yet it
seemed a beauty to him. Q. Catulus, my friend and colleague’s father,
was enamored with your fellow-citizen Roscius, on whom he wrote these
verses:
As once I stood to hail the rising day,
Roscius appearing on the left I spied:
Forgive me, Gods, if I presume to say
The mortal’s beauty with th’ immortal vied.
Roscius more beautiful than a God! yet he was then, as he now is,
squint-eyed. But what signifies that, if his defects were beauties to
Catulus?
XXIX. I return to the Gods. Can we suppose any of them to be
squint-eyed, or even to have a cast in the eye? Have they any warts? Are
any of them hook-nosed, flap-eared, beetle-browed, or jolt-headed, as
some of us are? Or are they free from imperfections? Let us grant you
that. Are they all alike in the face? For if they are many, then one
must necessarily be more beautiful than another, and then there must be
some Deity not absolutely most beautiful. Or if their faces are all
alike, there would be an Academy90 in heaven; for if one God does not
differ from another, there is no possibility of knowing or
distinguishing them.
What if your assertion, Velleius, proves absolutely false, that no form
occurs to us, in our contemplations on the 238Deity, but the human? Will
you, notwithstanding that, persist in the defence of such an absurdity?
Supposing that form occurs to us, as you say it does, and we know
Jupiter, Juno, Minerva, Neptune, Vulcan, Apollo, and the other Deities,
by the countenance which painters and statuaries have given them, and
not only by their countenances, but by their decorations, their age, and
attire; yet the Egyptians, the Syrians, and almost all barbarous
nations,91 are without such distinctions. You may see a greater regard
paid by them to certain beasts than by us to the most sacred temples and
images of the Gods; for many shrines have been rifled, and images of the
Deities have been carried from their most sacred places by us; but we
never heard that an Egyptian offered any violence to a crocodile, an
ibis, or a cat. What do you think, then? Do not the Egyptians esteem
their sacred bull, their Apis, as a Deity? Yes, by Hercules! as
certainly as you do our protectress Juno, whom you never behold, even in
your dreams, without a goat-skin, a spear, a shield, and broad sandals.
But the Grecian Juno of Argos and the Roman Juno are not represented in
this manner; so that the Grecians, the Lanuvinians, and we, ascribe
different forms to Juno; and our Capitoline Jupiter is not the same with
the Jupiter Ammon of the Africans.
XXX. Therefore, ought not a natural philosopher—that is, an inquirer
into the secrets of nature—to be ashamed of seeking a testimony to
truth from minds prepossessed by custom? According to the rule you have
laid down, it may be said that Jupiter is always bearded, Apollo always
beardless; that Minerva has gray and Neptune azure eyes; and, indeed, we
must then honor that Vulcan at Athens, made by Alcamenes, whose lameness
through his thin robes appears to be no deformity. Shall we, therefore,
receive a lame Deity because we have such an account of him?
Consider, likewise, that the Gods go by what names we give them. Now, in
the first place, they have as many names as men have languages; for
Vulcan is not called Vulcan in Italy, Africa, or Spain, as you are
called Velleius in all countries. Besides, the Gods are innumerable,
though the list of their names is of no great length even 239in the
records of our priests. Have they no names? You must necessarily
confess, indeed, they have none; for what occasion is there for
different names if their persons are alike?
How much more laudable would it be, Velleius, to acknowledge that you do
not know what you do not know than to follow a man whom you must
despise! Do you think the Deity is like either me or you? You do not
really think he is like either of us. What is to be done, then? Shall I
call the sun, the moon, or the sky a Deity? If so, they are consequently
happy. But what pleasures can they enjoy? And they are wise too. But how
can wisdom reside in such shapes? These are your own principles.
Therefore, if they are not of human form, as I have proved, and if you
cannot persuade yourself that they are of any other, why are you
cautious of denying absolutely the being of any Gods? You dare not deny
it—which is very prudent in you, though here you are not afraid of the
people, but of the Gods themselves. I have known Epicureans who
reverence92 even the least images of the Gods, though I perceive it to
be the opinion of some that Epicurus, through fear of offending against
the Athenian laws, has allowed a Deity in words and destroyed him in
fact; so in those his select and short sentences, which are called by
you κυρίαι δόξαι,93 this, I think, is the first: “That being which is
happy and immortal is not burdened with any labor, and does not impose
any on any one else.”
XXXI. In his statement of this sentence, some think that he avoided
speaking clearly on purpose, though it was manifestly without design.
But they judge ill of a man who had not the least art. It is doubtful
whether he means that there is any being happy and immortal, or that if
there is any being happy, he must likewise be immortal. They do not
consider that he speaks here, indeed, ambiguously; but in many other
places both he and Metrodorus explain themselves as clearly as you have
done. But he believed there are Gods; nor have I ever seen any one 240who
was more exceedingly afraid of what he declared ought to be no objects
of fear, namely, death and the Gods, with the apprehensions of which the
common rank of people are very little affected; but he says that the
minds of all mortals are terrified by them. Many thousands of men commit
robberies in the face of death; others rifle all the temples they can
get into: such as these, no doubt, must be greatly terrified, the one by
the fears of death, and the others by the fear of the Gods.
But since you dare not (for I am now addressing my discourse to Epicurus
himself) absolutely deny the existence of the Gods, what hinders you
from ascribing a divine nature to the sun, the world, or some eternal
mind? I never, says he, saw wisdom and a rational soul in any but a
human form. What! did you ever observe anything like the sun, the moon,
or the five moving planets? The sun, terminating his course in two
extreme parts of one circle,94 finishes his annual revolutions. The
moon, receiving her light from the sun, completes the same course in
the space of a month.95 The five planets in the same circle, some
nearer, others more remote from the earth, begin the same courses
together, and finish them in different spaces of time. Did you ever
observe anything like this, Epicurus? So that, according to you, there
can be neither sun, moon, nor stars, because nothing can exist but what
we have touched or seen.96 What! have you ever seen the Deity himself?
Why else do you believe there is any? If this doctrine prevails, we must
reject all that history relates or reason discovers; and the people who
inhabit inland countries must not believe there is such a thing as the
sea. This is so narrow a way of thinking that if you had been born in
Seriphus, and never had been from out of that island, where you had
frequently been in the habit of seeing little hares and foxes, you would
not, therefore, believe that there are such beasts as lions and
panthers; 241and if any one should describe an elephant to you, you would
think that he designed to laugh at you.
XXXII. You indeed, Velleius, have concluded your argument, not after the
manner of your own sect, but of the logicians, to which your people are
utter strangers. You have taken it for granted that the Gods are happy.
I allow it. You say that without virtue no one can be happy. I willingly
concur with you in this also. You likewise say that virtue cannot reside
where reason is not. That I must necessarily allow. You add, moreover,
that reason cannot exist but in a human form. Who, do you think, will
admit that? If it were true, what occasion was there to come so
gradually to it? And to what purpose? You might have answered it on your
own authority. I perceive your gradations from happiness to virtue, and
from virtue to reason; but how do you come from reason to human form?
There, indeed, you do not descend by degrees, but precipitately.
Nor can I conceive why Epicurus should rather say the Gods are like men
than that men are like the Gods. You ask what is the difference; for,
say you, if this is like that, that is like this. I grant it; but this I
assert, that the Gods could not take their form from men; for the Gods
always existed, and never had a beginning, if they are to exist
eternally; but men had a beginning: therefore that form, of which the
immortal Gods are, must have had existence before mankind; consequently,
the Gods should not be said to be of human form, but our form should be
called divine. However, let this be as you will. I now inquire how this
extraordinary good fortune came about; for you deny that reason had any
share in the formation of things. But still, what was this extraordinary
fortune? Whence proceeded that happy concourse of atoms which gave so
sudden a rise to men in the form of Gods? Are we to suppose the divine
seed fell from heaven upon earth, and that men sprung up in the likeness
of their celestial sires? I wish you would assert it; for I should not
be unwilling to acknowledge my relation to the Gods. But you say nothing
like it; no, our resemblance to the Gods, it seems, was by chance. Must
I now seek for arguments to refute this doctrine seriously? I wish I
could 242as easily discover what is true as I can overthrow what is false.
XXXIII. You have enumerated with so ready a memory, and so copiously,
the opinions of philosophers, from Thales the Milesian, concerning the
nature of the Gods, that I am surprised to see so much learning in a
Roman. But do you think they were all madmen who thought that a Deity
could by some possibility exist without hands and feet? Does not even
this consideration have weight with you when you consider what is the
use and advantage of limbs in men, and lead you to admit that the Gods
have no need of them? What necessity can there be of feet, without
walking; or of hands, if there is nothing to be grasped? The same may be
asked of the other parts of the body, in which nothing is vain, nothing
useless, nothing superfluous; therefore we may infer that no art can
imitate the skill of nature. Shall the Deity, then, have a tongue, and
not speak—teeth, palate, and jaws, though he will have no use for them?
Shall the members which nature has given to the body for the sake of
generation be useless to the Deity? Nor would the internal parts be less
superfluous than the external. What comeliness is there in the heart,
the lungs, the liver, and the rest of them, abstracted from their use? I
mention these because you place them in the Deity on account of the
beauty of the human form.
Depending on these dreams, not only Epicurus, Metrodorus, and Hermachus
declaimed against Pythagoras, Plato, and Empedocles, but that little
harlot Leontium presumed to write against Theophrastus: indeed, she had
a neat Attic style; but yet, to think of her arguing against
Theophrastus! So much did the garden of Epicurus97 abound with these
liberties, and, indeed, you are always complaining against them. Zeno
wrangled. Why need I mention Albutius? Nothing could be more elegant or
humane than Phædrus; yet a sharp expression would disgust the old man.
Epicurus treated Aristotle with great contumely. He foully slandered
Phædo, the disciple of Socrates. He pelted Timocrates, the brother of
his companion Metrodorus, with whole volumes, because he disagreed with
him in some trifling point of philosophy. He 243was ungrateful even to
Democritus, whose follower he was; and his master Nausiphanes, from whom
he learned nothing, had no better treatment from him.
XXXIV. Zeno gave abusive language not only to those who were then
living, as Apollodorus, Syllus, and the rest, but he called Socrates,
who was the father of philosophy, the Attic buffoon, using the Latin
word Scurra. He never called Chrysippus by any name but Chesippus. And
you yourself a little before, when you were numbering up a senate, as we
may call them, of philosophers, scrupled not to say that the most
eminent men talked like foolish, visionary dotards. Certainly,
therefore, if they have all erred in regard to the nature of the Gods,
it is to be feared there are no such beings. What you deliver on that
head are all whimsical notions, and not worthy the consideration even of
old women. For you do not seem to be in the least aware what a task you
draw on yourselves, if you should prevail on us to grant that the same
form is common to Gods and men. The Deity would then require the same
trouble in dressing, and the same care of the body, that mankind does.
He must walk, run, lie down, lean, sit, hold, speak, and discourse. You
need not be told the consequence of making the Gods male and female.
Therefore I cannot sufficiently wonder how this chief of yours came to
entertain these strange opinions. But you constantly insist on the
certainty of this tenet, that the Deity is both happy and immortal.
Supposing he is so, would his happiness be less perfect if he had not
two feet? Or cannot that blessedness or beatitude—call it which you
will (they are both harsh terms, but we must mollify them by use)—can
it not, I say, exist in that sun, or in this world, or in some eternal
mind that has not human shape or limbs? All you say against it is, that
you never saw any happiness in the sun or the world. What, then? Did you
ever see any world but this? No, you will say. Why, therefore, do you
presume to assert that there are not only six hundred thousand worlds,
but that they are innumerable? Reason tells you so. Will not reason tell
you likewise that as, in our inquiries into the most excellent nature,
we find none but the divine nature can be happy and eternal, so the same
divine nature surpasses us in
244excellence of mind; and as in mind, so in body? Why,
therefore, as we are inferior in all other respects, should
we be equal in form? For human virtue approaches
nearer to the divinity than human form.
XXXV. To return to the subject I was upon. What
can be more childish than to assert that there are no such
creatures as are generated in the Red Sea or in India?
The most curious inquirer cannot arrive at the knowledge
of all those creatures which inhabit the earth, sea, fens, and
rivers; and shall we deny the existence of them because
we never saw them? That similitude which you are so
very fond of is nothing to the purpose. Is not a dog like
a wolf? And, as Ennius says,
The monkey, filthiest beast, how like to man!
Yet they differ in nature. No beast has more sagacity
than an elephant; yet where can you find any of a larger
size? I am speaking here of beasts. But among men, do
we not see a disparity of manners in persons very much
alike, and a similitude of manners in persons unlike? If
this sort of argument were once to prevail, Velleius, observe
what it would lead to. You have laid it down as
certain that reason cannot possibly reside in any but the
human form. Another may affirm that it can exist in none
but a terrestrial being; in none but a being that is born,
that grows up, and receives instruction, and that consists
of a soul, and an infirm and perishable body; in short, in
none but a mortal man. But if you decline those opinions,
why should a single form disturb you? You perceive
that man is possessed of reason and understanding, with
all the infirmities which I have mentioned interwoven
with his being; abstracted from which, you nevertheless
know God, you say, if the lineaments do but remain.
This is not talking considerately, but at a venture; for
surely you did not think what an encumbrance anything
superfluous or useless is, not only in a man, but a tree.
How troublesome it is to have a finger too much! And
why so? Because neither use nor ornament requires
more than five; but your Deity has not only a finger more
than he wants, but a head, a neck, shoulders, sides, a
paunch, back, hams, hands, feet, thighs, and legs. Are
245these parts necessary to immortality? Are they conducive
to the existence of the Deity? Is the face itself of
use? One would rather say so of the brain, the heart,
the lights, and the liver; for these are the seats of life.
The features of the face contribute nothing to the preservation
of it.
XXXVI. You censured those who, beholding those excellent
and stupendous works, the world, and its respective
parts—the heaven, the earth, the seas—and the splendor
with which they are adorned; who, contemplating the
sun, moon, and stars; and who, observing the maturity
and changes of the seasons, and vicissitudes of times, inferred
from thence that there must be some excellent and
eminent essence that originally made, and still moves, directs,
and governs them. Suppose they should mistake in
their conjecture, yet I see what they aim at. But what is
that great and noble work which appears to you to be the
effect of a divine mind, and from which you conclude that
there are Gods? “I have,” say you, “a certain information
of a Deity imprinted in my mind.” Of a bearded
Jupiter, I suppose, and a helmeted Minerva.
But do you really imagine them to be such? How
much better are the notions of the ignorant vulgar, who
not only believe the Deities have members like ours, but
that they make use of them; and therefore they assign
them a bow and arrows, a spear, a shield, a trident, and
lightning; and though they do not behold the actions of
the Gods, yet they cannot entertain a thought of a Deity
doing nothing. The Egyptians (so much ridiculed) held
no beasts to be sacred, except on account of some advantage
which they had received from them. The ibis, a very
large bird, with strong legs and a horny long beak, destroys
a great number of serpents. These birds keep
Egypt from pestilential diseases by killing and devouring
the flying serpents brought from the deserts of Lybia by
the south-west wind, which prevents the mischief that
may attend their biting while alive, or any infection when
dead. I could speak of the advantage of the ichneumon,
the crocodile, and the cat; but I am unwilling to be tedious;
yet I will conclude with observing that the barbarians
paid divine honors to beasts because of the benefits
246they received from them; whereas your
Gods not only confer no benefit, but are idle, and do no single act of
any description whatever.
XXXVII. “They have nothing to do,” your teacher says. Epicurus truly,
like indolent boys, thinks nothing preferable to idleness; yet those
very boys, when they have a holiday, entertain themselves in some
sportive exercise. But we are to suppose the Deity in such an inactive
state that if he should move we may justly fear he would be no longer
happy. This doctrine divests the Gods of motion and operation; besides,
it encourages men to be lazy, as they are by this taught to believe that
the least labor is incompatible even with divine felicity.
But let it be as you would have it, that the Deity is in the form and
image of a man. Where is his abode? Where is his habitation? Where is
the place where he is to be found? What is his course of life? And what
is it that constitutes the happiness which you assert that he enjoys?
For it seems necessary that a being who is to be happy must use and
enjoy what belongs to him. And with regard to place, even those natures
which are inanimate have each their proper stations assigned to them: so
that the earth is the lowest; then water is next above the earth; the
air is above the water; and fire has the highest situation of all
allotted to it. Some creatures inhabit the earth, some the water, and
some, of an amphibious nature, live in both. There are some, also, which
are thought to be born in fire, and which often appear fluttering in
burning furnaces.
In the first place, therefore, I ask you, Where is the habitation of
your Deity? Secondly, What motive is it that stirs him from his place,
supposing he ever moves? And, lastly, since it is peculiar to animated
beings to have an inclination to something that is agreeable to their
several natures, what is it that the Deity affects, and to what purpose
does he exert the motion of his mind and reason? In short, how is he
happy? how eternal? Whichever of these points you touch upon, I am
afraid you will come lamely off. For there is never a proper end to
reasoning which proceeds on a false foundation; for you asserted
likewise that the form of the Deity is perceptible by the mind, but 247not
by sense; that it is neither solid, nor invariable in number; that it is
to be discerned by similitude and transition, and that a constant supply
of images is perpetually flowing on from innumerable atoms, on which our
minds are intent; so that we from that conclude that divine nature to be
happy and everlasting.
XXXVIII. What, in the name of those Deities concerning whom we are now
disputing, is the meaning of all this? For if they exist only in
thought, and have no solidity nor substance, what difference can there
be between thinking of a Hippocentaur and thinking of a Deity? Other
philosophers call every such conformation of the mind a vain motion; but
you term it “the approach and entrance of images into the mind.” Thus,
when I imagine that I behold T. Gracchus haranguing the people in the
Capitol, and collecting their suffrages concerning M. Octavius, I call
that a vain motion of the mind: but you affirm that the images of
Gracchus and Octavius are present, which are only conveyed to my mind
when they have arrived at the Capitol. The case is the same, you say, in
regard to the Deity, with the frequent representation of which the mind
is so affected that from thence it may be clearly understood that the
Gods98 are happy and eternal.
Let it be granted that there are images by which the mind is affected,
yet it is only a certain form that occurs; and why must that form be
pronounced happy? why eternal? But what are those images you talk of,
or whence do they proceed? This loose manner of arguing is taken from
Democritus; but he is reproved by many people for it; nor can you derive
any conclusions from it: the whole system is weak and imperfect. For
what can be more improbable than that the images of Homer, Archilochus,
Romulus, Numa, Pythagoras, and Plato should come into my mind, and yet
not in the form in which they existed? How, therefore, can they be those
persons? And whose images are they? Aristotle tells us that there never
was such a person as Orpheus the poet;99 and it is said that the verse
248called Orphic verse was the invention of Cercops, a Pythagorean; yet
Orpheus, that is to say, the image of him, as you will have it, often
runs in my head. What is the reason that I entertain one idea of the
figure of the same person, and you another? Why do we image to ourselves
such things as never had any existence, and which never can have, such
as Scyllas and Chimæras? Why do we frame ideas of men, countries, and
cities which we never saw? How is it that the very first moment that I
choose I can form representations of them in my mind? How is it that
they come to me, even in my sleep, without being called or sought after?
XXXIX. The whole affair, Velleius, is ridiculous. You do not impose
images on our eyes only, but on our minds. Such is the privilege which
you have assumed of talking nonsense with impunity. But there is, you
say, a transition of images flowing on in great crowds in such a way
that out of many some one at least must be perceived! I should be
ashamed of my incapacity to understand this if you, who assert it, could
comprehend it yourselves; for how do you prove that these images are
continued in uninterrupted motion? Or, if uninterrupted, still how do
you prove them to be eternal? There is a constant supply, you say, of
innumerable atoms. But must they, for that reason, be all eternal? To
elude this, you have recourse to equilibration (for so, with your leave,
I will call your бјёПѓОїОЅОїОјбЅ·О±),100 and say that as there is a sort of
nature mortal, so there must also be a sort which is immortal. By the
same rule, as there are men mortal, there are men immortal; and as some
arise from the earth, some must arise from the water also; and as there
are causes which destroy, there must likewise be causes which preserve.
Be it as you say; but let those causes preserve which have existence
themselves. I cannot conceive these your Gods to have any. But how does
all this face of things arise from atomic corpuscles? Were there any
such atoms (as there 249are not), they might perhaps impel one another,
and be jumbled together in their motion; but they could never be able to
impart form, or figure, or color, or animation, so that you by no means
demonstrate the immortality of your Deity.
XL. Let us now inquire into his happiness. It is certain that without
virtue there can be no happiness; but virtue consists in action: now
your Deity does nothing; therefore he is void of virtue, and
consequently cannot be happy. What sort of life does he lead? He has a
constant supply, you say, of good things, without any intermixture of
bad. What are those good things? Sensual pleasures, no doubt; for you
know no delight of the mind but what arises from the body, and returns
to it. I do not suppose, Velleius, that you are like some of the
Epicureans, who are ashamed of those expressions of Epicurus,101 in
which he openly avows that he has no idea of any good separate from
wanton and obscene pleasures, which, without a blush, he names
distinctly. What food, therefore, what drink, what variety of music or
flowers, what kind of pleasures of touch, what odors, will you offer to
the Gods to fill them with pleasures? The poets indeed provide them with
banquets of nectar and ambrosia, and a Hebe or a Ganymede to serve up
the cup. But what is it, Epicurus, that you do for them? For I do not
see from whence your Deity should have those things, nor how he could
use them. Therefore the nature of man is better constituted for a happy
life than the nature of the Gods, because men enjoy various kinds of
pleasures; but you look on all those pleasures as superficial which
delight the senses only by a titillation, as Epicurus calls it. Where is
to be the end of this trifling? Even Philo, who followed the Academy,
could not bear to hear the soft and luscious delights of the Epicureans
despised; for with his admirable memory he perfectly remembered and used
to repeat many sentences of Epicurus in the very words in which they
were written. He likewise used to quote many, 250which were more gross,
from Metrodorus, the sage colleague of Epicurus, who blamed his brother
Timocrates because he would not allow that everything which had any
reference to a happy life was to be measured by the belly; nor has he
said this once only, but often. You grant what I say, I perceive; for
you know it to be true. I can produce the books, if you should deny it;
but I am not now reproving you for referring all things to the standard
of pleasure: that is another question. What I am now showing is, that
your Gods are destitute of pleasure; and therefore, according to your
own manner of reasoning, they are not happy.
XLI. But they are free from pain. Is that sufficient for beings who are
supposed to enjoy all good things and the most supreme felicity? The
Deity, they say, is constantly meditating on his own happiness, for he
has no other idea which can possibly occupy his mind. Consider a little;
reflect what a figure the Deity would make if he were to be idly
thinking of nothing through all eternity but “It is very well with me,
and I am happy;” nor do I see why this happy Deity should not fear being
destroyed, since, without any intermission, he is driven and agitated by
an everlasting incursion of atoms, and since images are constantly
floating off from him. Your Deity, therefore, is neither happy nor
eternal.
Epicurus, it seems, has written books concerning sanctity and piety
towards the Gods. But how does he speak on these subjects? You would say
that you were listening to Coruncanius or Scævola, the high-priests, and
not to a man who tore up all religion by the roots, and who overthrew
the temples and altars of the immortal Gods; not, indeed, with hands,
like Xerxes, but with arguments; for what reason is there for your
saying that men ought to worship the Gods, when the Gods not only do not
regard men, but are entirely careless of everything, and absolutely do
nothing at all?
But they are, you say, of so glorious and excellent a nature that a wise
man is induced by their excellence to adore them. Can there be any glory
or excellence in that nature which only contemplates its own happiness,
and neither will do, nor does, nor ever did anything? Besides, 251what
piety is due to a being from whom you receive nothing? Or how can you,
or any one else, be indebted to him who bestows no benefits? For piety
is only justice towards the Gods; but what right have they to it, when
there is no communication whatever between the Gods and men? And
sanctity is the knowledge of how we ought to worship them; but I do not
understand why they are to be worshipped, if we are neither to receive
nor expect any good from them.
XLII. And why should we worship them from an admiration only of that
nature in which we can behold nothing excellent? and as for that freedom
from superstition, which you are in the habit of boasting of so much, it
is easy to be free from that feeling when you have renounced all belief
in the power of the Gods; unless, indeed, you imagine that Diagoras or
Theodorus, who absolutely denied the being of the Gods, could possibly
be superstitious. I do not suppose that even Protagoras could, who
doubted whether there were Gods or not. The opinions of these
philosophers are not only destructive of superstition, which arises from
a vain fear of the Gods, but of religion also, which consists in a pious
adoration of them.
What think you of those who have asserted that the whole doctrine
concerning the immortal Gods was the invention of politicians, whose
view was to govern that part of the community by religion which reason
could not influence? Are not their opinions subversive of all religion?
Or what religion did Prodicus the Chian leave to men, who held that
everything beneficial to human life should be numbered among the Gods?
Were not they likewise void of religion who taught that the Deities, at
present the object of our prayers and adoration, were valiant,
illustrious, and mighty men who arose to divinity after death?
Euhemerus, whom our Ennius translated, and followed more than other
authors, has particularly advanced this doctrine, and treated of the
deaths and burials of the Gods; can he, then, be said to have confirmed
religion, or, rather, to have totally subverted it? I shall say nothing
of that sacred and august Eleusina, into whose mysteries the most
distant nations were initiated, 252nor of the solemnities in Samothrace,
or in Lemnos, secretly resorted to by night, and surrounded by thick and
shady groves; which, if they were properly explained, and reduced to
reasonable principles, would rather explain the nature of things than
discover the knowledge of the Gods.
XLIII. Even that great man Democritus, from whose fountains Epicurus
watered his little garden, seems to me to be very inferior to his usual
acuteness when speaking about the nature of the Gods. For at one time he
thinks that there are images endowed with divinity, inherent in the
universality of things; at another, that the principles and minds
contained in the universe are Gods; then he attributes divinity to
animated images, employing themselves in doing us good or harm; and,
lastly, he speaks of certain images of such vast extent that they
encompass the whole outside of the universe; all which opinions are more
worthy of the country102 of Democritus than of Democritus himself; for
who can frame in his mind any ideas of such images? who can admire them?
who can think they merit a religious adoration?
But Epicurus, when he divests the Gods of the power of doing good,
extirpates all religion from the minds of men; for though he says the
divine nature is the best and the most excellent of all natures, he will
not allow it to be susceptible of any benevolence, by which he destroys
the chief and peculiar attribute of the most perfect being. For what is
better and more excellent than goodness and beneficence? To refuse your
Gods that quality is to say that no man is any object of their favor,
and no Gods either; that they neither love nor esteem any one; in short,
that they not only give themselves no trouble about us, but even look on
each other with the greatest indifference.
XLIV. How much more reasonable is the doctrine of the Stoics, whom you
censure? It is one of their maxims that the wise are friends to the
wise, though unknown to each other; for as nothing is more amiable than
virtue, he who possesses it is worthy our love, to whatever country 253he
belongs. But what evils do your principles bring, when you make good
actions and benevolence the marks of imbecility! For, not to mention the
power and nature of the Gods, you hold that even men, if they had no
need of mutual assistance, would be neither courteous nor beneficent. Is
there no natural charity in the dispositions of good men? The very name
of love, from which friendship is derived, is dear to men;103 and if
friendship is to centre in our own advantage only, without regard to him
whom we esteem a friend, it cannot be called friendship, but a sort of
traffic for our own profit. Pastures, lands, and herds of cattle are
valued in the same manner on account of the profit we gather from them;
but charity and friendship expect no return. How much more reason have
we to think that the Gods, who want nothing, should love each other, and
employ themselves about us! If it were not so, why should we pray to or
adore them? Why do the priests preside over the altars, and the augurs
over the auspices? What have we to ask of the Gods, and why do we prefer
our vows to them?
But Epicurus, you say, has written a book concerning sanctity. A
trifling performance by a man whose wit is not so remarkable in it, as
the unrestrained license of writing which he has permitted himself; for
what sanctity can there be if the Gods take no care of human affairs? Or
how can that nature be called animated which neither regards nor
performs anything? Therefore our friend Posidonius has well observed, in
his fifth book of the Nature of the Gods, that Epicurus believed there
were no Gods, and that what he had said about the immortal Gods was only
said from a desire to avoid unpopularity. He could not be so weak as to
imagine that the Deity has only the outward features of a simple mortal,
without any real solidity; that he has all the members of a man, without
the least power to use them—a certain unsubstantial pellucid being,
neither favorable nor beneficial to any one, neither regarding nor doing
anything. There can be no such being in nature; and as Epicurus said
this plainly, he allows 254the Gods in words, and destroys them in fact;
and if the Deity is truly such a being that he shows no favor, no
benevolence to mankind, away with him! For why should I entreat him to
be propitious? He can be propitious to none, since, as you say, all his
favor and benevolence are the effects of imbecility.
BOOK II.
I.
When Cotta had thus concluded, Velleius replied: I certainly was
inconsiderate to engage in argument with an Academician who is likewise
a rhetorician. I should not have feared an Academician without
eloquence, nor a rhetorician without that philosophy, however eloquent
he might be; for I am never puzzled by an empty flow of words, nor by
the most subtle reasonings delivered without any grace of oratory. But
you, Cotta, have excelled in both. You only wanted the assembly and the
judges. However, enough of this at present. Now, let us hear what
Lucilius has to say, if it is agreeable to him.
I had much rather, says Balbus, hear Cotta resume his discourse, and
demonstrate the true Gods with the same eloquence which he made use of
to explode the false; for, on such a subject, the loose, unsettled
doctrine of the Academy does not become a philosopher, a priest, a
Cotta, whose opinions should be, like those we hold, firm and certain.
Epicurus has been more than sufficiently refuted; but I would willingly
hear your own sentiments, Cotta.
Do you forget, replies Cotta, what I at first said—that it is easier
for me, especially on this point, to explain what opinions those are
which I do not hold, rather than what those are which I do? Nay, even if
I did feel some certainty on any particular point, yet, after having
been so diffuse myself already, I would prefer now hearing you speak in
your turn. I submit, says Balbus, and will be as brief as I possibly
can; for as you have confuted the errors of Epicurus, my part in the
dispute will be the shorter.
255Our sect divide the whole question
concerning the immortal Gods into four parts. First, they prove that
there are Gods; secondly, of what character and nature they are;
thirdly, that the universe is governed by them; and, lastly, that they
exercise a superintendence over human affairs. But in this present
discussion let us confine ourselves to the first two articles, and defer
the third and fourth till another opportunity, as they require more time
to discuss. By no means, says Cotta, for we have time enough on our
hands; besides that, we are now discussing a subject which should be
preferred even to serious business.
II. The first point, then, says Lucilius, I think needs no discourse to
prove it; for what can be so plain and evident, when we behold the
heavens and contemplate the celestial bodies, as the existence of some
supreme, divine intelligence, by which all these things are governed?
Were it otherwise, Ennius would not, with a universal approbation, have
said,
Look up to the refulgent heaven above,
Which all men call, unanimously, Jove.
This is Jupiter, the governor of the world, who rules all things with
his nod, and is, as the same Ennius adds,
——of Gods and men the sire,
104
an omnipresent and omnipotent God. And if any one doubts this, I really
do not understand why the same man may not also doubt whether there is a
sun or not. For what can possibly be more evident than this? And if it
were not a truth universally impressed on the minds of men, the belief
in it would never have been so firm; nor would it have been, as it is,
increased by length of years, nor would it have gathered strength and
stability through every age. And, in truth, we see that other opinions,
being false and groundless, have already fallen into oblivion by lapse
of time. Who now believes in Hippocentaurs and 256Chimæras? Or what old
woman is now to be found so weak and ignorant as to stand in fear of
those infernal monsters which once so terrified mankind? For time
destroys the fictions of error and opinion, while it confirms the
determinations of nature and of truth. And therefore it is that, both
among us and among other nations, sacred institutions and the divine
worship of the Gods have been strengthened and improved from time to
time. And this is not to be imputed to chance or folly, but to the
frequent appearance of the Gods themselves. In the war with the Latins,
when A. Posthumius, the dictator, attacked Octavius Mamilius, the
Tusculan, at Regillus, Castor and Pollux were seen fighting in our army
on horseback; and since that the same offspring of Tyndarus gave notice
of the defeat of Perses; for as P. Vatienus, the grandfather of the
present young man of that name, was coming in the night to Rome from his
government of Reate, two young men on white horses appeared to him, and
told him that King105 Perses was that day taken prisoner. This news he
carried to the senate, who immediately threw him into prison for
speaking inconsiderately on a state affair; but when it was confirmed by
letters from Paullus, he was recompensed by the senate with land and
immunities.106 Nor do we forget when the Locrians defeated the people
of Crotone, in a great battle on the banks of the river Sagra, that it
was known the same day at the Olympic Games. The voices of the Fauns
have been often heard, and Deities have appeared in forms so visible
that they have compelled every one who is not senseless, or hardened in
impiety, to confess the presence of the Gods.
III. What do predictions and foreknowledge of future events indicate,
but that such future events are shown, pointed out, portended, and
foretold to men? From whence they are called omens, signs, portents,
prodigies. But though we should esteem fabulous what is said of
257Mopsus,107 Tiresias,108 Amphiaraus,109 Calchas,110 and
Helenus111 (who would not have been delivered down to us as augurs
even in fable if their art had been despised), may we not be
sufficiently apprised of the power of the Gods by domestic examples?
Will not the temerity of P. Claudius, in the first Punic war, affect us?
who, when the poultry were let out of the coop and would not feed,
ordered them to be thrown into the water, and, joking even upon the
Gods, said, with a sneer, “Let them drink, since they will not eat;”
which piece of ridicule, being followed by a victory over his fleet,
cost him many tears, and brought great calamity on the Roman people. Did
not his colleague Junius, in the same war, lose his fleet in a tempest
by disregarding the auspices? Claudius, therefore, was condemned by the
people, and Junius killed himself. CЕ“lius says that P. Flaminius, from
his neglect of religion, fell at Thrasimenus; a loss which the public
severely felt. By these instances of calamity we may be assured that
Rome owes her grandeur and success to the conduct of those who were
tenacious of their religious duties; and if we compare ourselves to our
neighbors, we shall find that we are infinitely distinguished above
foreign nations by our zeal for religious ceremonies, though in other
things we may be only equal to them, and in other respects even inferior
to them.
Ought we to contemn Attius Navius’s staff, with which 258he divided the
regions of the vine to find his sow?112 I should despise it, if I were
not aware that King Hostilius had carried on most important wars in
deference to his auguries; but by the negligence of our nobility the
discipline of the augury is now omitted, the truth of the auspices
despised, and only a mere form observed; so that the most important
affairs of the commonwealth, even the wars, on which the public safety
depends, are conducted without any auspices; the Peremnia113 are
discussed; no part of the Acumina114 performed; no select men are
called to witness to the military testaments;115 our generals now
begin their wars as soon as they have arranged the Auspicia. The force
of religion was so great among our ancestors that some of their
commanders have, with their faces veiled, and with the solemn, formal
expressions of religion, sacrificed themselves to the immortal Gods to
save their country.116 I could mention many of the Sibylline
prophecies, and many answers of the haruspices, to confirm those things,
which ought not to be doubted.
IV. For example: our augurs and the Etrurian haruspices saw the truth of
their art established when P. Scipio and C. Figulus were consuls; for as
Tiberius Gracchus, who was a second time consul, wished to proceed to a
259fresh election, the first Rogator,117 as he was collecting the
suffrages, fell down dead on the spot. Gracchus nevertheless went on
with the assembly, but perceiving that this accident had a religious
influence on the people, he brought the affair before the senate. The
senate thought fit to refer it to those who usually took cognizance of
such things. The haruspices were called, and declared that the man who
had acted as Rogator of the assembly had no right to do so; to which, as
I have heard my father say, he replied with great warmth, Have I no
right, who am consul, and augur, and favored by the Auspicia? And shall
you, who are Tuscans and Barbarians, pretend that you have authority
over the Roman Auspicia, and a right to give judgment in matters
respecting the formality of our assemblies? Therefore, he then commanded
them to withdraw; but not long afterward he wrote from his province118
to the college of augurs, acknowledging that in reading the books119
he remembered that he had illegally chosen a place for his tent in the
gardens of Scipio, and had afterward entered the PomЕ“rium, in order to
hold a senate, but that in repassing the same PomЕ“rium he had forgotten
to take the auspices; and that, therefore, the consuls had been created
informally. The augurs laid the case before the senate. The senate
decreed that they should resign their charge, and so they accordingly
abdicated. What greater example need we seek for? The wisest, perhaps
the most excellent of men, chose to confess his fault, which he might
have concealed, rather than leave the public the least atom of religious
guilt; and the consuls chose to quit the highest office in the State,
rather than fill it for a moment in defiance of religion. How great is
the reputation of the augurs!
And is not the art of the soothsayers divine? And must not every one who
sees what innumerable instances of the same kind there are confess the
existence of the 260Gods? For they who have interpreters must certainly
exist themselves; now, there are interpreters of the Gods; therefore we
must allow there are Gods. But it may be said, perhaps, that all
predictions are not accomplished. We may as well conclude there is no
art of physic, because all sick persons do not recover. The Gods show us
signs of future events; if we are occasionally deceived in the results,
it is not to be imputed to the nature of the Gods, but to the
conjectures of men. All nations agree that there are Gods; the opinion
is innate, and, as it were, engraved in the minds of all men. The only
point in dispute among us is, what they are.
V. Their existence no one denies. Cleanthes, one of our sect, imputes
the way in which the idea of the Gods is implanted in the minds of men
to four causes. The first is that which I just now mentioned—the
foreknowledge of future things. The second is the great advantages which
we enjoy from the temperature of the air, the fertility of the earth,
and the abundance of various benefits of other kinds. The third cause is
deduced from the terror with which the mind is affected by thunder,
tempests, storms, snow, hail, devastation, pestilence, earthquakes often
attended with hideous noises, showers of stones, and rain like drops of
blood; by rocks and sudden openings of the earth; by monstrous births of
men and beasts; by meteors in the air, and blazing stars, by the Greeks
called cometæ, by us crinitæ, the appearance of which, in the late
Octavian war,120 were foreboders of great calamities; by two suns,
which, as I have heard my father say, happened in the consulate of
Tuditanus and Aquillius, and in which year also another sun (P.
Africanus) was extinguished. These things terrified mankind, and raised
in them a firm belief of the existence of some celestial and divine
power.
His fourth cause, and that the strongest, is drawn from the regularity
of the motion and revolution of the heavens, the distinctness, variety,
beauty, and order of the sun, moon, and all the stars, the appearance
only of which is sufficient to convince us they are not the effects of
chance; as when we enter into a house, or school, or court, and observe
the exact order, discipline, and method of it, we cannot suppose 261that
it is so regulated without a cause, but must conclude that there is some
one who commands, and to whom obedience is paid. It is quite impossible
for us to avoid thinking that the wonderful motions, revolutions, and
order of those many and great bodies, no part of which is impaired by
the countless and infinite succession of ages, must be governed and
directed by some supreme intelligent being.
VI. Chrysippus, indeed, had a very penetrating genius; yet such is the
doctrine which he delivers, that he seems rather to have been instructed
by nature than to owe it to any discovery of his own. “If,” says he,
“there is anything in the universe which no human reason, ability, or
power can make, the being who produced it must certainly be preferable
to man. Now, celestial bodies, and all those things which proceed in any
eternal order, cannot be made by man; the being who made them is
therefore preferable to man. What, then, is that being but a God? If
there be no such thing as a Deity, what is there better than man, since
he only is possessed of reason, the most excellent of all things? But it
is a foolish piece of vanity in man to think there is nothing preferable
to him. There is, therefore, something preferable; consequently, there
is certainly a God.”
When you behold a large and beautiful house, surely no one can persuade
you it was built for mice and weasels, though you do not see the master;
and would it not, therefore, be most manifest folly to imagine that a
world so magnificently adorned, with such an immense variety of
celestial bodies of such exquisite beauty, and that the vast sizes and
magnitude of the sea and land were intended as the abode of man, and not
as the mansion of the immortal Gods? Do we not also plainly see this,
that all the most elevated regions are the best, and that the earth is
the lowest region, and is surrounded with the grossest air? so that as
we perceive that in some cities and countries the capacities of men are
naturally duller, from the thickness of the climate, so mankind in
general are affected by the heaviness of the air which surrounds the
earth, the grossest region of the world.
Yet even from this inferior intelligence of man we may 262discover the
existence of some intelligent agent that is divine, and wiser than
ourselves; for, as Socrates says in Xenophon, from whence had man his
portion of understanding? And, indeed, if any one were to push his
inquiries about the moisture and heat which is diffused through the
human body, and the earthy kind of solidity existing in our entrails,
and that soul by which we breathe, and to ask whence we derived them, it
would be plain that we have received one thing from the earth, another
from liquid, another from fire, and another from that air which we
inhale every time that we breathe.
VII. But where did we find that which excels all these things—I mean
reason, or (if you please, in other terms) the mind, understanding,
thought, prudence; and from whence did we receive it? Shall the world be
possessed of every other perfection, and be destitute of this one, which
is the most important and valuable of all? But certainly there is
nothing better, or more excellent, or more beautiful than the world; and
not only there is nothing better, but we cannot even conceive anything
superior to it; and if reason and wisdom are the greatest of all
perfections, they must necessarily be a part of what we all allow to be
the most excellent.
Who is not compelled to admit the truth of what I assert by that
agreeable, uniform, and continued agreement of things in the universe?
Could the earth at one season be adorned with flowers, at another be
covered with snow? Or, if such a number of things regulated their own
changes, could the approach and retreat of the sun in the summer and
winter solstices be so regularly known and calculated? Could the flux
and reflux of the sea and the height of the tides be affected by the
increase or wane of the moon? Could the different courses of the stars
be preserved by the uniform movement of the whole heaven? Could these
things subsist, I say, in such a harmony of all the parts of the
universe without the continued influence of a divine spirit?
If these points are handled in a free and copious manner, as I purpose
to do, they will be less liable to the cavils of the Academics; but the
narrow, confined way in which Zeno reasoned upon them laid them more
open to 263objection; for as running streams are seldom or never tainted,
while standing waters easily grow corrupt, so a fluency of expression
washes away the censures of the caviller, while the narrow limits of a
discourse which is too concise is almost defenceless; for the arguments
which I am enlarging upon are thus briefly laid down by Zeno:
VIII. “That which reasons is superior to that which does not; nothing is
superior to the world; the world, therefore, reasons.” By the same rule
the world may be proved to be wise, happy, and eternal; for the
possession of all these qualities is superior to the want of them; and
nothing is superior to the world; the inevitable consequence of which
argument is, that the world, therefore, is a Deity. He goes on: “No part
of anything void of sense is capable of perception; some parts of the
world have perception; the world, therefore, has sense.” He proceeds,
and pursues the argument closely. “Nothing,” says he, “that is destitute
itself of life and reason can generate a being possessed of life and
reason; but the world does generate beings possessed of life and reason;
the world, therefore, is not itself destitute of life and reason.”
He concludes his argument in his usual manner with a simile: “If
well-tuned pipes should spring out of the olive, would you have the
slightest doubt that there was in the olive-tree itself some kind of
skill and knowledge? Or if the plane-tree could produce harmonious
lutes, surely you would infer, on the same principle, that music was
contained in the plane-tree. Why, then, should we not believe the world
is a living and wise being, since it produces living and wise beings out
of itself?”
IX. But as I have been insensibly led into a length of discourse beyond
my first design (for I said that, as the existence of the Gods was
evident to all, there was no need of any long oration to prove it), I
will demonstrate it by reasons deduced from the nature of things. For it
is a fact that all beings which take nourishment and increase contain in
themselves a power of natural heat, without which they could neither be
nourished nor increase. For everything which is of a warm and fiery
character is agitated and stirred up by its own motion. But that which
is nourished and grows is influenced by a certain regular 264and equable
motion. And as long as this motion remains in us, so long does sense and
life remain; but the moment that it abates and is extinguished, we
ourselves decay and perish.
By arguments like these, Cleanthes shows how great is the power of heat
in all bodies. He observes that there is no food so gross as not to be
digested in a night and a day; and that even in the excrementitious
parts, which nature rejects, there remains a heat. The veins and
arteries seem, by their continual quivering, to resemble the agitation
of fire; and it has often been observed when the heart of an animal is
just plucked from the body that it palpitates with such visible motion
as to resemble the rapidity of fire. Everything, therefore, that has
life, whether it be animal or vegetable, owes that life to the heat
inherent in it; it is this nature of heat which contains in itself the
vital power which extends throughout the whole world. This will appear
more clearly on a more close explanation of this fiery quality, which
pervades all things.
Every division, then, of the world (and I shall touch upon the most
considerable) is sustained by heat; and first it may be observed in
earthly substances that fire is produced from stones by striking or
rubbing one against another; that “the warm earth smokes”121 when just
turned up, and that water is drawn warm from well-springs; and this is
most especially the case in the winter season, because there is a great
quantity of heat contained in the caverns of the earth; and this becomes
more dense in the winter, and on that account confines more closely the
innate heat which is discoverable in the earth.
X. It would require a long dissertation, and many reasons would require
to be adduced, to show that all the seeds which the earth conceives, and
all those which it contains having been generated from itself, and fixed
in roots and trunks, derive all their origin and increase from the
temperature and regulation of heat. And that even every liquor has a
mixture of heat in it is plainly demonstrated by the effusion of water;
for it would not congeal by cold, nor become solid, as ice or snow, and
return again 265to its natural state, if it were not that, when heat is
applied to it, it again becomes liquefied and dissolved, and so diffuses
itself. Therefore, by northern and other cold winds it is frozen and
hardened, and in turn it dissolves and melts again by heat. The seas
likewise, we find, when agitated by winds, grow warm, so that from this
fact we may understand that there is heat included in that vast body of
water; for we cannot imagine it to be external and adventitious heat,
but such as is stirred up by agitation from the deep recesses of the
seas; and the same thing takes place with respect to our bodies, which
grow warm with motion and exercise.
And the very air itself, which indeed is the coldest element, is by no
means void of heat; for there is a great quantity, arising from the
exhalations of water, which appears to be a sort of steam occasioned by
its internal heat, like that of boiling liquors. The fourth part of the
universe is entirely fire, and is the source of the salutary and vital
heat which is found in the rest. From hence we may conclude that, as all
parts of the world are sustained by heat, the world itself also has such
a great length of time subsisted from the same cause; and so much the
more, because we ought to understand that that hot and fiery principle
is so diffused over universal nature that there is contained in it a
power and cause of generation and procreation, from which all animate
beings, and all those creatures of the vegetable world, the roots of
which are contained in the earth, must inevitably derive their origin
and their increase.
XI. It is nature, consequently, that continues and preserves the world,
and that, too, a nature which is not destitute of sense and reason; for
in every essence that is not simple, but composed of several parts,
there must be some predominant quality—as, for instance, the mind in
man, and in beasts something resembling it, from which arise all the
appetites and desires for anything. As for trees, and all the vegetable
produce of the earth, it is thought to be in their roots. I call that
the predominant quality,122 which 266the Greeks call бјЎОіОµОјОїОЅО№ОєбЅ№ОЅ; which
must and ought to be the most excellent quality, wherever it is found.
That, therefore, in which the prevailing quality of all nature resides
must be the most excellent of all things, and most worthy of the power
and pre-eminence over all things.
Now, we see that there is nothing in being that is not a part of the
universe; and as there are sense and reason in the parts of it, there
must therefore be these qualities, and these, too, in a more energetic
and powerful degree, in that part in which the predominant quality of
the world is found. The world, therefore, must necessarily be possessed
of wisdom; and that element, which embraces all things, must excel in
perfection of reason. The world, therefore, is a God, and the whole
power of the world is contained in that divine element.
The heat also of the world is more pure, clear, and lively, and,
consequently, better adapted to move the senses than the heat allotted
to us; and it vivifies and preserves all things within the compass of
our knowledge.
It is absurd, therefore, to say that the world, which is endued with a
perfect, free, pure, spirituous, and active heat, is not sensitive,
since by this heat men and beasts are preserved, and move, and think;
more especially since this heat of the world is itself the sole
principle of agitation, and has no external impulse, but is moved
spontaneously; for what can be more powerful than the world, which moves
and raises that heat by which it subsists?
XII. For let us listen to Plato, who is regarded as a God among
philosophers. He says that there are two sorts of motion, one innate and
the other external; and that that which is moved spontaneously is more
divine than that which is moved by another power. This self-motion he
places in the mind alone, and concludes that the first principle of
motion is derived from the mind. Therefore, since all motion arises from
the heat of the world, and that heat is not moved by the effect of any
external impulse, but of its own accord, it must necessarily be a mind;
from whence it follows that the world is animated.
On such reasoning is founded this opinion, that the world is possessed
of understanding, because it certainly has more perfections in itself
than any other nature; for 267as there is no part of our bodies so
considerable as the whole of us, so it is clear that there is no
particular portion of the universe equal in magnitude to the whole of
it; from whence it follows that wisdom must be an attribute of the
world; otherwise man, who is a part of it, and possessed of reason,
would be superior to the entire world.
And thus, if we proceed from the first rude, unfinished natures to the
most superior and perfect ones, we shall inevitably come at last to the
nature of the Gods. For, in the first place, we observe that those
vegetables which are produced out of the earth are supported by nature,
and she gives them no further supply than is sufficient to preserve them
by nourishing them and making them grow. To beasts she has given sense
and motion, and a faculty which directs them to what is wholesome, and
prompts them to shun what is noxious to them. On man she has conferred a
greater portion of her favor; inasmuch as she has added reason, by which
he is enabled to command his passions, to moderate some, and to subdue
others.
XIII. In the fourth and highest degree are those beings which are
naturally wise and good, who from the first moment of their existence
are possessed of right and consistent reason, which we must consider
superior to man and deserving to be attributed to a God; that is to say,
to the world, in which it is inevitable that that perfect and complete
reason should be inherent. Nor is it possible that it should be said
with justice that there is any arrangement of things in which there
cannot be something entire and perfect. For as in a vine or in beasts we
see that nature, if not prevented by some superior violence, proceeds by
her own appropriate path to her destined end; and as in painting,
architecture, and the other arts there is a point of perfection which is
attainable, and occasionally attained, so it is even much more necessary
that in universal nature there must be some complete and perfect result
arrived at. Many external accidents may happen to all other natures
which may impede their progress to perfection, but nothing can hinder
universal nature, because she is herself the ruler and governor of all
other natures. That, therefore, must be the fourth and most elevated
degree to which no other power can approach.
268But this degree is that on which the nature of all things is placed;
and since she is possessed of this, and she presides over all things,
and is subject to no possible impediment, the world must necessarily be
an intelligent and even a wise being. But how marvellously great is the
ignorance of those men who dispute the perfection of that nature which
encircles all things; or who, allowing it to be infinitely perfect, yet
deny it to be, in the first place, animated, then reasonable, and,
lastly, prudent and wise! For how without these qualities could it be
infinitely perfect? If it were like vegetables, or even like beasts,
there would be no more reason for thinking it extremely good than
extremely bad; and if it were possessed of reason, and had not wisdom
from the beginning, the world would be in a worse condition than man;
for man may grow wise, but the world, if it were destitute of wisdom
through an infinite space of time past, could never acquire it. Thus it
would be worse than man. But as that is absurd to imagine, the world
must be esteemed wise from all eternity, and consequently a Deity: since
there is nothing existing that is not defective, except the universe,
which is well provided, and fully complete and perfect in all its
numbers and parts.
XIV. For Chrysippus says, very acutely, that as the case is made for the
buckler, and the scabbard for the sword, so all things, except the
universe, were made for the sake of something else. As, for instance,
all those crops and fruits which the earth produces were made for the
sake of animals, and animals for man; as, the horse for carrying, the ox
for the plough, the dog for hunting and for a guard. But man himself was
born to contemplate and imitate the world, being in no wise perfect,
but, if I may so express myself, a particle of perfection; but the
world, as it comprehends all, and as nothing exists that is not
contained in it, is entirely perfect. In what, therefore, can it be
defective, since it is perfect? It cannot want understanding and reason,
for they are the most desirable of all qualities. The same Chrysippus
observes also, by the use of similitudes, that everything in its kind,
when arrived at maturity and perfection, is superior to that which is
not—as, a horse to a colt, a dog to a puppy, and a man to a boy—so
whatever 269is best in the whole universe must exist in some complete and
perfect being. But nothing is more perfect than the world, and nothing
better than virtue. Virtue, therefore, is an attribute of the world. But
human nature is not perfect, and nevertheless virtue is produced in it:
with how much greater reason, then, do we conceive it to be inherent in
the world! Therefore the world has virtue, and it is also wise, and
consequently a Deity.
XV. The divinity of the world being now clearly perceived, we must
acknowledge the same divinity to be likewise in the stars, which are
formed from the lightest and purest part of the ether, without a mixture
of any other matter; and, being altogether hot and transparent, we may
justly say they have life, sense, and understanding. And Cleanthes
thinks that it may be established by the evidence of two of our
senses—feeling and seeing—that they are entirely fiery bodies; for the
heat and brightness of the sun far exceed any other fire, inasmuch as it
enlightens the whole universe, covering such a vast extent of space, and
its power is such that we perceive that it not only warms, but often
even burns: neither of which it could do if it were not of a fiery
quality. Since, then, says he, the sun is a fiery body, and is nourished
by the vapors of the ocean (for no fire can continue without some
sustenance), it must be either like that fire which we use to warm us
and dress our food, or like that which is contained in the bodies of
animals.
And this fire, which the convenience of life requires, is the devourer
and consumer of everything, and throws into confusion and destroys
whatever it reaches. On the contrary, the corporeal heat is full of
life, and salutary; and vivifies, preserves, cherishes, increases, and
sustains all things, and is productive of sense; therefore, says he,
there can be no doubt which of these fires the sun is like, since it
causes all things in their respective kinds to flourish and arrive to
maturity; and as the fire of the sun is like that which is contained in
the bodies of animated beings, the sun itself must likewise be animated,
and so must the other stars also, which arise out of the celestial ardor
that we call the sky, or firmament.
As, then, some animals are generated in the earth, some 270in the water,
and some in the air, Aristotle123 thinks it ridiculous to imagine that
no animal is formed in that part of the universe which is the most
capable to produce them. But the stars are situated in the ethereal
space; and as this is an element the most subtle, whose motion is
continual, and whose force does not decay, it follows, of necessity,
that every animated being which is produced in it must be endowed with
the quickest sense and the swiftest motion. The stars, therefore, being
there generated, it is a natural inference to suppose them endued with
such a degree of sense and understanding as places them in the rank of
Gods.
XVI. For it may be observed that they who inhabit countries of a pure,
clear air have a quicker apprehension and a readier genius than those
who live in a thick, foggy climate. It is thought likewise that the
nature of a man’s diet has an effect on the mind; therefore it is
probable that the stars are possessed of an excellent understanding,
inasmuch as they are situated in the ethereal part of the universe, and
are nourished by the vapors of the earth and sea, which are purified by
their long passage to the heavens. But the invariable order and regular
motion of the stars plainly manifest their sense and understanding; for
all motion which seems to be conducted with reason and harmony supposes
an intelligent principle, that does not act blindly, or inconsistently,
or at random. And this regularity and consistent course of the stars
from all eternity indicates not any natural order, for it is pregnant
with sound reason, not fortune (for fortune, being a friend to change,
despises consistency). It follows, therefore, that they move
spontaneously by their own sense and divinity.
Aristotle also deserves high commendation for his observation that
everything that moves is either put in motion by natural impulse, or by
some external force, or of its own accord; and that the sun, and moon,
and all the stars move; but that those things which are moved by natural
impulse are either borne downward by their weight, or upward by their
lightness; neither of which things could be the case with the stars,
because they move in a regular circle and orbit. Nor can it be said that
271there is some superior force which causes the stars to be moved in a
manner contrary to nature. For what superior force can there be? It
follows, therefore, that their motion must be voluntary. And whoever is
convinced of this must discover not only great ignorance, but great
impiety likewise, if he denies the existence of the Gods; nor is the
difference great whether a man denies their existence, or deprives them
of all design and action; for whatever is wholly inactive seems to me
not to exist at all. Their existence, therefore, appears so plain that I
can scarcely think that man in his senses who denies it.
XVII. It now remains that we consider what is the character of the Gods.
Nothing is more difficult than to divert our thoughts and judgment from
the information of our corporeal sight, and the view of objects which
our eyes are accustomed to; and it is this difficulty which has had such
an influence on the unlearned, and on philosophers124 also who
resembled the unlearned multitude, that they have been unable to form
any idea of the immortal Gods except under the clothing of the human
figure; the weakness of which opinion Cotta has so well confuted that I
need not add my thoughts upon it. But as the previous idea which we have
of the Deity comprehends two things—first of all, that he is an
animated being; secondly, that there is nothing in all nature superior
to him—I do not see what can be more consistent with this idea and
preconception than to attribute a mind and divinity to the world,125
the most excellent of all beings.
Epicurus may be as merry with this notion as he pleases; a man not the
best qualified for a joker, as not having the wit and sense of his
country.126 Let him say that a voluble round Deity is to him
incomprehensible; yet he shall never dissuade me from a principle which
he himself approves, for he is of opinion there are Gods when he allows
that there must be a nature excellently perfect. But it is certain 272that
the world is most excellently perfect: nor is it to be doubted that
whatever has life, sense, reason, and understanding must excel that
which is destitute of these things. It follows, then, that the world has
life, sense, reason, and understanding, and is consequently a Deity. But
this shall soon be made more manifest by the operation of these very
things which the world causes.
XVIII. In the mean while, Velleius, let me entreat you not to be always
saying that we are utterly destitute of every sort of learning. The
cone, you say, the cylinder, and the pyramid, are more beautiful to you
than the sphere. This is to have different eyes from other men. But
suppose they are more beautiful to the sight only, which does not appear
to me, for I can see nothing more beautiful than that figure which
contains all others, and which has nothing rough in it, nothing
offensive, nothing cut into angles, nothing broken, nothing swelling,
and nothing hollow; yet as there are two forms most esteemed,127 the
globe in solids (for so the Greek word ПѓП†О±бї–ПЃО±, I think, should be
construed), and the circle, or orb, in planes (in Greek, ОєбЅ»ОєО»ОїП‚); and as
they only have an exact similitude of parts in which every extreme is
equally distant from the centre, what can we imagine in nature to be
more just and proper? But if you have never raked into this learned
dust128 to find out these things, surely, at all events, you natural
philosophers must know that equality of motion and invariable order
could not be preserved in any other figure. Nothing, therefore, can be
more illiterate than to assert, as you are in the habit of doing, that
it is doubtful whether the world is round or not, because it may
possibly be of another shape, and that there are innumerable worlds of
different forms; which Epicurus, if he ever had learned that two and two
are equal to four, would not have said. But while he judges of what is
best by his palate, he does not look up to the “palace of heaven,” as
Ennius calls it.
XIX. For as there are two sorts of stars,129 one kind of 273which
measure their journey from east to west by immutable stages, never in
the least varying from their usual course, while the other completes a
double revolution with an equally constant regularity; from each of
these facts we demonstrate the volubility of the world (which could not
possibly take place in any but a globular form) and the circular orbits
of the stars. And first of all the sun, which has the chief rank among
all the stars, is moved in such a manner that it fills the whole earth
with its light, and illuminates alternately one part of the earth, while
it leaves the other in darkness. The shadow of the earth interposing
causes night; and the intervals of night are equal to those of day. And
it is the regular approaches and retreats of the sun from which arise
the regulated degrees of cold and heat. His annual circuit is in three
hundred and sixty-five days, and nearly six hours more.130 At one time
he bends his course to the north, at another to the south, and thus
produces summer and winter, with the other two seasons, one of which
succeeds the decline of winter, and the other that of summer. And so to
these four changes of the seasons we attribute the origin and cause of
all the productions both of sea and land.
The moon completes the same course every month which the sun does in a
year. The nearer she approaches to the sun, the dimmer light does she
yield, and when most remote from it she shines with the fullest
brilliancy; nor are her figure and form only changed in her wane, but
her situation likewise, which is sometimes in the north and sometimes in
the south. By this course she has a sort of summer and winter solstices;
and by her influence she contributes to the nourishment and increase of
animated 274beings, and to the ripeness and maturity of all vegetables.
XX. But most worthy our admiration is the motion of those five stars
which are falsely called wandering stars; for they cannot be said to
wander which keep from all eternity their approaches and retreats, and
have all the rest of their motions, in one regular constant and
established order. What is yet more wonderful in these stars which we
are speaking of is that sometimes they appear, and sometimes they
disappear; sometimes they advance towards the sun, and sometimes they
retreat; sometimes they precede him, and sometimes follow him; sometimes
they move faster, sometimes slower, and sometimes they do not stir in
the least, but for a while stand still. From these unequal motions of
the planets, mathematicians have called that the “great year”131 in
which the sun, moon, and five wandering stars, having finished their
revolutions, are found in their original situation. In how long a time
this is effected is much disputed, but it must be a certain and definite
period. For the planet Saturn (called by the Greeks О¦О±бЅ·ОЅОїОЅ), which is
farthest from the earth, finishes his course in about thirty years; and
in his course there is something very singular, for sometimes he moves
before the sun, sometimes he keeps behind it; at one time lying hidden
in the night, at another again appearing in the morning; and ever
performing the same motions in the same space of time without any
alteration, so as to be for infinite ages regular in these courses.
Beneath this planet, and nearer the earth, is Jupiter, called О¦О±бЅіОёП‰ОЅ,
which passes the same orbit of the twelve signs132 in twelve years,
and goes through exactly the same variety in its course that the star of
Saturn does. Next to Jupiter is the planet Mars (in Greek, О П…ПЃбЅ№ОµО№П‚),
which finishes its revolution through the same orbit as the two
previously mentioned,133 in twenty-four months, wanting six days, as I
275imagine. Below this is Mercury (called by the Greeks ОЈП„бЅ·О»ОІП‰ОЅ), which
performs the same course in little less than a year, and is never
farther distant from the sun than the space of one sign, whether it
precedes or follows it. The lowest of the five planets, and nearest the
earth, is that of Venus (called in Greek О¦П‰ПѓП†бЅ№ПЃОїП‚). Before the rising of
the sun, it is called the morning-star, and after the setting, the
evening-star. It has the same revolution through the zodiac, both as to
latitude and longitude, with the other planets, in a year, and never is
more than two134 signs from the sun, whether it precedes or follows
it.
XXI. I cannot, therefore, conceive that this constant course of the
planets, this just agreement in such various motions through all
eternity, can be preserved without a mind, reason, and consideration;
and since we may perceive these qualities in the stars, we cannot but
place them in the rank of Gods. Those which are called the fixed stars
have the same indications of reason and prudence. Their motion is daily,
regular, and constant. They do not move with the sky, nor have they an
adhesion to the firmament, as they who are ignorant of natural
philosophy affirm. For the sky, which is thin, transparent, and suffused
with an equal heat, does not seem by its nature to have power to whirl
about the stars, or to be proper to contain them. The fixed stars,
therefore, have their own sphere, separate and free from any conjunction
with the sky. Their perpetual courses, with that admirable and
incredible regularity of theirs, so plainly declare a divine power and
mind to be in them, that he who cannot perceive that they are also
endowed with divine power must be incapable of all perception whatever.
In the heavens, therefore, there is nothing fortuitous, unadvised,
inconstant, or variable: all there is order, truth, reason, and
constancy; and all the things which are destitute of these qualities are
counterfeit, deceitful, and erroneous, and have their residence about
the earth135 beneath the moon, the lowest of all the planets. He,
therefore, 276who believes that this admirable order and almost incredible
regularity of the heavenly bodies, by which the preservation and entire
safety of all things is secured, is destitute of intelligence, must be
considered to be himself wholly destitute of all intellect whatever.
I think, then, I shall not deceive myself in maintaining this dispute
upon the principle of Zeno, who went the farthest in his search after
truth.
XXII. Zeno, then, defines nature to be “an artificial fire, proceeding
in a regular way to generation;” for he thinks that to create and beget
are especial properties of art, and that whatever may be wrought by the
hands of our artificers is much more skilfully performed by nature, that
is, by this artificial fire, which is the master of all other arts.
According to this manner of reasoning, every particular nature is
artificial, as it operates agreeably to a certain method peculiar to
itself; but that universal nature which embraces all things is said by
Zeno to be not only artificial, but absolutely the artificer, ever
thinking and providing all things useful and proper; and as every
particular nature owes its rise and increase to its own proper seed, so
universal nature has all her motions voluntary, has affections and
desires (by the Greeks called бЅЃПЃОјбЅ°П‚) productive of actions agreeable to
them, like us, who have sense and understanding to direct us. Such,
then, is the intelligence of the universe; for which reason it may be
properly termed prudence or providence (in Greek, ПЂПЃбЅ№ОЅОїО№О±), since her
chiefest care and employment is to provide all things fit for its
duration, that it may want nothing, and, above all, that it may be
adorned with all perfection of beauty and ornament.
XXIII. Thus far have I spoken concerning the universe, and also of the
stars; from whence it is apparent that there is almost an infinite
number of Gods, always in action, but without labor or fatigue; for they
are not composed of veins, nerves, and bones; their food and drink are
not such as cause humors too gross or too subtle; nor are their bodies
such as to be subject to the fear of falls or blows, or in danger of
diseases from a weariness of limbs. Epicurus, to secure his Gods from
such accidents, 277has made them only outlines of Deities, void of action;
but our Gods being of the most beautiful form, and situated in the
purest region of the heavens, dispose and rule their course in such a
manner that they seem to contribute to the support and preservation of
all things.
Besides these, there are many other natures which have with reason been
deified by the wisest Grecians, and by our ancestors, in consideration
of the benefits derived from them; for they were persuaded that whatever
was of great utility to human kind must proceed from divine goodness,
and the name of the Deity was applied to that which the Deity produced,
as when we call corn Ceres, and wine Bacchus; whence that saying of
Terence,136
Without Ceres and Bacchus, Venus starves.
And any quality, also, in which there was any singular virtue was
nominated a Deity, such as Faith and Wisdom, which are placed among the
divinities in the Capitol; the last by Г†milius Scaurus, but Faith was
consecrated before by Atilius Calatinus. You see the temple of Virtue
and that of Honor repaired by M. Marcellus, erected formerly, in the
Ligurian war, by Q. Maximus. Need I mention those dedicated to Help,
Safety, Concord, Liberty, and Victory, which have been called Deities,
because their efficacy has been so great that it could not have
proceeded from any but from some divine power? In like manner are the
names of Cupid, Voluptas, and of Lubentine Venus consecrated, though
they were things vicious and not natural, whatever Velleius may think
to the contrary, for they frequently stimulate nature in too violent a
manner. Everything, then, from which any great utility proceeded was
deified; and, indeed, the names I have just now mentioned are
declaratory of the particular virtue of each Deity.
XXIV. It has been a general custom likewise, that men who have done
important service to the public should be exalted to heaven by fame and
universal consent. Thus Hercules, Castor and Pollux, Г†sculapius, and
Liber became Gods (I mean Liber137 the son of Semele, and not him138
whom our ancestors consecrated in such state and 278solemnity with Ceres
and Libera; the difference in which may be seen in our Mysteries.139
But because the offsprings of our bodies are called “Liberi” (children),
therefore the offsprings of Ceres are called Liber and Libera
(Libera140 is the feminine, and Liber the masculine); thus likewise
Romulus, or Quirinus—for they are thought to be the same—became a God.
They are justly esteemed as Deities, since their souls subsist and enjoy
eternity, from whence they are perfect and immortal beings.
There is another reason, too, and that founded on natural philosophy,
which has greatly contributed to the number of Deities; namely, the
custom of representing in human form a crowd of Gods who have supplied
the poets with fables, and filled mankind with all sorts of
superstition. Zeno has treated of this subject, but it has been
discussed more at length by Cleanthes and Chrysippus. All Greece was of
opinion that CЕ“lum was castrated by his son Saturn,141 and that Saturn
was chained by his son Jupiter. In these impious fables, a physical and
not inelegant meaning is contained; for they would denote that the
celestial, most exalted, and ethereal nature—that is, the fiery nature,
which produces all things by itself—is destitute of that part of the
body which is necessary for the act of generation by conjunction with
another.
XXV. By Saturn they mean that which comprehends the course and
revolution of times and seasons; the Greek name for which Deity implies
as much, for he is called 279ОљПЃбЅ№ОЅОїП‚, which is the same with О§ПЃбЅ№ОЅОїП‚, that
is, a “space of time.” But he is called Saturn, because he is filled
(saturatur) with years; and he is usually feigned to have devoured his
children, because time, ever insatiable, consumes the rolling years; but
to restrain him from immoderate haste, Jupiter has confined him to the
course of the stars, which are as chains to him. Jupiter (that is,
juvans pater) signifies a “helping father,” whom, by changing the
cases, we call Jove,142 a juvando. The poets call him “father of
Gods and men;”143 and our ancestors “the most good, the most great;”
and as there is something more glorious in itself, and more agreeable to
others, to be good (that is, beneficent) than to be great, the title of
“most good” precedes that of “most great.” This, then, is he whom Ennius
means in the following passage, before quoted—
Look up to the refulgent heaven above,
Which all men call, unanimously, Jove:
which is more plainly expressed than in this other passage144 of the
same poet—
On whose account I’ll curse that flood of light,
Whate’er it is above that shines so bright.
Our augurs also mean the same, when, for the “thundering and lightning
heaven,” they say the “thundering and lightning Jove.” Euripides, among
many excellent things, has this:
The vast, expanded, boundless sky behold,
See it with soft embrace the earth enfold;
This own the chief of Deities above,
And this acknowledge by the name of Jove.
XXVI. The air, according to the Stoics, which is between the sea and the
heaven, is consecrated by the name of Juno, and is called the sister and
wife of Jove, because
280it resembles the sky, and is in close conjunction
with it. They have made it feminine, because there is nothing softer.
But I believe it is called Juno,
a juvando (from helping).
To make three separate kingdoms, by fable, there remained yet the water
and the earth. The dominion of the sea is given, therefore, to Neptune,
a brother, as he is called, of Jove; whose name, Neptunus—as
Portunus,
a portu, from a port—is derived
a nando (from swimming), the first
letters being a little changed. The sovereignty and power over the earth
is the portion of a God, to whom we, as well as the Greeks, have given a
name that denotes riches (in Latin,
Dis; in Greek,
О О»ОїбЅ»П„П‰ОЅ), because
all things arise from the earth and return to it. He forced away
Proserpine (in Greek called
О ОµПЃПѓОµП†бЅ№ОЅО·), by which the poets mean the
“seed of corn,” from whence comes their fiction of Ceres, the mother of
Proserpine, seeking for her daughter, who was hidden from her. She is
called Ceres, which is the same as Geres—
a gerendis
frugibus145—“from bearing fruit,” the first letter of the word being
altered after the manner of the Greeks, for by them she is called
О”О·ОјбЅµП„О·ПЃ, the same as
О“О·ОјбЅµП„О·ПЃ.
146 Again, he (
qui magna vorteret) “who
brings about mighty changes” is called Mavors; and Minerva is so called
because (
minueret, or
minaretur) she diminishes or menaces.
XXVII. And as the beginnings and endings of all things are of the
greatest importance, therefore they would have their sacrifices to begin
with Janus.
147 His name is derived
ab eundo, from passing; from
whence thorough passages are called
jani, and the outward doors of
common houses are called
januæ. The name of Vesta is, from the Greeks,
the same with their
бј™ПѓП„бЅ·О±. Her province is over altars and hearths; and
in the name of this Goddess, who is the keeper of all things within,
prayers and sacrifices are concluded. The
Dii Penates, “household Gods,”
have some affinity with this power, and are so called either from
penus,
281“all kind of human provisions,” or because
penitus insident
(they reside within), from which, by the poets, they are called
penetrales also. Apollo, a Greek name, is called
Sol, the sun; and
Diana,
Luna, the moon. The sun (
sol) is so named either because he
is
solus (alone), so eminent above all the stars; or because he
obscures all the stars, and appears alone as soon as he rises.
Luna,
the moon, is so called
a lucendo (from shining); she bears the name
also of Lucina: and as in Greece the women in labor invoke Diana
Lucifera, so here they invoke Juno Lucina. She is likewise called Diana
omnivaga, not
a venando (from hunting), but because she is reckoned
one of the seven stars that seem to wander.
148 She is called Diana
because she makes a kind of day of the night;
149 and presides over
births, because the delivery is effected sometimes in seven, or at most
in nine, courses of the moon; which, because they make
mensa spatia
(measured spaces), are called
menses (months). This occasioned a
pleasant observation of Timæus (as he has many). Having said in his
history that “the same night in which Alexander was born, the temple of
Diana at Ephesus was burned down,” he adds, “It is not in the least to
be wondered at, because Diana, being willing to assist at the labor of
Olympias,
150 was absent from home.” But to this Goddess, because
ad
res omnes veniret—“she has an influence upon all things”—we have
given the appellation of Venus,
151 from whom the word
venustas
(beauty) is rather derived than Venus from
venustas.
XXVIII. Do you not see, therefore, how, from the productions of nature
and the useful inventions of men, have arisen fictitious and imaginary
Deities, which have been the foundation of false opinions, pernicious
errors, and wretched superstitions? For we know how the different forms
of the Gods—their ages, apparel, ornaments; their
282pedigrees,
marriages, relations, and everything belonging to them—are adapted to
human weakness and represented with our passions; with lust, sorrow, and
anger, according to fabulous history: they have had wars and combats,
not only, as Homer relates, when they have interested themselves in two
different armies, but when they have fought battles in their own defence
against the Titans and giants. These stories, of the greatest weakness
and levity, are related and believed with the most implicit folly.
But, rejecting these fables with contempt, a Deity is diffused in every
part of nature; in earth under the name of Ceres, in the sea under the
name of Neptune, in other parts under other names. Yet whatever they
are, and whatever characters and dispositions they have, and whatever
name custom has given them, we are bound to worship and adore them. The
best, the chastest, the most sacred and pious worship of the Gods is to
reverence them always with a pure, perfect, and unpolluted mind and
voice; for our ancestors, as well as the philosophers, have separated
superstition from religion. They who prayed whole days and sacrificed,
that their children might survive them (
ut superstites essent), were
called superstitious, which word became afterward more general; but they
who diligently perused, and, as we may say, read or practised over
again, all the duties relating to the worship of the Gods, were called
religiosi—religious, from
relegendo—“reading over again, or
practising;” as
elegantes, elegant,
ex eligendo, “from choosing,
making a good choice;”
diligentes, diligent,
ex diligendo, “from
attending on what we love;”
intelligentes, intelligent, from
understanding—for the signification is derived in the same manner. Thus
are the words superstitious and religious understood; the one being a
term of reproach, the other of commendation. I think I have now
sufficiently demonstrated that there are Gods, and what they are.
XXIX. I am now to show that the world is governed by the providence of
the Gods. This is an important point, which you Academics endeavor to
confound; and, indeed, the whole contest is with you, Cotta; for your
sect, Velleius, know very little of what is said on different subjects
by other schools. You read and have a taste only for
283your own books,
and condemn all others without examination. For instance, when you
mentioned yesterday
152 that prophetic old dame
О ПЃбЅ№ОЅОїО№О±, Providence,
invented by the Stoics, you were led into that error by imagining that
Providence was made by them to be a particular Deity that governs the
whole universe, whereas it is only spoken in a short manner; as when it
is said “The commonwealth of Athens is governed by the council,” it is
meant “of the Areopagus;”
153 so when we say “The world is governed by
providence,” we mean “by the providence of the Gods.” To express
ourselves, therefore, more fully and clearly, we say, “The world is
governed by the providence of the Gods.” Be not, therefore, lavish of
your railleries, of which your sect has little to spare: if I may advise
you, do not attempt it. It does not become you, it is not your talent,
nor is it in your power. This is not applied to you in particular who
have the education and politeness of a Roman, but to all your sect in
general, and especially to your leader
154—a man unpolished,
illiterate, insulting, without wit, without reputation, without
elegance.
XXX. I assert, then, that the universe, with all its parts, was
originally constituted, and has, without any cessation, been ever
governed by the providence of the Gods. This argument we Stoics commonly
divide into three parts; the first of which is, that the existence of
the Gods being once known, it must follow that the world is governed by
their wisdom; the second, that as everything is under the direction of
an intelligent nature, which has produced that beautiful order in the
world, it is evident that it is formed from animating principles; the
third is deduced from those glorious works which we behold in the
heavens and the earth.
First, then, we must either deny the existence of the Gods (as
Democritus and Epicurus by their doctrine of images in some sort do),
or, if we acknowledge that there
284are Gods, we must believe they are
employed, and that, too, in something excellent. Now, nothing is so
excellent as the administration of the universe. The universe,
therefore, is governed by the wisdom of the Gods. Otherwise, we must
imagine that there is some cause superior to the Deity, whether it be a
nature inanimate, or a necessity agitated by a mighty force, that
produces those beautiful works which we behold. The nature of the Gods
would then be neither supreme nor excellent, if you subject it to that
necessity or to that nature, by which you would make the heaven, the
earth, and the seas to be governed. But there is nothing superior to the
Deity; the world, therefore, must be governed by him: consequently, the
Deity is under no obedience or subjection to nature, but does himself
rule over all nature. In effect, if we allow the Gods have
understanding, we allow also their providence, which regards the most
important things; for, can they be ignorant of those important things,
and how they are to be conducted and preserved, or do they want power to
sustain and direct them? Ignorance is inconsistent with the nature of
the Gods, and imbecility is repugnant to their majesty. From whence it
follows, as we assert, that the world is governed by the providence of
the Gods.
XXXI. But supposing, which is incontestable, that there are Gods, they
must be animated, and not only animated, but endowed with
reason—united, as we may say, in a civil agreement and society, and
governing together one universe, as a republic or city. Thus the same
reason, the same verity, the same law, which ordains good and prohibits
evil, exists in the Gods as it does in men. From them, consequently, we
have prudence and understanding, for which reason our ancestors erected
temples to the Mind, Faith, Virtue, and Concord. Shall we not then allow
the Gods to have these perfections, since we worship the sacred and
august images of them? But if understanding, faith, virtue, and concord
reside in human kind, how could they come on earth, unless from heaven?
And if we are possessed of wisdom, reason, and prudence, the Gods must
have the same qualities in a greater degree; and not only have them, but
employ them in the best and greatest works. The universe is the best and
greatest
285work; therefore it must be governed by the wisdom and
providence of the Gods.
Lastly, as we have sufficiently shown that those glorious and luminous
bodies which we behold are Deities—I mean the sun, the moon, the fixed
and wandering stars, the firmament, and the world itself, and those
other things also which have any singular virtue, and are of any great
utility to human kind—it follows that all things are governed by
providence and a divine mind. But enough has been said on the first
part.
XXXII. It is now incumbent on me to prove that all things are subjected
to nature, and most beautifully directed by her. But, first of all, it
is proper to explain precisely what that nature is, in order to come to
the more easy understanding of what I would demonstrate. Some think that
nature is a certain irrational power exciting in bodies the necessary
motions. Others, that it is an intelligent power, acting by order and
method, designing some end in every cause, and always aiming at that
end, whose works express such skill as no art, no hand, can imitate;
for, they say, such is the virtue of its seed, that, however small it
is, if it falls into a place proper for its reception, and meets with
matter conducive to its nourishment and increase, it forms and produces
everything in its respective kind; either vegetables, which receive
their nourishment from their roots; or animals, endowed with motion,
sense, appetite, and abilities to beget their likeness.
Some apply the word nature to everything; as Epicurus does, who
acknowledges no cause, but atoms, a vacuum, and their accidents. But
when we
155 say that nature forms and governs the world, we do not
apply it to a clod of earth, or piece of stone, or anything of that
sort, whose parts have not the necessary cohesion,
156 but to a tree,
in
286which there is not the appearance of chance, but of order and a
resemblance of art.
XXXIII. But if the art of nature gives life and increase to vegetables,
without doubt it supports the earth itself; for, being impregnated with
seeds, she produces every kind of vegetable, and embracing their roots,
she nourishes and increases them; while, in her turn, she receives her
nourishment from the other elements, and by her exhalations gives proper
sustenance to the air, the sky, and all the superior bodies. If nature
gives vigor and support to the earth, by the same reason she has an
influence over the rest of the world; for as the earth gives nourishment
to vegetables, so the air is the preservation of animals. The air sees
with us, hears with us, and utters sounds with us; without it, there
would be no seeing, hearing, or sounding. It even moves with us; for
wherever we go, whatever motion we make, it seems to retire and give
place to us.
That which inclines to the centre, that which rises from it to the
surface, and that which rolls about the centre, constitute the universal
world, and make one entire nature; and as there are four sorts of
bodies, the continuance of nature is caused by their reciprocal changes;
for the water arises from the earth, the air from the water, and the
fire from the air; and, reversing this order, the air arises from fire,
the water from the air, and from the water the earth, the lowest of the
four elements, of which all beings are formed. Thus by their continual
motions backward and forward, upward and downward, the conjunction of
the several parts of the universe is preserved; a union which, in the
beauty we now behold it, must be eternal, or at least of a very long
duration, and almost for an infinite space of time; and, whichever it
is, the universe must of consequence be governed by nature. For what art
of navigating fleets, or of marshalling an army, and—to instance the
produce of nature—what vine, what tree, what animated form and
conformation of their members, give us so great an indication of skill
as appears in the universe? Therefore we must either deny that there is
the least trace of an intelligent nature, or acknowledge that the world
is governed by it. But since the universe
287contains all particular
beings, as well as their seeds, can we say that it is not itself
governed by nature? That would be the same as saying that the teeth and
the beard of man are the work of nature, but that the man himself is
not. Thus the effect would be understood to be greater than the cause.
XXXIV. Now, the universe sows, as I may say, plants, produces, raises,
nourishes, and preserves what nature administers, as members and parts
of itself. If nature, therefore, governs them, she must also govern the
universe. And, lastly, in nature’s administration there is nothing
faulty. She produced the best possible effect out of those elements
which existed. Let any one show how it could have been better. But that
can never be; and whoever attempts to mend it will either make it worse,
or aim at impossibilities.
But if all the parts of the universe are so constituted that nothing
could be better for use or beauty, let us consider whether this is the
effect of chance, or whether, in such a state they could possibly
cohere, but by the direction of wisdom and divine providence. Nature,
therefore, cannot be void of reason, if art can bring nothing to
perfection without it, and if the works of nature exceed those of art.
How is it consistent with common-sense that when you view an image or a
picture, you imagine it is wrought by art; when you behold afar off a
ship under sail, you judge it is steered by reason and art; when you see
a dial or water-clock,
157 you believe the hours are shown by art, and
not by chance; and yet that you should imagine that the universe, which
contains all arts and the artificers, can be void of reason and
understanding?
But if that sphere which was lately made by our friend Posidonius, the
regular revolutions of which show the course of the sun, moon, and five
wandering stars, as it is every day and night performed, were carried
into Scythia or Britain, who, in those barbarous countries, would doubt
that that sphere had been made so perfect by the exertion of reason?
XXXV. Yet these people
158 doubt whether the universe,
288from whence all
things arise and are made, is not the effect of chance, or some
necessity, rather than the work of reason and a divine mind. According
to them, Archimedes shows more knowledge in representing the motions of
the celestial globe than nature does in causing them, though the copy is
so infinitely beneath the original. The shepherd in Attius,
159 who had
never seen a ship, when he perceived from a mountain afar off the divine
vessel of the Argonauts, surprised and frighted at this new object,
expressed himself in this manner:
What horrid bulk is that before my eyes,
Which o’er the deep with noise and vigor flies?
It turns the whirlpools up, its force so strong,
And drives the billows as it rolls along.
The ocean’s violence it fiercely braves;
Runs furious on, and throws about the waves.
Swiftly impetuous in its course, and loud,
Like the dire bursting of a show’ry cloud;
Or, like a rock, forced by the winds and rain,
Now whirl’d aloft, then plunged into the main.
But hold! perhaps the Earth and Neptune jar,
And fiercely wage an elemental war;
Or Triton with his trident has o’erthrown
His den, and loosen’d from the roots the stone;
The rocky fragment, from the bottom torn,
Is lifted up, and on the surface borne.
At first he is in suspense at the sight of this unknown object; but on
seeing the young mariners, and hearing their singing, he says,
Like sportive dolphins, with their snouts they roar;
160
and afterward goes on,
Loud in my ears methinks their voices ring,
As if I heard the God Sylvanus sing.
As at first view the shepherd thinks he sees something inanimate and
insensible, but afterward, judging by more
289trustworthy indications, he
begins to figure to himself what it is; so philosophers, if they are
surprised at first at the sight of the universe, ought, when they have
considered the regular, uniform, and immutable motions of it, to
conceive that there is some Being that is not only an inhabitant of this
celestial and divine mansion, but a ruler and a governor, as architect
of this mighty fabric.
XXXVI. Now, in my opinion, they
161 do not seem to have even the least
suspicion that the heavens and earth afford anything marvellous. For, in
the first place, the earth is situated in the middle part of the
universe, and is surrounded on all sides by the air, which we breathe,
and which is called “aer,”
162 which, indeed, is a Greek word; but by
constant use it is well understood by our countrymen, for, indeed, it is
employed as a Latin word. The air is encompassed by the boundless ether
(sky), which consists of the fires above. This word we borrow also, for
we use
Г¦ther in Latin as well as
aer; though Pacuvius thus expresses
it,
—This, of which I speak,
In Latin’s cœlum, æther call’d in Greek.
As though he were not a Greek into whose mouth he puts this sentence;
but he is speaking in Latin, though we listen as if he were speaking
Greek; for, as he says elsewhere,
His speech discovers him a Grecian born.
But to return to more important matters. In the sky innumerable fiery
stars exist, of which the sun is the chief, enlightening all with his
refulgent splendor, and being by many degrees larger than the whole
earth; and this multitude of vast fires are so far from hurting the
earth, and things terrestrial, that they are of benefit to them;
whereas, if they were moved from their stations, we should inevitably be
burned through the want of a proper moderation and temperature of heat.
XXXVII. Is it possible for any man to behold these things, and yet
imagine that certain solid and individual bodies move by their natural
force and gravitation, and that a world so beautifully adorned was made
by their fortuitous concourse? He who believes this may as well
290believe
that if a great quantity of the one-and-twenty letters, composed either
of gold or any other matter, were thrown upon the ground, they would
fall into such order as legibly to form the Annals of Ennius. I doubt
whether fortune could make a single verse of them. How, therefore, can
these people assert that the world was made by the fortuitous concourse
of atoms, which have no color, no quality—which the Greeks call
ПЂОїО№бЅ№П„О·П‚, no sense? or that there are innumerable worlds, some rising and
some perishing, in every moment of time? But if a concourse of atoms can
make a world, why not a porch, a temple, a house, a city, which are
works of less labor and difficulty?
Certainly those men talk so idly and inconsiderately concerning this
lower world that they appear to me never to have contemplated the
wonderful magnificence of the heavens; which is the next topic for our
consideration.
Well, then, did Aristotle
163 observe: “If there were men whose
habitations had been always underground, in great and commodious houses,
adorned with statues and pictures, furnished with everything which they
who are reputed happy abound with; and if, without stirring from thence,
they should be informed of a certain divine power and majesty, and,
after some time, the earth should open, and they should quit their dark
abode to come to us, where they should immediately behold the earth, the
seas, the heavens; should consider the vast extent of the clouds and
force of the winds; should see the sun, and observe his grandeur and
beauty, and also his generative power, inasmuch as day is occasioned by
the diffusion of his light through the sky; and when night has obscured
the earth, they should contemplate the heavens bespangled and adorned
with stars, the surprising variety of the moon in her increase and wane,
the rising and setting of all the stars, and the inviolable regularity
of their courses; when,” says he, “they should see these things, they
would undoubtedly conclude that there are Gods, and that these are their
mighty works.”
XXXVIII. Thus far Aristotle. Let us imagine, also, as great darkness as
was formerly occasioned by the irruption of the fires of Mount Г†tna,
which are said to have obscured
291the adjacent countries for two days to
such a degree that no man could recognize his fellow; but on the third,
when the sun appeared, they seemed to be risen from the dead. Now, if we
should be suddenly brought from a state of eternal darkness to see the
light, how beautiful would the heavens seem! But our minds have become
used to it from the daily practice and habituation of our eyes, nor do
we take the trouble to search into the principles of what is always in
view; as if the novelty, rather than the importance, of things ought to
excite us to investigate their causes.
Is he worthy to be called a man who attributes to chance, not to an
intelligent cause, the constant motion of the heavens, the regular
courses of the stars, the agreeable proportion and connection of all
things, conducted with so much reason that our intellect itself is
unable to estimate it rightly? When we see machines move artificially,
as a sphere, a clock, or the like, do we doubt whether they are the
productions of reason? And when we behold the heavens moving with a
prodigious celerity, and causing an annual succession of the different
seasons of the year, which vivify and preserve all things, can we doubt
that this world is directed, I will not say only by reason, but by
reason most excellent and divine? For without troubling ourselves with
too refined a subtlety of discussion, we may use our eyes to contemplate
the beauty of those things which we assert have been arranged by divine
providence.
XXXIX. First, let us examine the earth, whose situation is in the middle
of the universe,
164 solid, round, and conglobular by its natural
tendency; clothed with flowers, herbs, trees, and fruits; the whole in
multitudes incredible, and with a variety suitable to every taste: let
us consider the ever-cool and running springs, the clear waters of the
rivers, the verdure of their banks, the hollow depths of caves, the
cragginess of rocks, the heights of impending mountains, and the
boundless extent of plains, the hidden veins of gold and silver, and the
infinite quarries of marble.
292What and how various are the kinds of animals, tame or wild? The
flights and notes of birds? How do the beasts live in the fields and in
the forests? What shall I say of men, who, being appointed, as we may
say, to cultivate the earth, do not suffer its fertility to be choked
with weeds, nor the ferocity of beasts to make it desolate; who, by the
houses and cities which they build, adorn the fields, the isles, and the
shores? If we could view these objects with the naked eye, as we can by
the contemplation of the mind, nobody, at such a sight, would doubt
there was a divine intelligence.
But how beautiful is the sea! How pleasant to see the extent of it! What
a multitude and variety of islands! How delightful are the coasts! What
numbers and what diversity of inhabitants does it contain; some within
the bosom of it, some floating on the surface, and others by their
shells cleaving to the rocks! While the sea itself, approaching to the
land, sports so closely to its shores that those two elements appear to
be but one.
Next above the sea is the air, diversified by day and night: when
rarefied, it possesses the higher region; when condensed, it turns into
clouds, and with the waters which it gathers enriches the earth by the
rain. Its agitation produces the winds. It causes heat and cold
according to the different seasons. It sustains birds in their flight;
and, being inhaled, nourishes and preserves all animated beings.
XL. Add to these, which alone remaineth to be mentioned, the firmament
of heaven, a region the farthest from our abodes, which surrounds and
contains all things. It is likewise called ether, or sky, the extreme
bounds and limits of the universe, in which the stars perform their
appointed courses in a most wonderful manner; among which, the sun,
whose magnitude far surpasses the earth, makes his revolution round it,
and by his rising and setting causes day and night; sometimes coming
near towards the earth, and sometimes going from it, he every year makes
two contrary reversions
165 from the extreme
293point of its course. In
his retreat the earth seems locked up in sadness; in his return it
appears exhilarated with the heavens. The moon, which, as mathematicians
demonstrate, is bigger than half the earth, makes her revolutions
through the same spaces
166 as the sun; but at one time approaching,
and at another receding from, the sun, she diffuses the light which she
has borrowed from him over the whole earth, and has herself also many
various changes in her appearance. When she is found under the sun, and
opposite to it, the brightness of her rays is lost; but when the earth
directly interposes between the moon and sun, the moon is totally
eclipsed. The other wandering stars have their courses round the earth
in the same spaces,
167 and rise and set in the same manner; their
motions are sometimes quick, sometimes slow, and often they stand still.
There is nothing more wonderful, nothing more beautiful. There is a vast
number of fixed stars, distinguished by the names of certain figures, to
which we find they have some resemblance.
XLI. I will here, says Balbus, looking at me, make use of the verses
which, when you were young, you translated from Aratus,
168 and which,
because they are in Latin, gave me so much delight that I have many of
them still in my memory. As then, we daily see, without any change or
variation,
—the rest169
Swiftly pursue the course to which they’re bound;
And with the heavens the days and nights go round;
the contemplation of which, to a mind desirous of observing the
constancy of nature, is inexhaustible.
The extreme top of either point is call’d
The pole.
170
294About this the two бјЊПЃОєП„ОїО№ are turned, which never set;
Of these, the Greeks one Cynosura call,
The other Helice.
171
The brightest stars,172 indeed, of Helice are discernible all night,
Which are by us Septentriones call’d.
Cynosura moves about the same pole, with a like number of stars, and
ranged in the same order:
This
173 the PhЕ“nicians choose to make their guide
When on the ocean in the night they ride.
Adorned with stars of more refulgent light,
The other
174 shines, and first appears at night.
Though this is small, sailors its use have found;
More inward is its course, and short its round.
XLII. The aspect of those stars is the more admirable, because,
The Dragon grim between them bends his way,
As through the winding banks the currents stray,
And up and down in sinuous bending rolls.
175
His whole form is excellent; but the shape of his head and the ardor of
his eyes are most remarkable.
Various the stars which deck his glittering head;
His temples are with double glory spread;
From his fierce eyes two fervid lights afar
Flash, and his chin shines with one radiant star;
Bow’d is his head; and his round neck he bends,
And to the tail of Helice
176 extends.
The rest of the Dragon’s body we see177 at every hour in the night.
295Here
178 suddenly the head a little hides
Itself, where all its parts, which are in sight,
And those unseen in the same place unite.
Near to this head
Is placed the figure of a man that moves
Weary and sad,
which the Greeks
Engonasis do call, because he’s borne
179
About with bended knee. Near him is placed
The crown with a refulgent lustre graced.
This indeed is at his back; but Anguitenens (the Snake-holder) is near
his head:180
The Greeks him Ophiuchus call, renown’d
The name. He strongly grasps the serpent round
With both his hands; himself the serpent folds
Beneath his breast, and round his middle holds;
Yet gravely he, bright shining in the skies,
Moves on, and treads on Nepa’s
181 breast and eyes.
The Septentriones182 are followed by—
Arctophylax,
183 that’s said to be the same
Which we Boötes call, who has the name,
Because he drives the Greater Bear along
Yoked to a wain.
Besides, in Boötes,
A star of glittering rays about his waist,
Arcturus called, a name renown’d, is placed.
184
296Beneath which is
The Virgin of illustrious form, whose hand
Holds a bright spike.
XLIII. And truly these signs are so regularly disposed that a divine
wisdom evidently appears in them:
Beneath the Bear’s
185 head have the Twins their seat,
Under his chest the Crab, beneath his feet
The mighty Lion darts a trembling flame.
186
The Charioteer
On the left side of Gemini we see,
187
And at his head behold fierce Helice;
On his left shoulder the bright Goat appears.
But to proceed—
This is indeed a great and glorious star,
On th’ other side the Kids, inferior far,
Yield but a slender light to mortal eyes.
Under his feet
The horned bull,
188 with sturdy limbs, is placed:
his head is spangled with a number of stars;
These by the Greeks are called the Hyades,
from raining; for бЅ•ОµО№ОЅ is to rain: therefore they are injudiciously
called Suculæ by our people, as if they had their name from ὗς, a sow,
and not from бЅ•П‰.
Behind the Lesser Bear, Cepheus189 follows with extended hands,
For close behind the Lesser Bear he comes.
297Before him goes
Cassiopea
190 with a faintish light;
But near her moves (fair and illustrious sight!)
Andromeda,
191 who, with an eager pace,
Seems to avoid her parent’s mournful face.
192
With glittering mane the Horse
193 now seems to tread,
So near he comes, on her refulgent head;
With a fair star, that close to him appears,
A double form
194 and but one light he wears;
By which he seems ambitious in the sky
An everlasting knot of stars to tie.
Near him the Ram, with wreathed horns, is placed;
by whom
The Fishes
195 are; of which one seems to haste
Somewhat before the other, to the blast
Of the north wind exposed.
XLIV. Perseus is described as placed at the feet of Andromeda:
And him the sharp blasts of the north wind beat.
Near his left knee, but dim their light, their seat
The small Pleiades
196 maintain. We find,
Not far from them, the Lyre
197 but slightly join’d.
Next is the winged Bird,
198 that seems to fly
Beneath the spacious covering of the sky.
298Near the head of the Horse199 lies the right hand of Aquarius, then
all Aquarius himself.200
Then Capricorn, with half the form of beast,
Breathes chill and piercing colds from his strong breast,
And in a spacious circle takes his round;
When him, while in the winter solstice bound,
The sun has visited with constant light,
He turns his course, and shorter makes the night.
201
Not far from hence is seen
The Scorpion
202 rising lofty from below;
By him the Archer,
203 with his bended bow;
Near him the Bird, with gaudy feathers spread;
And the fierce Eagle
204 hovers o’er his head.
Next comes the Dolphin;205
Then bright Orion,
206 who obliquely moves;
he is followed by
The fervent Dog,
207 bright with refulgent stars:
next the Hare follows208
Unwearied in his course. At the Dog’s tail
Argo
209 moves on, and moving seems to sail;
O’er her the Ram and Fishes have their place;
210
The illustrious vessel touches, in her pace,
The river’s banks;
211
which you may see winding and extending itself to a great length.
299The Fetters
212 at the Fishes’ tails are hung.
By Nepa’s
213 head behold the Altar stand,
214
Which by the breath of southern winds is fann’d;
near which the Centaur215
Hastens his mingled parts to join beneath
The Serpent,
216 there extending his right hand,
To where you see the monstrous Scorpion stand,
Which he at the bright Altar fiercely slays.
Here on her lower parts see Hydra
217 raise
Herself;
whose bulk is very far extended.
Amid the winding of her body’s placed
The shining Goblet;
218 and the glossy Crow
219
Plunges his beak into her parts below.
Antecanis beneath the Twins is seen,
Call’d Procyon by the Greeks.
220
Can any one in his senses imagine that this disposition of the stars,
and this heaven so beautifully adorned, could ever have been formed by a
fortuitous concourse of atoms? Or what other nature, being destitute of
intellect and reason, could possibly have produced these effects, which
not only required reason to bring them about, but the very character of
which could not be understood and appreciated without the most strenuous
exertions of well-directed reason?
XLV. But our admiration is not limited to the objects here described.
What is most wonderful is that the world is so durable, and so perfectly
made for lasting that it is not to be impaired by time; for all its
parts tend equally to the centre, and are bound together by a sort of
chain, which surrounds the elements. This chain is nature, which
300being
diffused through the universe, and performing all things with judgment
and reason, attracts the extremities to the centre.
If, then, the world is round, and if on that account all its parts,
being of equal dimensions and relative proportions, mutually support and
are supported by one another, it must follow that as all the parts
incline to the centre (for that is the lowest place of a globe) there is
nothing whatever which can put a stop to that propensity in the case of
such great weights. For the same reason, though the sea is higher than
the earth, yet because it has the like tendency, it is collected
everywhere, equally concentres, and never overflows, and is never
wasted.
The air, which is contiguous, ascends by its lightness, but diffuses
itself through the whole; therefore it is by nature joined and united to
the sea, and at the same time borne by the same power towards the
heaven, by the thinness and heat of which it is so tempered as to be
made proper to supply life and wholesome air for the support of animated
beings. This is encompassed by the highest region of the heavens, which
is called the sky, which is joined to the extremity of the air, but
retains its own heat pure and unmixed.
XLVI. The stars have their revolutions in the sky, and are continued by
the tendency of all parts towards the centre. Their duration is
perpetuated by their form and figure, for they are round; which form, as
I think has been before observed, is the least liable to injury; and as
they are composed of fire, they are fed by the vapors which are exhaled
by the sun from the earth, the sea, and other waters; but when these
vapors have nourished and refreshed the stars, and the whole sky, they
are sent back to be exhaled again; so that very little is lost or
consumed by the fire of the stars and the flame of the sky. Hence we
Stoics conclude—which Panætius
221 is said to have doubted of—that
the whole world at last would be consumed by a general conflagration,
when, all moisture being exhausted, neither the earth could have any
nourishment, nor the air return again, since water, of which it is
formed, would then be all consumed; so that only fire would subsist; and
301from this fire, which is an animating power and a Deity, a new world
would arise and be re-established in the same beauty.
I should be sorry to appear to you to dwell too long upon this subject
of the stars, and more especially upon that of the planets, whose
motions, though different, make a very just agreement. Saturn, the
highest, chills; Mars, placed in the middle, burns; while Jupiter,
interposing, moderates their excess, both of light and heat. The two
planets beneath Mars
222 obey the sun. The sun himself fills the whole
universe with his own genial light; and the moon, illuminated by him,
influences conception, birth, and maturity. And who is there who is not
moved by this union of things, and by this concurrence of nature
agreeing together, as it were, for the safety of the world? And yet I
feel sure that none of these reflections have ever been made by these
men.
XLVII. Let us proceed from celestial to terrestrial things. What is
there in them which does not prove the principle of an intelligent
nature? First, as to vegetables; they have roots to sustain their stems,
and to draw from the earth a nourishing moisture to support the vital
principle which those roots contain. They are clothed with a rind or
bark, to secure them more thoroughly from heat and cold. The vines we
see take hold on props with their tendrils, as if with hands, and raise
themselves as if they were animated; it is even said that they shun
cabbages and coleworts, as noxious and pestilential to them, and, if
planted by them, will not touch any part.
But what a vast variety is there of animals! and how wonderfully is
every kind adapted to preserve itself! Some are covered with hides, some
clothed with fleeces, and some guarded with bristles; some are sheltered
with feathers, some with scales; some are armed with horns, and some are
furnished with wings to escape from danger. Nature hath also liberally
and plentifully provided for all animals their proper food. I could
expatiate on the judicious and curious formation and disposition of
their bodies for the reception and digestion of it, for all their
interior parts are so framed and disposed that there is
302nothing
superfluous, nothing that is not necessary for the preservation of life.
Besides, nature has also given these beasts appetite and sense; in order
that by the one they may be excited to procure sufficient sustenance,
and by the other they may distinguish what is noxious from what is
salutary. Some animals seek their food walking, some creeping, some
flying, and some swimming; some take it with their mouth and teeth; some
seize it with their claws, and some with their beaks; some suck, some
graze, some bolt it whole, and some chew it. Some are so low that they
can with ease take such food as is to be found on the ground; but the
taller, as geese, swans, cranes, and camels, are assisted by a length of
neck. To the elephant is given a hand,
223 without which, from his
unwieldiness of body, he would scarce have any means of attaining food.
XLVIII. But to those beasts which live by preying on others, nature has
given either strength or swiftness. On some animals she has even
bestowed artifice and cunning; as on spiders, some of which weave a sort
of net to entrap and destroy whatever falls into it, others sit on the
watch unobserved to fall on their prey and devour it. The naker—by the
Greeks called
Pinna—has a kind of confederacy with the prawn for
procuring food. It has two large shells open, into which when the little
fishes swim, the naker, having notice given by the bite of the prawn,
closes them immediately. Thus, these little animals, though of different
kinds, seek their food in common; in which it is matter of wonder
whether they associate by any agreement, or are naturally joined
together from their beginning.
There is some cause to admire also the provision of nature in the case
of those aquatic animals which are generated on land, such as
crocodiles, river-tortoises, and a certain kind of serpents, which seek
the water as soon as they are able to drag themselves along. We
frequently put duck-eggs under hens, by which, as by their true mothers,
the ducklings are at first hatched and nourished; but when they see the
water, they forsake them and run to it, as to
303their natural abode: so
strong is the impression of nature in animals for their own
preservation.
XLIX. I have read that there is a bird called Platalea (the shoveller),
that lives by watching those fowls which dive into the sea for their
prey, and when they return with it, he squeezes their heads with his
beak till they drop it, and then seizes on it himself. It is said
likewise that he is in the habit of filling his stomach with shell-fish,
and when they are digested by the heat which exists in the stomach, they
cast them up, and then pick out what is proper nourishment. The
sea-frogs, they say, are wont to cover themselves with sand, and moving
near the water, the fishes strike at them, as at a bait, and are
themselves taken and devoured by the frogs. Between the kite and the
crow there is a kind of natural war, and wherever the one finds the eggs
of the other, he breaks them.
But who is there who can avoid being struck with wonder at that which
has been noticed by Aristotle, who has enriched us with so many valuable
remarks? When the cranes
224 pass the sea in search of warmer climes,
they fly in the form of a triangle. By the first angle they repel the
resisting air; on each side, their wings serve as oars to facilitate
their flight; and the basis of their triangle is assisted by the wind in
their stern. Those which are behind rest their necks and heads on those
which precede; and as the leader has not the same relief, because he has
none to lean upon, he at length flies behind that he may also rest,
while one of those which have been eased succeeds him, and through the
whole flight each regularly takes his turn.
I could produce many instances of this kind; but these may suffice. Let
us now proceed to things more familiar to us. The care of beasts for
their own preservation, their circumspection while feeding, and their
manner of taking rest in their lairs, are generally known, but still
they are greatly to be admired.
L. Dogs cure themselves by a vomit, the Egyptian ibis by a purge; from
whence physicians have lately—I mean but few ages since—greatly
improved their art. It is reported
304that panthers, which in barbarous
countries are taken with poisoned flesh, have a certain remedy
225 that
preserves them from dying; and that in Crete, the wild goats, when they
are wounded with poisoned arrows, seek for an herb called dittany,
which, when they have tasted, the arrows (they say) drop from their
bodies. It is said also that deer, before they fawn, purge themselves
with a little herb called hartswort.
226 Beasts, when they receive any
hurt, or fear it, have recourse to their natural arms: the bull to his
horns, the boar to his tusks, and the lion to his teeth. Some take to
flight, others hide themselves; the cuttle-fish vomits
227 blood; the
cramp-fish benumbs; and there are many animals that, by their
intolerable stink, oblige their pursuers to retire.
LI. But that the beauty of the world might be eternal, great care has
been taken by the providence of the Gods to perpetuate the different
kinds of animals, and vegetables, and trees, and all those things which
sink deep into the earth, and are contained in it by their roots and
trunks; in order to which every individual has within itself such
fertile seed that many are generated from one; and in vegetables this
seed is enclosed in the heart of their fruit, but in such abundance that
men may plentifully feed on it, and the earth be always replanted.
With regard to animals, do we not see how aptly they are formed for the
propagation of their species? Nature for this end created some males and
some females. Their parts are perfectly framed for generation, and they
have a wonderful propensity to copulation. When the seed has fallen on
the matrix, it draws almost all the nourishment to itself, by which the
fЕ“tus is formed; but as soon as it is discharged from thence, if it is
an animal that is nourished by milk, almost all the food of the mother
turns into milk, and the animal, without any direction but by the pure
instinct of nature, immediately hunts for the
305teat, and is there fed
with plenty. What makes it evidently appear that there is nothing in
this fortuitous, but the work of a wise and foreseeing nature, is, that
those females which bring forth many young, as sows and bitches, have
many teats, and those which bear a small number have but few. What
tenderness do beasts show in preserving and raising up their young till
they are able to defend themselves! They say, indeed, that fish, when
they have spawned, leave their eggs; but the water easily supports them,
and produces the young fry in abundance.
LII. It is said, likewise, that tortoises and crocodiles, when they have
laid their eggs on the land, only cover them with earth, and then leave
them, so that their young are hatched and brought up without assistance;
but fowls and other birds seek for quiet places to lay in, where they
build their nests in the softest manner, for the surest preservation of
their eggs; which, when they have hatched, they defend from the cold by
the warmth of their wings, or screen them from the sultry heat of the
sun. When their young begin to be able to use their wings, they attend
and instruct them; and then their cares are at an end.
Human art and industry are indeed necessary towards the preservation and
improvement of certain animals and vegetables; for there are several of
both kinds which would perish without that assistance. There are
likewise innumerable facilities (being different in different places)
supplied to man to aid him in his civilization, and in procuring
abundantly what he requires. The Nile waters Egypt, and after having
overflowed and covered it the whole summer, it retires, and leaves the
fields softened and manured for the reception of seed. The Euphrates
fertilizes Mesopotamia, into which, as we may say, it carries yearly new
fields.
228 The Indus, which is the largest of all rivers,
229 not
only improves and cultivates the ground,
306but sows it also; for it is
said to carry with it a great quantity of grain. I could mention many
other countries remarkable for something singular, and many fields,
which are, in their own natures, exceedingly fertile.
LIII. But how bountiful is nature that has provided for us such an
abundance of various and delicious food; and this varying with the
different seasons, so that we may be constantly pleased with change, and
satisfied with abundance! How seasonable and useful to man, to beasts,
and even to vegetables, are the Etesian winds
230 she has bestowed,
which moderate intemperate heat, and render navigation more sure and
speedy! Many things must be omitted on a subject so copious—and still a
great deal must be said—for it is impossible to relate the great
utility of rivers, the flux and reflux of the sea, the mountains clothed
with grass and trees, the salt-pits remote from the sea-coasts, the
earth replete with salutary medicines, or, in short, the innumerable
designs of nature necessary for sustenance and the enjoyment of life. We
must not forget the vicissitudes of day and night, ordained for the
health of animated beings, giving them a time to labor and a time to
rest. Thus, if we every way examine the universe, it is apparent, from
the greatest reason, that the whole is admirably governed by a divine
providence for the safety and preservation of all beings.
If it should be asked for whose sake this mighty fabric was raised,
shall we say for trees and other vegetables, which, though destitute of
sense, are supported by nature? That would be absurd. Is it for beasts?
Nothing can be less probable than that the Gods should have taken such
pains for beings void of speech and understanding. For whom, then, will
any one presume to say that the world was made? Undoubtedly for
reasonable beings; these are the Gods and men, who are certainly the
most perfect of all beings, as nothing is equal to reason. It is
therefore credible that the universe, and all things in it, were made
for the Gods and for men.
But we may yet more easily comprehend that the Gods have taken great
care of the interests and welfare of men,
307if we examine thoroughly into
the structure of the body, and the form and perfection of human nature.
There are three things absolutely necessary for the support of life—to
eat, to drink, and to breathe. For these operations the mouth is most
aptly framed, which, by the assistance of the nostrils, draws in the
more air.
LIV. The teeth are there placed to divide and grind the food.
231 The
fore-teeth, being sharp and opposite to each other, cut it asunder, and
the hind-teeth (called the grinders) chew it, in which office the tongue
seems to assist. At the root of the tongue is the gullet, which receives
whatever is swallowed: it touches the tonsils on each side, and
terminates at the interior extremity of the palate. When, by the motions
of the tongue, the food is forced into this passage, it descends, and
those parts of the gullet which are below it are dilated, and those
above are contracted. There is another passage, called by physicians the
rough artery,
232 which reaches to the lungs, for the entrance and
return of the air we breathe; and as its orifice is joined to the roots
of the tongue a little above the part to which the gullet is annexed, it
is furnished with a sort of coverlid,
233 lest, by the accidental
falling of any food into it, the respiration should be stopped.
As the stomach, which is beneath the gullet, receives the meat and
drink, so the lungs and the heart draw in the air from without. The
stomach is wonderfully composed, consisting almost wholly of nerves; it
abounds with membranes and fibres, and detains what it receives, whether
solid or liquid, till it is altered and digested. It sometimes
contracts, sometimes dilates. It blends and mixes the food together, so
that it is easily concocted and digested by its force of heat, and by
the animal spirits is distributed into the other parts of the body.
LV. As to the lungs, they are of a soft and spongy substance, which
renders them the most commodious for respiration;
308they alternately
dilate and contract to receive and return the air, that what is the
chief animal sustenance may be always fresh. The juice,
234 by which we
are nourished, being separated from the rest of the food, passes the
stomach and intestines to the liver, through open and direct passages,
which lead from the mesentery to the gates of the liver (for so they
call those vessels at the entrance of it). There are other passages from
thence, through which the food has its course when it has passed the
liver. When the bile, and those humors which proceed from the kidneys,
are separated from the food, the remaining part turns to blood, and
flows to those vessels at the entrance of the liver to which all the
passages adjoin. The chyle, being conveyed from this place through them
into the vessel called the hollow vein, is mixed together, and, being
already digested and distilled, passes into the heart; and from the
heart it is communicated through a great number of veins to every part
of the body.
It is not difficult to describe how the gross remains are detruded by
the motion of the intestines, which contract and dilate; but that must
be declined, as too indelicate for discourse. Let us rather explain that
other wonder of nature, the air, which is drawn into the lungs, receives
heat both by that already in and by the coagitation of the lungs; one
part is turned back by respiration, and the other is received into a
place called the ventricle of the heart.
235 There is another ventricle
like it annexed to the heart, into which the blood flows from the liver
through the hollow vein. Thus by one ventricle the blood is diffused to
the extremities through the veins, and by the other the breath is
communicated through the arteries; and there are such numbers of both
dispersed through the whole body that they manifest a divine art.
Why need I speak of the bones, those supports of the body, whose joints
are so wonderfully contrived for stability, and to render the limbs
complete with regard to motion and to every action of the body? Or need
I mention
309the nerves, by which the limbs are governed—their many
interweavings, and their proceeding from the heart,
236 from whence,
like the veins and arteries, they have their origin, and are distributed
through the whole corporeal frame?
LVI. To this skill of nature, and this care of providence, so diligent
and so ingenious, many reflections may be added, which show what
valuable things the Deity has bestowed on man. He has made us of a
stature tall and upright, in order that we might behold the heavens, and
so arrive at the knowledge of the Gods; for men are not simply to dwell
here as inhabitants of the earth, but to be, as it were, spectators of
the heavens and the stars, which is a privilege not granted to any other
kind of animated beings. The senses, which are the interpreters and
messengers of things, are placed in the head, as in a tower, and
wonderfully situated for their proper uses; for the eyes, being in the
highest part, have the office of sentinels, in discovering to us
objects; and the ears are conveniently placed in a high part of the
person, being appointed to receive sound, which naturally ascends. The
nostrils have the like situation, because all scent likewise ascends;
and they have, with great reason, a near vicinity to the mouth, because
they assist us in judging of meat and drink. The taste, which is to
distinguish the quality of what we take; is in that part of the mouth
where nature has laid open a passage for what we eat and drink. But the
touch is equally diffused through the whole body, that we may not
receive any blows, or the too rigid attacks of cold and heat, without
feeling them. And as in building the architect averts from the eyes and
nose of the master those things which must necessarily be offensive, so
has nature removed far from our senses what is of the same kind in the
human body.
LVII. What artificer but nature, whose direction is incomparable, could
have exhibited so much ingenuity in the formation of the senses? In the
first place, she has covered and invested the eyes with the finest
membranes, which she hath made transparent, that we may see through
310them, and firm in their texture, to preserve the eyes. She has made
them slippery and movable, that they might avoid what would offend them,
and easily direct the sight wherever they will. The actual organ of
sight, which is called the pupil, is so small that it can easily shun
whatever might be hurtful to it. The eyelids, which are their coverings,
are soft and smooth, that they may not injure the eyes; and are made to
shut at the apprehension of any accident, or to open at pleasure; and
these movements nature has ordained to be made in an instant: they are
fortified with a sort of palisade of hairs, to keep off what may be
noxious to them when open, and to be a fence to their repose when sleep
closes them, and allows them to rest as if they were wrapped up in a
case. Besides, they are commodiously hidden and defended by eminences on
every side; for on the upper part the eyebrows turn aside the
perspiration which falls from the head and forehead; the cheeks beneath
rise a little, so as to protect them on the lower side; and the nose is
placed between them as a wall of separation.
The hearing is always open, for that is a sense of which we are in need
even while we are sleeping; and the moment that any sound is admitted by
it we are awakened even from sleep. It has a winding passage, lest
anything should slip into it, as it might if it were straight and
simple. Nature also hath taken the same precaution in making there a
viscous humor, that if any little creatures should endeavor to creep in,
they might stick in it as in bird-lime. The ears (by which we mean the
outward part) are made prominent, to cover and preserve the hearing,
lest the sound should be dissipated and escape before the sense is
affected. Their entrances are hard and horny, and their form winding,
because bodies of this kind better return and increase the sound. This
appears in the harp, lute, or horn;
237 and from all tortuous and
enclosed places sounds are returned stronger.
The nostrils, in like manner, are ever open, because we have a continual
use for them; and their entrances also are rather narrow, lest anything
noxious should enter
311them; and they have always a humidity necessary
for the repelling dust and many other extraneous bodies. The taste,
having the mouth for an enclosure, is admirably situated, both in regard
to the use we make of it and to its security.
LVIII. Besides, every human sense is much more exquisite than those of
brutes; for our eyes, in those arts which come under their judgment,
distinguish with great nicety; as in painting, sculpture, engraving, and
in the gesture and motion of bodies. They understand the beauty,
proportion, and, as I may so term it, the becomingness of colors and
figures; they distinguish things of greater importance, even virtues and
vices; they know whether a man is angry or calm, cheerful or sad,
courageous or cowardly, bold or timorous.
The judgment of the ears is not less admirably and scientifically
contrived with regard to vocal and instrumental music. They distinguish
the variety of sounds, the measure, the stops, the different sorts of
voices, the treble and the base, the soft and the harsh, the sharp and
the flat, of which human ears only are capable to judge. There is
likewise great judgment in the smell, the taste, and the touch; to
indulge and gratify which senses more arts have been invented than I
could wish: it is apparent to what excess we have arrived in the
composition of our perfumes, the preparation of our food, and the
enjoyment of corporeal pleasures.
LIX. Again, he who does not perceive the soul and mind of man, his
reason, prudence, and discernment, to be the work of a divine
providence, seems himself to be destitute of those faculties. While I am
on this subject, Cotta, I wish I had your eloquence: how would you
illustrate so fine a subject! You would show the great extent of the
understanding; how we collect our ideas, and join those which follow to
those which precede; establish principles, draw consequences, define
things separately, and comprehend them with accuracy; from whence you
demonstrate how great is the power of intelligence and knowledge, which
is such that even God himself has no qualities more admirable. How
valuable (though you Academics despise and even deny that we have it) is
our
312knowledge of exterior objects, from the perception of the senses
joined to the application of the mind; by which we see in what relation
one thing stands to another, and by the aid of which we have invented
those arts which are necessary for the support and pleasure of life. How
charming is eloquence! How divine that mistress of the universe, as you
call it! It teaches us what we were ignorant of, and makes us capable of
teaching what we have learned. By this we exhort others; by this we
persuade them; by this we comfort the afflicted; by this we deliver the
affrighted from their fear; by this we moderate excessive joy; by this
we assuage the passions of lust and anger. This it is which bound men by
the chains of right and law, formed the bonds of civil society, and made
us quit a wild and savage life.
And it will appear incredible, unless you carefully observe the facts,
how complete the work of nature is in giving us the use of speech; for,
first of all, there is an artery from the lungs to the bottom of the
mouth, through which the voice, having its original principle in the
mind, is transmitted. Then the tongue is placed in the mouth, bounded by
the teeth. It softens and modulates the voice, which would otherwise be
confusedly uttered; and, by pushing it to the teeth and other parts of
the mouth, makes the sound distinct and articulate. We Stoics,
therefore, compare the tongue to the bow of an instrument, the teeth to
the strings, and the nostrils to the sounding-board.
LX. But how commodious are the hands which nature has given to man, and
how beautifully do they minister to many arts! For, such is the
flexibility of the joints, that our fingers are closed and opened
without any difficulty. With their help, the hand is formed for
painting, carving, and engraving; for playing on stringed instruments,
and on the pipe. These are matters of pleasure. There are also works of
necessity, such as tilling the ground, building houses, making cloth and
habits, and working in brass and iron. It is the business of the mind to
invent, the senses to perceive, and the hands to execute; so that if we
have buildings, if we are clothed, if we live in safety, if we have
cities, walls, habitations, and temples, it is to the hands we owe them.
313By our labor, that is, by our hands, variety and plenty of food are
provided; for, without culture, many fruits, which serve either for
present or future consumption, would not be produced; besides, we feed
on flesh, fish, and fowl, catching some, and bringing up others. We
subdue four-footed beasts for our carriage, whose speed and strength
supply our slowness and inability. On some we put burdens, on others
yokes. We convert the sagacity of the elephant and the quick scent of
the dog to our own advantage. Out of the caverns of the earth we dig
iron, a thing entirely necessary for the cultivation of the ground. We
discover the hidden veins of copper, silver, and gold, advantageous for
our use and beautiful as ornaments. We cut down trees, and use every
kind of wild and cultivated timber, not only to make fire to warm us and
dress our meat, but also for building, that we may have houses to defend
us from the heat and cold. With timber likewise we build ships, which
bring us from all parts every commodity of life. We are the only animals
who, from our knowledge of navigation, can manage what nature has made
the most violent—the sea and the winds. Thus we obtain from the ocean
great numbers of profitable things. We are the absolute masters of what
the earth produces. We enjoy the mountains and the plains. The rivers
and the lakes are ours. We sow the seed, and plant the trees. We
fertilize the earth by overflowing it. We stop, direct, and turn the
rivers: in short, by our hands we endeavor, by our various operations in
this world, to make, as it were, another nature.
LXI. But what shall I say of human reason? Has it not even entered the
heavens? Man alone of all animals has observed the courses of the stars,
their risings and settings. By man the day, the month, the year, is
determined. He foresees the eclipses of the sun and moon, and foretells
them to futurity, marking their greatness, duration, and precise time.
>From the contemplation of these things the mind extracts the knowledge
of the Gods—a knowledge which produces piety, with which is connected
justice, and all the other virtues; from which arises a life of
felicity, inferior to that of the Gods in no single particular, except
in immortality, which is not absolutely necessary
314to happy living. In
explaining these things, I think that I have sufficiently demonstrated
the superiority of man to other animated beings; from whence we should
infer that neither the form and position of his limbs nor that strength
of mind and understanding could possibly be the effect of chance.
LXII. I am now to prove, by way of conclusion, that every thing in this
world of use to us was made designedly for us.
First of all, the universe was made for the Gods and men, and all things
therein were prepared and provided for our service. For the world is the
common habitation or city of the Gods and men; for they are the only
reasonable beings: they alone live by justice and law. As, therefore, it
must be presumed the cities of Athens and Lacedæmon were built for the
Athenians and Lacedæmonians, and as everything there is said to belong
to those people, so everything in the universe may with propriety be
said to belong to the Gods and men, and to them alone.
In the next place, though the revolutions of the sun, moon, and all the
stars are necessary for the cohesion of the universe, yet may they be
considered also as objects designed for the view and contemplation of
man. There is no sight less apt to satiate the eye, none more beautiful,
or more worthy to employ our reason and penetration. By measuring their
courses we find the different seasons, their durations and vicissitudes,
which, if they are known to men alone, we must believe were made only
for their sake.
Does the earth bring forth fruit and grain in such excessive abundance
and variety for men or for brutes? The plentiful and exhilarating fruit
of the vine and the olive-tree are entirely useless to beasts. They know
not the time for sowing, tilling, or for reaping in season and gathering
in the fruits of the earth, or for laying up and preserving their
stores. Man alone has the care and advantage of these things.
LXIII. Thus, as the lute and the pipe were made for those, and those
only, who are capable of playing on them, so it must be allowed that the
produce of the earth was designed for those only who make use of them;
and
315though some beasts may rob us of a small part, it does not follow
that the earth produced it also for them. Men do not store up corn for
mice and ants, but for their wives, their children, and their families.
Beasts, therefore, as I said before, possess it by stealth, but their
masters openly and freely. It is for us, therefore, that nature hath
provided this abundance. Can there be any doubt that this plenty and
variety of fruit, which delight not only the taste, but the smell and
sight, was by nature intended for men only? Beasts are so far from being
partakers of this design, that we see that even they themselves were
made for man; for of what utility would sheep be, unless for their wool,
which, when dressed and woven, serves us for clothing? For they are not
capable of anything, not even of procuring their own food, without the
care and assistance of man. The fidelity of the dog, his affectionate
fawning on his master, his aversion to strangers, his sagacity in
finding game, and his vivacity in pursuit of it, what do these qualities
denote but that he was created for our use? Why need I mention oxen? We
perceive that their backs were not formed for carrying burdens, but
their necks were naturally made for the yoke, and their strong broad
shoulders to draw the plough. In the Golden Age, which poets speak of,
they were so greatly beneficial to the husbandman in tilling the fallow
ground that no violence was ever offered them, and it was even thought a
crime to eat them:
The Iron Age began the fatal trade
Of blood, and hammer’d the destructive blade;
Then men began to make the ox to bleed,
And on the tamed and docile beast to feed
238.
LXIV. It would take a long time to relate the advantages which we
receive from mules and asses, which undoubtedly were designed for our
use. What is the swine good for but to eat? whose life, Chrysippus says,
was given it but as salt
239 to keep it from putrefying; and as it
316is
proper food for man, nature hath made no animal more fruitful. What a
multitude of birds and fishes are taken by the art and contrivance of
man only, and which are so delicious to our taste that one would be
tempted sometimes to believe that this Providence which watches over us
was an Epicurean! Though we think there are some birds—the alites and
oscines
240, as our augurs call them—which were made merely to
foretell events.
The large savage beasts we take by hunting, partly for food, partly to
exercise ourselves in imitation of martial discipline, and to use those
we can tame and instruct, as elephants, or to extract remedies for our
diseases and wounds, as we do from certain roots and herbs, the virtues
of which are known by long use and experience. Represent to yourself the
whole earth and seas as if before your eyes. You will see the vast and
fertile plains, the thick, shady mountains, the immense pasturage for
cattle, and ships sailing over the deep with incredible celerity; nor
are our discoveries only on the face of the earth, but in its secret
recesses there are many useful things, which being made for man, by man
alone are discovered.
LXV. Another, and in my opinion the strongest, proof that the providence
of the Gods takes care of us is divination, which both of you, perhaps,
will attack; you, Cotta, because Carneades took pleasure in inveighing
against the Stoics; and you, Velleius, because there is nothing Epicurus
ridicules so much as the prediction of events. Yet the truth of
divination appears in many places, on many occasions, often in private,
but particularly in public concerns. We receive many intimations from
the foresight and presages of augurs and auspices; from oracles,
prophecies, dreams, and prodigies; and it often happens that by these
means events have proved happy to men, and imminent dangers have been
avoided. This knowledge, therefore—call it either a kind of transport,
or an art, or a natural faculty—is certainly found only in men, and is
a gift from the immortal Gods. If these proofs, when taken
317separately,
should make no impression upon your mind, yet, when collected together,
they must certainly affect you.
Besides, the Gods not only provide for mankind universally, but for
particular men. You may bring this universality to gradually a smaller
number, and again you may reduce that smaller number to individuals.
LXVI. For if the reasons which I have given prove to all of us that the
Gods take care of all men, in every country, in every part of the world
separate from our continent, they take care of those who dwell on the
same land with us, from east to west; and if they regard those who
inhabit this kind of great island, which we call the globe of the earth,
they have the like regard for those who possess the parts of this
island—Europe, Asia, and Africa; and therefore they favor the parts of
these parts, as Rome, Athens, Sparta, and Rhodes; and particular men of
these cities, separate from the whole; as Curius, Fabricius,
Coruncanius, in the war with Pyrrhus; in the first Punic war, Calatinus,
Duillius, Metellus, Lutatius; in the second, Maximus, Marcellus,
Africanus; after these, Paullus, Gracchus, Cato; and in our fathers’
times, Scipio, Lælius. Rome also and Greece have produced many
illustrious men, who we cannot believe were so without the assistance of
the Deity; which is the reason that the poets, Homer in particular,
joined their chief heroes—Ulysses, Agamemnon, Diomedes, Achilles—to
certain Deities, as companions in their adventures and dangers. Besides,
the frequent appearances of the Gods, as I have before mentioned,
demonstrate their regard for cities and particular men. This is also
apparent indeed from the foreknowledge of events, which we receive
either sleeping or waking. We are likewise forewarned of many things by
the entrails of victims, by presages, and many other means, which have
been long observed with such exactness as to produce an art of
divination.
There never, therefore, was a great man without divine inspiration. If a
storm should damage the corn or vineyard of a person, or any accident
should deprive him of some conveniences of life, we should not judge
from thence that the Deity hates or neglects him. The Gods take care
318of
great things, and disregard the small. But to truly great men all things
ever happen prosperously; as has been sufficiently asserted and proved
by us Stoics, as well as by Socrates, the prince of philosophers, in his
discourses on the infinite advantages arising from virtue.
LXVII. This is almost the whole that hath occurred to my mind on the
nature of the Gods, and what I thought proper to advance. Do you, Cotta,
if I may advise, defend the same cause. Remember that in Rome you keep
the first rank; remember that you are Pontifex; and as your school is at
liberty to argue on which side you please
241, do you rather take mine,
and reason on it with that eloquence which you acquired by your
rhetorical exercises, and which the Academy improved; for it is a
pernicious and impious custom to argue against the Gods, whether it be
done seriously, or only in pretence and out of sport.
BOOK III.
I.
When Balbus had ended this discourse, then Cotta, with a smile,
rejoined, You direct me too late which side to defend; for during the
course of your argument I was revolving in my mind what objections to
make to what you were saying, not so much for the sake of opposition, as
of obliging you to explain what I did not perfectly comprehend; and as
every one may use his own judgment, it is scarcely possible for me to
think in every instance exactly what you wish.
You have no idea, O Cotta, said Velleius, how impatient I am to hear
what you have to say. For since our friend Balbus was highly delighted
with your discourse against Epicurus, I ought in my turn to be
solicitous to hear what you can say against the Stoics; and I therefore
will give you my best attention, for I believe you are, as usual, well
prepared for the engagement.
I wish, by Hercules! I were, replies Cotta; for it is more difficult to
dispute with Lucilius than it was with you.
319Why so? says Velleius.
Because, replies Cotta, your Epicurus, in my opinion, does not contend
strongly for the Gods: he only, for the sake of avoiding any
unpopularity or punishment, is afraid to deny their existence; for when
he asserts that the Gods are wholly inactive and regardless of
everything, and that they have limbs like ours, but make no use of them,
he seems to jest with us, and to think it sufficient if he allows that
there are beings of any kind happy and eternal. But with regard to
Balbus, I suppose you observed how many things were said by him, which,
however false they may be, yet have a perfect coherence and connection;
therefore, my design, as I said, in opposing him, is not so much to
confute his principles as to induce him to explain what I do not clearly
understand: for which reason, Balbus, I will give you the choice, either
to answer me every particular as I go on, or permit me to proceed
without interruption. If you want any explanation, replies Balbus, I
would rather you would propose your doubts singly; but if your intention
is rather to confute me than to seek instruction for yourself, it shall
be as you please; I will either answer you immediately on every point,
or stay till you have finished your discourse.
II. Very well, says Cotta; then let us proceed as our conversation shall
direct. But before I enter on the subject, I have a word to say
concerning myself; for I am greatly influenced by your authority, and
your exhortation at the conclusion of your discourse, when you desired
me to remember that I was Cotta and Pontifex; by which I presume you
intimated that I should defend the sacred rites and religion and
ceremonies which we received from our ancestors. Most undoubtedly I
always have, and always shall defend them, nor shall the arguments
either of the learned or unlearned ever remove the opinions which I have
imbibed from them concerning the worship of the immortal Gods. In
matters of religion I submit to the rules of the high-priests, T.
Coruncanius, P. Scipio, and P. Scævola; not to the sentiments of Zeno,
Cleanthes, or Chrysippus; and I pay a greater regard to what C. Lælius,
one of our augurs and wise men, has written concerning religion, in that
noble oration of his, than to the most eminent of the Stoics: and as the
whole religion of the Romans at
320first consisted in sacrifices and
divination by birds, to which have since been added predictions, if the
interpreters
242 of the Sibylline oracle or the aruspices have foretold
any event from portents and prodigies, I have ever thought that there
was no point of all these holy things which deserved to be despised. I
have been even persuaded that Romulus, by instituting divination, and
Numa, by establishing sacrifices, laid the foundation of Rome, which
undoubtedly would never have risen to such a height of grandeur if the
Gods had not been made propitious by this worship. These, Balbus, are my
sentiments both as a priest and as Cotta. But you must bring me to your
opinion by the force of your reason: for I have a right to demand from
you, as a philosopher, a reason for the religion which you would have me
embrace. But I must believe the religion of our ancestors without any
proof.
III. What proof, says Balbus, do you require of me? You have proposed,
says Cotta, four articles. First of all, you undertook to prove that
there “are Gods;” secondly, “of what kind and character they are;”
thirdly, that “the universe is governed by them;” lastly, that “they
provide for the welfare of mankind in particular.” Thus, if I remember
rightly, you divided your discourse. Exactly so, replies Balbus; but let
us see what you require.
Let us examine, says Cotta, every proposition. The first one—that there
are Gods—is never contested but by the most impious of men; nay, though
it can never be rooted out of my mind, yet I believe it on the authority
of our ancestors, and not on the proofs which you have brought. Why do
you expect a proof from me, says Balbus, if you thoroughly believe it?
Because, says Cotta, I come to this discussion as if I had never thought
of the Gods, or heard anything concerning them. Take me as a disciple
wholly ignorant and unbiassed, and prove to me all the points which I
ask.
Begin, then, replies Balbus. I would first know, says Cotta, why you
have been so long in proving the existence of the Gods, which you said
was a point so very evident to all, that there was no need of any proof?
In that, answers
321Balbus, I have followed your example, whom I have
often observed, when pleading in the Forum, to load the judge with all
the arguments which the nature of your cause would permit. This also is
the practice of philosophers, and I have a right to follow it. Besides,
you may as well ask me why I look upon you with two eyes, since I can
see you with one.
IV. You shall judge, then, yourself, says Cotta, if this is a very just
comparison; for, when I plead, I do not dwell upon any point agreed to
be self-evident, because long reasoning only serves to confound the
clearest matters; besides, though I might take this method in pleading,
yet I should not make use of it in such a discourse as this, which
requires the nicest distinction. And with regard to your making use of
one eye only when you look on me, there is no reason for it, since
together they have the same view; and since nature, to which you
attribute wisdom, has been pleased to give us two passages by which we
receive light. But the truth is, that it was because you did not think
that the existence of the Gods was so evident as you could wish that you
therefore brought so many proofs. It was sufficient for me to believe it
on the tradition of our ancestors; and since you disregard authorities,
and appeal to reason, permit my reason to defend them against yours. The
proofs on which you found the existence of the Gods tend only to render
a proposition doubtful that, in my opinion, is not so; I have not only
retained in my memory the whole of these proofs, but even the order in
which you proposed them. The first was, that when we lift up our eyes
towards the heavens, we immediately conceive that there is some divinity
that governs those celestial bodies; on which you quoted this passage—
Look up to the refulgent heaven above,
Which all men call, unanimously, Jove;
intimating that we should invoke that as Jupiter, rather than our
Capitoline Jove243, or that it is evident to the whole world that
those bodies are Gods which Velleius and many others do not place even
in the rank of animated beings.
322Another strong proof, in your opinion, was that the belief of the
existence of the Gods was universal, and that mankind was daily more and
more convinced of it. What! should an affair of such importance be left
to the decision of fools, who, by your sect especially, are called
madmen?
V. But the Gods have appeared to us, as to Posthumius at the Lake
Regillus, and to Vatienus in the Salarian Way: something you mentioned,
too, I know not what, of a battle of the Locrians at Sagra. Do you
believe that the Tyndaridæ, as you called them; that is, men sprung from
men, and who were buried in Lacedæmon, as we learn from Homer, who lived
in the next age—do you believe, I say, that they appeared to Vatienus
on the road mounted on white horses, without any servant to attend them,
to tell the victory of the Romans to a country fellow rather than to M.
Cato, who was at that time the chief person of the senate? Do you take
that print of a horse’s hoof which is now to be seen on a stone at
Regillus to be made by Castor’s horse? Should you not believe, what is
probable, that the souls of eminent men, such as the Tyndaridæ, are
divine and immortal, rather than that those bodies which had been
reduced to ashes should mount on horses, and fight in an army? If you
say that was possible, you ought to show how it is so, and not amuse us
with fabulous old women’s stories.
Do you take these for fabulous stories? says Balbus. Is not the temple,
built by Posthumius in honor of Castor and Pollux, to be seen in the
Forum? Is not the decree of the senate concerning Vatienus still
subsisting? As to the affair of Sagra, it is a common proverb among the
Greeks; when they would affirm anything strongly, they say “It is as
certain as what passed at Sagra.” Ought not such authorities to move
you? You oppose me, replies Cotta, with stories, but I ask reasons of
you244. *В *В *
VI. We are now to speak of predictions. No one can avoid what is to
come, and, indeed, it is commonly useless to know it; for it is a
miserable case to be afflicted to no purpose, and not to have even the
last, the common comfort, 323hope, which, according to your principles,
none can have; for you say that fate governs all things, and call that
fate which has been true from all eternity. What advantage, then, is the
knowledge of futurity to us, or how does it assist us to guard against
impending evils, since it will come inevitably?
But whence comes that divination? To whom is owing that knowledge from
the entrails of beasts? Who first made observations from the voice of
the crow? Who invented the Lots?245 Not that I give no credit to these
things, or that I despise Attius Navius’s staff, which you mentioned;
but I ought to be informed how these things are understood by
philosophers, especially as the diviners are often wrong in their
conjectures. But physicians, you say, are likewise often mistaken. What
comparison can there be between divination, of the origin of which we
are ignorant, and physic, which proceeds on principles intelligible to
every one? You believe that the Decii,246 in devoting themselves to
death, appeased the Gods. How great, then, was the iniquity of the Gods
that they could not be appeased but at the price of such noble blood!
That was the stratagem of generals such as the Greeks call ПѓП„ПЃО±П„бЅµОіО·ОјО±,
and it was a stratagem worthy such illustrious leaders, who consulted
the public good even at the expense of their lives: they conceived
rightly, what indeed happened, that if the general rode furiously upon
the enemy, the whole army would follow his example. As to the voice of
the Fauns, I never heard it. If you assure me that you have, I shall
believe you, though I really know not what a Faun is.
VII. I do not, then, O Balbus, from anything that you have said,
perceive as yet that it is proved that there are Gods. I believe it,
indeed, but not from any arguments of the Stoics. Cleanthes, you have
said, attributes the idea that men have of the Gods to four causes. In
the first place (as I have already sufficiently mentioned), to a
foreknowledge 324of future events; secondly, to tempests, and other shocks
of nature; thirdly, to the utility and plenty of things we enjoy;
fourthly, to the invariable order of the stars and the heavens. The
arguments drawn from foreknowledge I have already answered. With regard
to tempests in the air, the sea, and the earth, I own that many people
are affrighted by them, and imagine that the immortal Gods are the
authors of them.
But the question is, not whether there are people who believe that there
are Gods, but whether there are Gods or not. As to the two other causes
of Cleanthes, one of which is derived from the great abundance of
desirable things which we enjoy, the other from the invariable order of
the seasons and the heavens, I shall treat on them when I answer your
discourse concerning the providence of the Gods—a point, Balbus, upon
which you have spoken at great length. I shall likewise defer till then
examining the argument which you attribute to Chrysippus, that “if there
is in nature anything which surpasses the power of man to produce, there
must consequently be some being better than man.” I shall also postpone,
till we come to that part of my argument, your comparison of the world
to a fine house, your observations on the proportion and harmony of the
universe, and those smart, short reasons of Zeno which you quote; and I
shall examine at the same time your reasons drawn from natural
philosophy, concerning that fiery force and that vital heat which you
regard as the principle of all things; and I will investigate, in its
proper place, all that you advanced the other day on the existence of
the Gods, and on the sense and understanding which you attributed to the
sun, the moon, and all the stars; and I shall ask you this question over
and over again, By what proofs are you convinced yourself there are
Gods?
VIII. I thought, says Balbus, that I had brought ample proofs to
establish this point. But such is your manner of opposing, that, when
you seem on the point of interrogating me, and when I am preparing to
answer, you suddenly divert the discourse, and give me no opportunity to
reply to you; and thus those most important points concerning divination
and fate are neglected which we Stoics 325have thoroughly examined, but
which your school has only slightly touched upon. But they are not
thought essential to the question in hand; therefore, if you think
proper, do not confuse them together, that we in this discussion may
come to a clear explanation of the subject of our present inquiry.
Very well, says Cotta. Since, then, you have divided the whole question
into four parts, and I have said all that I had to say on the first, I
will take the second into consideration; in which, when you attempted to
show what the character of the Gods was, you seemed to me rather to
prove that there are none; for you said that it was the greatest
difficulty to draw our minds from the prepossessions of the eyes; but
that as nothing is more excellent than the Deity, you did not doubt that
the world was God, because there is nothing better in nature than the
world, and so we may reasonably think it animated, or, rather, perceive
it in our minds as clearly as if it were obvious to our eyes.
Now, in what sense do you say there is nothing better than the world? If
you mean that there is nothing more beautiful, I agree with you; that
there is nothing more adapted to our wants, I likewise agree with you:
but if you mean that nothing is wiser than the world, I am by no means
of your opinion. Not that I find it difficult to conceive anything in my
mind independent of my eyes; on the contrary, the more I separate my
mind from my eyes, the less I am able to comprehend your opinion.
IX. Nothing is better than the world, you say. Nor is there, indeed,
anything on earth better than the city of Rome; do you think, therefore,
that our city has a mind; that it thinks and reasons; or that this most
beautiful city, being void of sense, is not preferable to an ant,
because an ant has sense, understanding, reason, and memory? You should
consider, Balbus, what ought to be allowed you, and not advance things
because they please you.
For that old, concise, and, as it seemed to you, acute syllogism of Zeno
has been all which you have so much enlarged upon in handling this
topic: “That which reasons is superior to that which does not; nothing
is superior to the world; therefore the world reasons.” If you would
326prove also that the world can very well read a book, follow the example
of Zeno, and say, “That which can read is better than that which cannot;
nothing is better than the world; the world therefore can read.” After
the same manner you may prove the world to be an orator, a
mathematician, a musician—that it possesses all sciences, and, in
short, is a philosopher. You have often said that God made all things,
and that no cause can produce an effect unlike itself. From hence it
will follow, not only that the world is animated, and is wise, but also
plays upon the fiddle and the flute, because it produces men who play on
those instruments. Zeno, therefore, the chief of your sect, advances no
argument sufficient to induce us to think that the world reasons, or,
indeed, that it is animated at all, and consequently none to think it a
Deity; though it may be said that there is nothing superior to it, as
there is nothing more beautiful, nothing more useful to us, nothing more
adorned, and nothing more regular in its motions. But if the world,
considered as one great whole, is not God, you should not surely deify,
as you have done, that infinite multitude of stars which only form a
part of it, and which so delight you with the regularity of their
eternal courses; not but that there is something truly wonderful and
incredible in their regularity; but this regularity of motion, Balbus,
may as well be ascribed to a natural as to a divine cause.
X. What can be more regular than the flux and reflux of the Euripus at
Chalcis, the Sicilian sea, and the violence of the ocean in those
parts247
where the rapid tide
Does Europe from the Libyan coast divide?
The same appears on the Spanish and British coasts. Must we conclude
that some Deity appoints and directs these ebbings and flowings to
certain fixed times? Consider, I pray, if everything which is regular in
its motion is deemed divine, whether it will not follow that tertian and
quartan agues must likewise be so, as their returns have the greatest
regularity. These effects are to be explained by reason; but, because
you are unable to assign any, you have recourse to a Deity as your last
refuge.
327The arguments of Chrysippus appeared to you of great weight; a
man undoubtedly of great quickness and subtlety (I call those quick who
have a sprightly turn of thought, and those subtle whose minds are
seasoned by use as their hands are by labor): “If,” says he, “there is
anything which is beyond the power of man to produce, the being who
produces it is better than man. Man is unable to make what is in the
world; the being, therefore, that could do it is superior to man. What
being is there but a God superior to man? Therefore there is a God.”
These arguments are founded on the same erroneous principles as Zeno’s,
for he does not define what is meant by being better or more excellent,
or distinguish between an intelligent cause and a natural cause.
Chrysippus adds, “If there are no Gods, there is nothing better than
man; but we cannot, without the highest arrogance, have this idea of
ourselves.” Let us grant that it is arrogance in man to think himself
better than the world; but to comprehend that he has understanding and
reason, and that in Orion and Canicula there is neither, is no
arrogance, but an indication of good sense. “Since we suppose,”
continues he, “when we see a beautiful house, that it was built for the
master, and not for mice, we should likewise judge that the world is the
mansion of the Gods.” Yes, if I believed that the Gods built the world;
but not if, as I believe, and intend to prove, it is the work of nature.
XI. Socrates, in Xenophon, asks, “Whence had man his understanding, if
there was none in the world?” And I ask, Whence had we speech, harmony,
singing; unless we think it is the sun conversing with the moon when she
approaches near it, or that the world forms an harmonious concert, as
Pythagoras imagines? This, Balbus, is the effect of nature; not of that
nature which proceeds artificially, as Zeno says, and the character of
which I shall presently examine into, but a nature which, by its own
proper motions and mutations, modifies everything.
For I readily agree to what you said about the harmony and general
agreement of nature, which you pronounced to be firmly bound and united
together, as it were, by ties of blood; but I do not approve of what you
added, that “it could not possibly be so, unless it were so united by
328one divine spirit.” On the contrary, the whole subsists by the power of
nature, independently of the Gods, and there is a kind of sympathy (as
the Greeks call it) which joins together all the parts of the universe;
and the greater that is in its own power, the less is it necessary to
have recourse to a divine intelligence.
XII. But how will you get rid of the objections which Carneades made?
“If,” says he, “there is no body immortal, there is none eternal; but
there is no body immortal, nor even indivisible, or that cannot be
separated and disunited; and as every animal is in its nature passive,
so there is not one which is not subject to the impressions of
extraneous bodies; none, that is to say, which can avoid the necessity
of enduring and suffering: and if every animal is mortal, there is none
immortal; so, likewise, if every animal may be cut up and divided, there
is none indivisible, none eternal, but all are liable to be affected by,
and compelled to submit to, external power. Every animal, therefore, is
necessarily mortal, dissoluble, and divisible.”
For as there is no wax, no silver, no brass which cannot be converted
into something else, whatever is composed of wax, or silver, or brass
may cease to be what it is. By the same reason, if all the elements are
mutable, every body is mutable.
Now, according to your doctrine, all the elements are mutable; all
bodies, therefore, are mutable. But if there were any body immortal,
then all bodies would not be mutable. Every body, then, is mortal; for
every body is either water, air, fire, or earth, or composed of the four
elements together, or of some of them. Now, there is not one of all
these elements that does not perish; for earthly bodies are fragile:
water is so soft that the least shock will separate its parts, and fire
and air yield to the least impulse, and are subject to dissolution;
besides, any of these elements perish when converted into another
nature, as when water is formed from earth, the air from water, and the
sky from air, and when they change in the same manner back again.
Therefore, if there is nothing but what is perishable in the composition
of all animals, there is no animal eternal.
XIII. But, not to insist on these arguments, there is no 329animal to be
found that had not a beginning, and will not have an end; for every
animal being sensitive, they are consequently all sensible of cold and
heat, sweet and bitter; nor can they have pleasing sensations without
being subject to the contrary. As, therefore, they receive pleasure,
they likewise receive pain; and whatever being is subject to pain must
necessarily be subject to death. It must be allowed, therefore, that
every animal is mortal.
Besides, a being that is not sensible of pleasure or pain cannot have
the essence of an animal; if, then, on the one hand, every animal must
be sensible of pleasure and pain, and if, on the other, every being that
has these sensations cannot be immortal, we may conclude that as there
is no animal insensible, there is none immortal. Besides, there is no
animal without inclination and aversion—an inclination to that which is
agreeable to nature, and an aversion to the contrary: there are in the
case of every animal some things which they covet, and others they
reject. What they reject are repugnant to their nature, and consequently
would destroy them. Every animal, therefore, is inevitably subject to be
destroyed. There are innumerable arguments to prove that whatever is
sensitive is perishable; for cold, heat, pleasure, pain, and all that
affects the sense, when they become excessive, cause destruction. Since,
then, there is no animal that is not sensitive, there is none immortal.
XIV. The substance of an animal is either simple or compound; simple, if
it is composed only of earth, of fire, of air, or of water (and of such
a sort of being we can form no idea); compound, if it is formed of
different elements, which have each their proper situation, and have a
natural tendency to it—this element tending towards the highest parts,
that towards the lowest, and another towards the middle. This
conjunction may for some time subsist, but not forever; for every
element must return to its first situation. No animal, therefore, is
eternal.
But your school, Balbus, allows fire only to be the sole active
principle; an opinion which I believe you derive from Heraclitus, whom
some men understand in one sense, some in another: but since he seems
unwilling to be understood, we will pass him by. You Stoics, then, say
that 330fire is the universal principle of all things; that all living
bodies cease to live on the extinction of that heat; and that throughout
all nature whatever is sensible of that heat lives and flourishes. Now,
I cannot conceive that bodies should perish for want of heat, rather
than for want of moisture or air, especially as they even die through
excess of heat; so that the life of animals does not depend more on fire
than on the other elements.
However, air and water have this quality in common with fire and heat.
But let us see to what this tends. If I am not mistaken, you believe
that in all nature there is nothing but fire, which is self-animated.
Why fire rather than air, of which the life of animals consists, and
which is called from thence anima,248 the soul? But how is it that
you take it for granted that life is nothing but fire? It seems more
probable that it is a compound of fire and air. But if fire is
self-animated, unmixed with any other element, it must be sensitive,
because it renders our bodies sensitive; and the same objection which I
just now made will arise, that whatever is sensitive must necessarily be
susceptible of pleasure and pain, and whatever is sensible of pain is
likewise subject to the approach of death; therefore you cannot prove
fire to be eternal.
You Stoics hold that all fire has need of nourishment, without which it
cannot possibly subsist; that the sun, moon, and all the stars are fed
either with fresh or salt waters; and the reason that Cleanthes gives
why the sun is retrograde, and does not go beyond the tropics in the
summer or winter, is that he may not be too far from his sustenance.
This I shall fully examine hereafter; but at present we may conclude
that whatever may cease to be cannot of its own nature be eternal; that
if fire wants sustenance, it will cease to be, and that, therefore, fire
is not of its own nature eternal.
XV. After all, what kind of a Deity must that be who 331is not graced with
one single virtue, if we should succeed in forming this idea of such a
one? Must we not attribute prudence to a Deity? a virtue which consists
in the knowledge of things good, bad, and indifferent. Yet what need has
a being for the discernment of good and ill who neither has nor can have
any ill? Of what use is reason to him? of what use is understanding? We
men, indeed, find them useful to aid us in finding out things which are
obscure by those which are clear to us; but nothing can be obscure to a
Deity. As to justice, which gives to every one his own, it is not the
concern of the Gods; since that virtue, according to your doctrine,
received its birth from men and from civil society. Temperance consists
in abstinence from corporeal pleasures, and if such abstinence hath a
place in heaven, so also must the pleasures abstained from. Lastly, if
fortitude is ascribed to the Deity, how does it appear? In afflictions,
in labor, in danger? None of these things can affect a God. How, then,
can we conceive this to be a Deity that makes no use of reason, and is
not endowed with any virtue?
However, when I consider what is advanced by the Stoics, my contempt for
the ignorant multitude vanishes. For these are their divinities. The
Syrians worshipped a fish. The Egyptians consecrated beasts of almost
every kind. The Greeks deified many men; as Alabandus249 at Alabandæ,
Tenes at Tenedos; and all Greece pay divine honors to Leucothea (who was
before called Ino), to her son Palæmon, to Hercules, to Æsculapius, and
to the Tyndaridæ; our own people to Romulus, and to many others, who, as
citizens newly admitted into the ancient body, they imagine have been
received into heaven.
These are the Gods of the illiterate.
XVI. What are the notions of you philosophers? In what respect are they
superior to these ideas? I shall pass them over; for they are certainly
very admirable. Let the world, then, be a Deity, for that, I conceive,
is what you mean by
The refulgent heaven above,
Which all men call, unanimously, Jove.
332But why are we to add many more Gods? What a multitude of them there
is! At least, it seems so to me; for every constellation, according to
you, is a Deity: to some you give the name of beasts, as the goat, the
scorpion, the bull, the lion; to others the names of inanimate things,
as the ship, the altar, the crown.
But supposing these were to be allowed, how can the rest be granted, or
even so much as understood? When we call corn Ceres, and wine Bacchus,
we make use of the common manner of speaking; but do you think any one
so mad as to believe that his food is a Deity? With regard to those who,
you say, from having been men became Gods, I should be very willing to
learn of you, either how it was possible formerly, or, if it had ever
been, why is it not so now? I do not conceive, as things are at present,
how Hercules,
Burn’d with fiery torches on Mount Œta,
as Accius says, should rise, with the flames,
To the eternal mansions of his father.
Besides, Homer also says that Ulysses
250 met him in the shades below,
among the other dead.
But yet I should be glad to know which Hercules we should chiefly
worship; for they who have searched into those histories, which are but
little known, tell us of several. The most ancient is he who fought with
Apollo about the Tripos of Delphi, and is son of Jupiter and Lisyto; and
of the most ancient Jupiters too, for we find many Jupiters also in the
Grecian chronicles. The second is the Egyptian Hercules, and is believed
to be the son of Nilus, and to be the author of the Phrygian characters.
The third, to whom they offered sacrifices, is one of the
333Idæi
Dactyli.
251 The fourth is the son of Jupiter and Asteria, the sister
of Latona, chiefly honored by the Tyrians, who pretend that
Carthago
252 is his daughter. The fifth, called Belus, is worshipped in
India. The sixth is the son of Alcmena by Jupiter; but by the third
Jupiter, for there are many Jupiters, as you shall soon see.
XVII. Since this examination has led me so far, I will convince you that
in matters of religion I have learned more from the pontifical rites,
the customs of our ancestors, and the vessels of Numa,
253 which Lælius
mentions in his little Golden Oration, than from all the learning of the
Stoics; for tell me, if I were a disciple of your school, what answer
could I make to these questions? If there are Gods, are nymphs also
Goddesses? If they are Goddesses, are Pans and Satyrs in the same rank?
But they are not; consequently, nymphs are not Goddesses. Yet they have
temples publicly dedicated to them. What do you conclude from thence?
Others who have temples are not therefore Gods. But let us go on. You
call Jupiter and Neptune Gods; their brother Pluto, then, is one; and if
so, those rivers also are Deities which they say flow in the infernal
regions—Acheron, Cocytus, Pyriphlegethon; Charon also, and Cerberus,
are Gods; but that cannot be allowed; nor can Pluto be placed among the
Deities. What, then, will you say of his brothers?
Thus reasons Carneades; not with any design to destroy the existence of
the Gods (for what would less become a philosopher?), but to convince us
that on that matter the Stoics have said nothing plausible. If, then,
Jupiter and Neptune are Gods, adds he, can that divinity be denied to
their father Saturn, who is principally worshipped throughout the West?
If Saturn is a God, then must his father, CЕ“lus, be one too, and so must
the parents of CЕ“lus, which are the Sky and Day, as also their brothers
and sisters, which by ancient genealogists are
334thus named: Love,
Deceit, Fear, Labor, Envy, Fate, Old Age, Death, Darkness, Misery,
Lamentation, Favor, Fraud, Obstinacy, the Destinies, the Hesperides, and
Dreams; all which are the offspring of Erebus and Night. These monstrous
Deities, therefore, must be received, or else those from whom they
sprung must be disallowed.
XVIII. If you say that Apollo, Vulcan, Mercury, and the rest of that
sort are Gods, can you doubt the divinity of Hercules and Г†sculapius,
Bacchus, Castor and Pollux? These are worshipped as much as those, and
even more in some places. Therefore they must be numbered among the
Gods, though on the mother’s side they are only of mortal race.
Aristæus, who is said to have been the son of Apollo, and to have found
out the art of making oil from the olive; Theseus, the son of Neptune;
and the rest whose fathers were Deities, shall they not be placed in the
number of the Gods? But what think you of those whose mothers were
Goddesses? They surely have a better title to divinity; for, in the
civil law, as he is a freeman who is born of a freewoman, so, in the law
of nature, he whose mother is a Goddess must be a God. The isle
Astypalæa religiously honor Achilles; and if he is a Deity, Orpheus and
Rhesus are so, who were born of one of the Muses; unless, perhaps, there
may be a privilege belonging to sea marriages which land marriages have
not. Orpheus and Rhesus are nowhere worshipped; and if they are
therefore not Gods, because they are nowhere worshipped as such, how can
the others be Deities? You, Balbus, seemed to agree with me that the
honors which they received were not from their being regarded as
immortals, but as men richly endued with virtue.
But if you think Latona a Goddess, how can you avoid admitting Hecate to
be one also, who was the daughter of Asteria, Latona’s sister? Certainly
she is one, if we may judge by the altars erected to her in Greece. And
if Hecate is a Goddess, how can you refuse that rank to the Eumenides?
for they also have a temple at Athens, and, if I understand right, the
Romans have consecrated a grove to them. The Furies, too, whom we look
upon as the inspectors into and scourges of impiety, I suppose, must
have their divinity too. As you hold that there is some divinity
335presides over every human affair, there is one who presides over the
travail of matrons, whose name,
Natio, is derived
a nascentibus,
from nativities, and to whom we used to sacrifice in our processions in
the fields of Ardæa; but if she is a Deity, we must likewise acknowledge
all those you mentioned, Honor, Faith, Intellect, Concord; by the same
rule also, Hope, Juno, Moneta,
254 and every idle phantom, every child
of our imagination, are Deities. But as this consequence is quite
inadmissible, do not you either defend the cause from which it flows.
XIX. What say you to this? If these are Deities, which we worship and
regard as such, why are not Serapis and Isis
255 placed in the same
rank? And if they are admitted, what reason have we to reject the Gods
of the barbarians? Thus we should deify oxen, horses, the ibis, hawks,
asps, crocodiles, fishes, dogs, wolves, cats, and many other beasts. If
we go back to the source of this superstition, we must equally condemn
all the Deities from which they proceed. Shall Ino, whom the Greeks call
Leucothea, and we Matuta, be reputed a Goddess, because she was the
daughter of Cadmus, and shall that title be refused to Circe and
Pasiphae,
256 who had the sun for their father, and Perseis, daughter
of the Ocean, for their mother? It is true, Circe has divine honors paid
her by our colony of Circæum; therefore you call her a Goddess; but what
will you say of Medea, the granddaughter of the Sun and the Ocean, and
daughter of Г†etes and Idyia? What will you say of her brother Absyrtus,
whom Pacuvius calls Г†gialeus, though the other name is more frequent in
the writings of the ancients? If you did not deify one as well as the
other, what will become of Ino? for all these Deities have the same
origin.
Shall Amphiaraus and Tryphonius be called Gods? Our publicans, when some
lands in BЕ“otia were exempted from the tax, as belonging to the immortal
Gods, denied that
336any were immortal who had been men. But if you deify
these, Erechtheus surely is a God, whose temple and priest we have seen
at Athens. And can you, then, refuse to acknowledge also Codrus, and
many others who shed their blood for the preservation of their country?
And if it is not allowable to consider all these men as Gods, then,
certainly, probabilities are not in favor of our acknowledging the
Divinity of those previously mentioned beings from whom these have
proceeded.
It is easy to observe, likewise, that if in many countries people have
paid divine honors to the memory of those who have signalized their
courage, it was done in order to animate others to practise virtue, and
to expose themselves the more willingly to dangers in their country’s
cause. From this motive the Athenians have deified Erechtheus and his
daughters, and have erected also a temple, called Leocorion, to the
daughters of Leus.
257 Alabandus is more honored in the city which he
founded than any of the more illustrious Deities; from thence
Stratonicus had a pleasant turn—as he had many—when he was troubled
with an impertinent fellow who insisted that Alabandus was a God, but
that Hercules was not; “Very well,” says he, “then let the anger of
Alabandus fall upon me, and that of Hercules upon you.”
XX. Do you not consider, Balbus, to what lengths your arguments for the
divinity of the heaven and the stars will carry you? You deify the sun
and the moon, which the Greeks take to be Apollo and Diana. If the moon
is a Deity, the morning-star, the other planets, and all the fixed stars
are also Deities; and why shall not the rainbow be placed in that
number? for it is so wonderfully beautiful that it is justly said to be
the daughter of Thaumas.
258 But if you deify the rainbow, what regard
will you pay to the clouds? for the colors which appear in the bow are
only formed of the clouds, one of which is said to have brought forth
the Centaurs; and if you deify the clouds, you cannot pay less regard to
the seasons, which the Roman people have really consecrated. Tempests,
showers,
337storms, and whirlwinds must then be Deities. It is certain, at
least, that our captains used to sacrifice a victim to the waves before
they embarked on any voyage.
As you deify the earth under the name of Ceres,
259 because, as you
said, she bears fruits (
a gerendo), and the ocean under that of
Neptune, rivers and fountains have the same right. Thus we see that
Maso, the conqueror of Corsica, dedicated a temple to a fountain, and
the names of the Tiber, Spino, Almo, Nodinus, and other neighboring
rivers are in the prayers
260 of the augurs. Therefore, either the
number of such Deities will be infinite, or we must admit none of them,
and wholly disapprove of such an endless series of superstition.
XXI. None of all these assertions, then, are to be admitted. I must
proceed now, Balbus, to answer those who say that, with regard to those
deified mortals, so religiously and devoutly reverenced, the public
opinion should have the force of reality. To begin, then: they who are
called theologists say that there are three Jupiters; the first and
second of whom were born in Arcadia; one of whom was the son of Г†ther,
and father of Proserpine and Bacchus; the other the son of CЕ“lus, and
father of Minerva, who is called the Goddess and inventress of war; the
third one born of Saturn in the isle of Crete,
261 where his sepulchre
is shown. The sons of Jupiter (
О”О№бЅ№ПѓОєОїП…ПЃОїО№) also, among the Greeks, have
many names; first, the three who at Athens have the title of
Anactes,
262 Tritopatreus, Eubuleus, and Dionysus, sons of the most
ancient king Jupiter and Proserpine; the next are Castor and Pollux,
sons of the third Jupiter and Leda; and, lastly, three others, by some
called Alco,
263 Melampus, and Tmolus, sons of Atreus, the son of
Pelops.
338As to the Muses, there were at first four—Thelxiope, Aœde, Arche, and
Melete—daughters of the second Jupiter; afterward there were nine,
daughters of the third Jupiter and Mnemosyne; there were also nine
others, having the same appellations, born of Pierus and Antiopa, by the
poets usually called Pierides and Pieriæ. Though
Sol (the sun) is so
called, you say, because he is
solus (single); yet how many suns do
theologists mention? There is one, the son of Jupiter and grandson of
Г†ther; another, the son of Hyperion; a third, who, the Egyptians say,
was of the city Heliopolis, sprung from Vulcan, the son of Nilus; a
fourth is said to have been born at Rhodes of Acantho, in the times of
the heroes, and was the grandfather of Jalysus, Camirus, and Lindus; a
fifth, of whom, it is pretended, Aretes and Circe were born at Colchis.
XXII. There are likewise several Vulcans. The first (who had of Minerva
that Apollo whom the ancient historians call the tutelary God of Athens)
was the son of CЕ“lus; the second, whom the Egyptians call Opas,
264 and
whom they looked upon as the protector of Egypt, is the son of Nilus;
the third, who is said to have been the master of the forges at Lemnos,
was the son of the third Jupiter and of Juno; the fourth, who possessed
the islands near Sicily called Vulcaniæ,
265 was the son of Menalius.
One Mercury had CЕ“lus for his father and Dies for his mother; another,
who is said to dwell in a cavern, and is the same as Trophonius, is the
son of Valens and Phoronis. A third, of whom, and of Penelope, Pan was
the offspring, is the son of the third Jupiter and Maia. A fourth, whom
the Egyptians think it a crime to name, is the son of Nilus. A fifth,
whom we call, in their language, Thoth, as with them the first month of
the year is called, is he whom the people of Pheneum
266 worship, and
who is said to have killed Argus, to have fled for it into Egypt, and to
have given laws and learning to the Egyptians. The first of the
Г†sculapii, the God of Arcadia, who is said to have invented the probe
and to have been the first person who taught men to use bandages for
wounds, is the son of
339Apollo. The second, who was killed with thunder,
and is said to be buried in Cynosura,
267 is the brother of the second
Mercury. The third, who is said to have found out the art of purging the
stomach, and of drawing teeth, is the son of Arsippus and Arsinoe; and
in Arcadia there is shown his tomb, and the wood which is consecrated to
him, near the river Lusium.
XXIII. I have already spoken of the most ancient of the Apollos, who is
the son of Vulcan, and tutelar God of Athens. There is another, son of
Corybas, and native of Crete, for which island he is said to have
contended with Jupiter himself. A third, who came from the regions of
the Hyperborei
268 to Delphi, is the son of the third Jupiter and of
Latona. A fourth was of Arcadia, whom the Arcadians called Nomio,
269
because they regarded him as their legislator. There are likewise many
Dianas. The first, who is thought to be the mother of the winged Cupid,
is the daughter of Jupiter and Proserpine. The second, who is more
known, is daughter of the third Jupiter and of Latona. The third, whom
the Greeks often call by her father’s name, is the daughter of Upis
270
and Glauce. There are many also of the Dionysi. The first was the son of
Jupiter and Proserpine. The second, who is said to have killed Nysa, was
the son of Nilus. The third, who reigned in Asia, and for whom the
Sabazia
271 were instituted, was the son of Caprius. The fourth, for
whom they celebrate the Orphic festivals, sprung from Jupiter and Luna.
The fifth, who is supposed to have instituted the Trieterides, was the
son of Nysus and Thyone.
The first Venus, who has a temple at Elis, was the daughter of CЕ“lus and
Dies. The second arose out of the froth of the sea, and became, by
Mercury, the mother of the second Cupid. The third, the daughter of
Jupiter and Diana, was married to Vulcan, but is said to have had
Anteros by Mars. The fourth was a Syrian, born of Tyro, who is called
Astarte, and is said to have been married to
340Adonis. I have already
mentioned one Minerva, mother of Apollo. Another, who is worshipped at
Sais, a city in Egypt, sprung from Nilus. The third, whom I have also
mentioned, was daughter of Jupiter. The fourth, sprung from Jupiter and
Coryphe, the daughter of the Ocean; the Arcadians call her Coria, and
make her the inventress of chariots. A fifth, whom they paint with wings
at her heels, was daughter of Pallas, and is said to have killed her
father for endeavoring to violate her chastity. The first Cupid is said
to be the son of Mercury and the first Diana; the second, of Mercury and
the second Venus; the third, who is the same as Anteros, of Mars and the
third Venus.
All these opinions arise from old stories that were spread in Greece;
the belief in which, Balbus, you well know, ought to be stopped, lest
religion should suffer. But you Stoics, so far from refuting them, even
give them authority by the mysterious sense which you pretend to find in
them. Can you, then, think, after this plain refutation, that there is
need to employ more subtle reasonings? But to return from this
digression.
XXIV. We see that the mind, faith, hope, virtue, honor, victory, health,
concord, and things of such kind, are purely natural, and have nothing
of divinity in them; for either they are inherent in us, as the mind,
faith, hope, virtue, and concord are; or else they are to be desired, as
honor, health, and victory. I know indeed that they are useful to us,
and see that statues have been religiously erected for them; but as to
their divinity, I shall begin to believe it when you have proved it for
certain. Of this kind I may particularly mention Fortune, which is
allowed to be ever inseparable from inconstancy and temerity, which are
certainly qualities unworthy of a divine being.
But what delight do you take in the explication of fables, and in the
etymology of names?—that Cœlus was castrated by his son, and that
Saturn was bound in chains by his son! By your defence of these and such
like fictions you would make the authors of them appear not only not to
be madmen, but to have been even very wise. But the pains which you take
with your etymologies deserve our pity. That Saturn is so called because
se saturat annis, he is full of years; Mavors, Mars, because
magna
341vortit, he brings about mighty changes; Minerva, because
minuit, she
diminishes, or because
minatur, she threatens; Venus, because
venit
ad omnia, she comes to all; Ceres,
a gerendo, from bearing. How
dangerous is this method! for there are many names would puzzle you.
>From what would you derive Vejupiter and Vulcan? Though, indeed, if you
can derive Neptune
a nando, from swimming, in which you seem to me to
flounder about yourself more than Neptune, you may easily find the
origin of all names, since it is founded only upon the conformity of
some one letter. Zeno first, and after him Cleanthes and Chrysippus, are
put to the unnecessary trouble of explaining mere fables, and giving
reasons for the several appellations of every Deity; which is really
owning that those whom we call Gods are not the representations of
deities, but natural things, and that to judge otherwise is an error.
XXV. Yet this error has so much prevailed that even pernicious things
have not only the title of divinity ascribed to them, but have also
sacrifices offered to them; for Fever has a temple on the Palatine hill,
and Orbona another near that of the Lares, and we see on the Esquiline
hill an altar consecrated to Ill-fortune. Let all such errors be
banished from philosophy, if we would advance, in our dispute concerning
the immortal Gods, nothing unworthy of immortal beings. I know myself
what I ought to believe; which is far different from what you have said.
You take Neptune for an intelligence pervading the sea. You have the
same opinion of Ceres with regard to the earth. I cannot, I own, find
out, or in the least conjecture, what that intelligence of the sea or
the earth is. To learn, therefore, the existence of the Gods, and of
what description and character they are, I must apply elsewhere, not to
the Stoics.
Let us proceed to the two other parts of our dispute: first, “whether
there is a divine providence which governs the world;” and lastly,
“whether that providence particularly regards mankind;” for these are
the remaining propositions of your discourse; and I think that, if you
approve of it, we should examine these more accurately. With all my
heart, says Velleius, for I readily agree to what you have hitherto
said, and expect still greater things from you.
I am unwilling to interrupt you, says Balbus to Cotta,
342but we shall
take another opportunity, and I shall effectually convince you. But
272
*В *В *
XXVI.
Shall I adore, and bend the suppliant knee,
Who scorn their power and doubt their deity?
Does not Niobe here seem to reason, and by that reasoning to bring all
her misfortunes upon herself? But what a subtle expression is the
following!
On strength of will alone depends success;
a maxim capable of leading us into all that is bad.
Though I’m confined, his malice yet is vain,
His tortured heart shall answer pain for pain;
His ruin soothe my soul with soft content,
Lighten my chains, and welcome banishment!
This, now, is reason; that reason which you say the divine goodness has
denied to the brute creation, kindly to bestow it on men alone. How
great, how immense the favor! Observe the same Medea flying from her
father and her country:
The guilty wretch from her pursuer flies.
By her own hands the young Absyrtus slain,
His mangled limbs she scatters o’er the plain,
That the fond sire might sink beneath his woe,
And she to parricide her safety owe.
Reflection, as well as wickedness, must have been necessary to the
preparation of such a fact; and did he too, who prepared that fatal
repast for his brother, do it without reflection?
Revenge as great as Atreus’ injury
Shall sink his soul and crown his misery.
XXVII. Did not Thyestes himself, not content with having defiled his
brother’s bed (of which Atreus with great justice thus complains,
When faithless comforts, in the lewd embrace,
With vile adultery stain a royal race,
The blood thus mix’d in fouler currents flows,
Taints the rich soil, and breeds unnumber’d woes)—
343did he not, I say, by that adultery, aim at the possession of the
crown? Atreus thus continues:
A lamb, fair gift of heaven, with golden fleece,
Promised in vain to fix my crown in peace;
But base Thyestes, eager for the prey,
Crept to my bed, and stole the gem away.
Do you not perceive that Thyestes must have had a share of reason
proportionable to the greatness of his crimes—such crimes as are not
only represented to us on the stage, but such as we see committed, nay,
often exceeded, in the common course of life? The private houses of
individual citizens, the public courts, the senate, the camp, our
allies, our provinces, all agree that reason is the author of all the
ill, as well as of all the good, which is done; that it makes few act
well, and that but seldom, but many act ill, and that frequently; and
that, in short, the Gods would have shown greater benevolence in denying
us any reason at all than in sending us that which is accompanied with
so much mischief; for as wine is seldom wholesome, but often hurtful in
diseases, we think it more prudent to deny it to the patient than to run
the risk of so uncertain a remedy; so I do not know whether it would not
be better for mankind to be deprived of wit, thought, and penetration,
or what we call reason, since it is a thing pernicious to many and very
useful to few, than to have it bestowed upon them with so much
liberality and in such abundance. But if the divine will has really
consulted the good of man in this gift of reason, the good of those men
only was consulted on whom a well-regulated one is bestowed: how few
those are, if any, is very apparent. We cannot admit, therefore, that
the Gods consulted the good of a few only; the conclusion must be that
they consulted the good of none.
XXVIII. You answer that the ill use which a great part of mankind make
of reason no more takes away the goodness of the Gods, who bestow it as
a present of the greatest benefit to them, than the ill use which
children make of their patrimony diminishes the obligation which they
have to their parents for it. We grant you this; but where is the
similitude? It was far from Deianira’s design to injure Hercules when
she made him a present
344of the shirt dipped in the blood of the
Centaurs. Nor was it a regard to the welfare of Jason of Pheræ that
influenced the man who with his sword opened his imposthume, which the
physicians had in vain attempted to cure. For it has often happened that
people have served a man whom they intended to injure, and have injured
one whom they designed to serve; so that the effect of the gift is by no
means always a proof of the intention of the giver; neither does the
benefit which may accrue from it prove that it came from the hands of a
benefactor. For, in short, what debauchery, what avarice, what crime
among men is there which does not owe its birth to thought and
reflection, that is, to reason? For all opinion is reason: right reason,
if men’s thoughts are conformable to truth; wrong reason, if they are
not. The Gods only give us the mere faculty of reason, if we have any;
the use or abuse of it depends entirely upon ourselves; so that the
comparison is not just between the present of reason given us by the
Gods, and a patrimony left to a son by his father; for, after all, if
the injury of mankind had been the end proposed by the Gods, what could
they have given them more pernicious than reason? for what seed could
there be of injustice, intemperance, and cowardice, if reason were not
laid as the foundation of these vices?
XXIX. I mentioned just now Medea and Atreus, persons celebrated in
heroic poems, who had used this reason only for the contrivance and
practice of the most flagitious crimes; but even the trifling characters
which appear in comedies supply us with the like instances of this
reasoning faculty; for example, does not he, in the Eunuch, reason with
some subtlety?—
What, then, must I resolve upon?
She turn’d me out-of-doors; she sends for me back again;
Shall I go? no, not if she were to beg it of me.
Another, in the Twins, making no scruple of opposing a received maxim,
after the manner of the Academics, asserts that when a man is in love
and in want, it is pleasant
To have a father covetous, crabbed, and passionate,
Who has no love or affection for his children.
345This unaccountable opinion he strengthens thus:
You may defraud him of his profits, or forge letters in his name,
Or fright him by your servant into compliance;
And what you take from such an old hunks,
How much more pleasantly do you spend it!
On the contrary, he says that an easy, generous father is an
inconvenience to a son in love; for, says he,
I can’t tell how to abuse so good, so prudent a parent,
Who always foreruns my desires, and meets me purse in hand,
To support me in my pleasures: this easy goodness and generosity
Quite defeat all my frauds, tricks, and stratagems.
273
What are these frauds, tricks, and stratagems but the effects of reason?
O excellent gift of the Gods! Without this Phormio could not have said,
Find me out the old man: I have something hatching for him in my
head.
XXX. But let us pass from the stage to the bar. The prætor
274 takes
his seat. To judge whom? The man who set fire to our archives. How
secretly was that villany conducted! Q. Sosius, an illustrious Roman
knight, of the Picene field,
275 confessed the fact. Who else is to be
tried? He who forged the public registers—Alenus, an artful fellow, who
counterfeited the handwriting of the six officers.
276 Let us call to
mind other trials: that on the subject of the gold of Tolosa, or the
conspiracy of Jugurtha. Let us trace back the informations laid against
Tubulus for bribery in his judicial office; and, since that, the
proceedings of the tribune Peduceus concerning the
346incest of the
vestals. Let us reflect upon the trials which daily happen for
assassinations, poisonings, embezzlement of public money, frauds in
wills, against which we have a new law; then that action against the
advisers or assisters of any theft; the many laws concerning frauds in
guardianship, breaches of trust in partnerships and commissions in
trade, and other violations of faith in buying, selling, borrowing, or
lending; the public decree on a private affair by the Lætorian Law;
277
and, lastly, that scourge of all dishonesty, the law against fraud,
proposed by our friend Aquillius; that sort of fraud, he says, by which
one thing is pretended and another done. Can we, then, think that this
plentiful fountain of evil sprung from the immortal Gods? If they have
given reason to man, they have likewise given him subtlety, for subtlety
is only a deceitful manner of applying reason to do mischief. To them
likewise we must owe deceit, and every other crime, which, without the
help of reason, would neither have been thought of nor committed. As the
old woman wished
That to the fir which on Mount Pelion grew
The axe had ne’er been laid,
278
so we should wish that the Gods had never bestowed this ability on man,
the abuse of which is so general that the small number of those who make
a good use of it are often oppressed by those who make a bad use of it;
so that it seems to be given rather to help vice than to promote virtue
among us.
XXXI. This, you insist on it, is the fault of man, and not of the Gods.
But should we not laugh at a physician or pilot, though they are weak
mortals, if they were to lay the blame of their ill success on the
violence of the disease or the fury of the tempest? Had there not been
danger, 347we should say, who would have applied to you? This reasoning
has still greater force against the Deity. The fault, you say, is in
man, if he commits crimes. But why was not man endued with a reason
incapable of producing any crimes? How could the Gods err? When we leave
our effects to our children, it is in hopes that they may be well
bestowed; in which we may be deceived, but how can the Deity be
deceived? As PhЕ“bus when he trusted his chariot to his son PhaГ«thon, or
as Neptune when he indulged his son Theseus in granting him three
wishes, the consequence of which was the destruction of Hippolitus?
These are poetical fictions; but truth, and not fables, ought to proceed
from philosophers. Yet if those poetical Deities had foreseen that
their indulgence would have proved fatal to their sons, they must have
been thought blamable for it.
Aristo of Chios used often to say that the philosophers do hurt to such
of their disciples as take their good doctrine in a wrong sense; thus
the lectures of Aristippus might produce debauchees, and those of Zeno
pedants. If this be true, it were better that philosophers should be
silent than that their disciples should be corrupted by a
misapprehension of their master’s meaning; so if reason, which was
bestowed on mankind by the Gods with a good design, tends only to make
men more subtle and fraudulent, it had been better for them never to
have received it. There could be no excuse for a physician who
prescribes wine to a patient, knowing that he will drink it and
immediately expire. Your Providence is no less blamable in giving reason
to man, who, it foresaw, would make a bad use of it. Will you say that
it did not foresee it? Nothing could please me more than such an
acknowledgment. But you dare not. I know what a sublime idea you
entertain of her.
XXXII. But to conclude. If folly, by the unanimous consent of
philosophers, is allowed to be the greatest of all evils, and if no one
ever attained to true wisdom, we, whom they say the immortal Gods take
care of, are consequently in a state of the utmost misery. For that
nobody is well, or that nobody can be well, is in effect the same thing;
and, in my opinion, that no man is truly wise, or that no 348man can be
truly wise, is likewise the same thing. But I will insist no further on
so self-evident a point. Telamon in one verse decides the question. If,
says he, there is a Divine Providence,
Good men would be happy, bad men miserable.
But it is not so. If the Gods had regarded mankind, they should have
made them all virtuous; but if they did not regard the welfare of all
mankind, at least they ought to have provided for the happiness of the
virtuous. Why, therefore, was the Carthaginian in Spain suffered to
destroy those best and bravest men, the two Scipios? Why did
Maximus279 lose his son, the consul? Why did Hannibal kill Marcellus?
Why did Cannæ deprive us of Paulus? Why was the body of Regulus
delivered up to the cruelty of the Carthaginians? Why was not Africanus
protected from violence in his own house? To these, and many more
ancient instances, let us add some of later date. Why is Rutilius, my
uncle, a man of the greatest virtue and learning, now in banishment? Why
was my own friend and companion Drusus assassinated in his own house?
Why was Scævola, the high-priest, that pattern of moderation and
prudence, massacred before the statue of Vesta? Why, before that, were
so many illustrious citizens put to death by Cinna? Why had Marius, the
most perfidious of men, the power to cause the death of Catulus, a man
of the greatest dignity? But there would be no end of enumerating
examples of good men made miserable and wicked men prosperous. Why did
that Marius live to an old age, and die so happily at his own house in
his seventh consulship? Why was that inhuman wretch Cinna permitted to
enjoy so long a reign?
XXXIII. He, indeed, met with deserved punishment at last. But would it
not have been better that these inhumanities had been prevented than
that the author of them should be punished afterward? Varius, a most
impious wretch, was tortured and put to death. If this was his
punishment for the murdering Drusus by the sword, and Metellus by
poison, would it not have been better to have preserved their lives than
to have their deaths avenged on 349Varius? Dionysius was thirty-eight
years a tyrant over the most opulent and flourishing city; and, before
him, how many years did Pisistratus tyrannize in the very flower of
Greece! Phalaris and Apollodorus met with the fate they deserved, but
not till after they had tortured and put to death multitudes. Many
robbers have been executed; but the number of those who have suffered
for their crimes is short of those whom they have robbed and murdered.
Anaxarchus,280 a scholar of Democritus, was cut to pieces by command
of the tyrant of Cyprus; and Zeno of Elea281 ended his life in
tortures. What shall I say of Socrates,282 whose death, as often as I
read of it in Plato, draws fresh tears from my eyes? If, therefore, the
Gods really see everything that happens to men, you must acknowledge
they make no distinction between the good and the bad.
XXXIV. Diogenes the Cynic used to say of Harpalus, one of the most
fortunate villains of his time, that the constant prosperity of such a
man was a kind of witness against the Gods. Dionysius, of whom we have
before spoken, after he had pillaged the temple of Proserpine at Locris,
set sail for Syracuse, and, having a fair wind during his voyage, said,
with a smile, “See, my friends, what favorable winds the immortal Gods
bestow upon church-robbers.” Encouraged by this prosperous event, he
proceeded in his impiety. When he landed at Peloponnesus, he went into
the temple of Jupiter Olympius, and disrobed his statue of a golden
mantle of great weight, an ornament which the tyrant Gelo283 had given
out of the spoils of the Carthaginians, and at the same time, in a
jesting manner, he said “that a golden mantle was too heavy in summer
and too cold in winter;” and then, throwing a woollen cloak over the
statue, added, “This will serve for all seasons.” At another time, he
ordered the golden beard of Г†sculapius of Epidaurus to be taken away,
saying that “it 350was absurd for the son to have a beard, when his father
had none.” He likewise robbed the temples of the silver tables, which,
according to the ancient custom of Greece, bore this inscription, “To
the good Gods,” saying “he was willing to make use of their goodness;”
and, without the least scruple, took away the little golden emblems of
victory, the cups and coronets, which were in the stretched-out hands of
the statues, saying “he did not take, but receive them; for it would be
folly not to accept good things from the Gods, to whom we are constantly
praying for favors, when they stretch out their hands towards us.” And,
last of all, all the things which he had thus pillaged from the temples
were, by his order, brought to the market-place and sold by the common
crier; and, after he had received the money for them, he commanded every
purchaser to restore what he had bought, within a limited time, to the
temples from whence they came. Thus to his impiety towards the Gods he
added injustice to man.
XXXV. Yet neither did Olympian Jove strike him with his thunder, nor did
Г†sculapius cause him to die by tedious diseases and a lingering death.
He died in his bed, had funeral honors284 paid to him, and left his
power, which he had wickedly obtained, as a just and lawful inheritance
to his son.
It is not without concern that I maintain a doctrine which seems to
authorize evil, and which might probably give a sanction to it, if
conscience, without any divine assistance, did not point out, in the
clearest manner, the difference between virtue and vice. Without
conscience man is contemptible. For as no family or state can be
supposed to be formed with any reason or discipline if there are no
rewards for good actions nor punishment for crimes, so we cannot believe
that a Divine Providence regulates the world if there is no distinction
between the honest and the wicked.
351But the Gods, you say, neglect trifling things: the little fields or
vineyards of particular men are not worthy their attention; and if
blasts or hail destroy their product, Jupiter does not regard it, nor do
kings extend their care to the lower offices of government. This
argument might have some weight if, in bringing Rutilius as an instance,
I had only complained of the loss of his farm at Formiæ; but I spoke of
a personal misfortune, his banishment.285
XXXVI. All men agree that external benefits, such as vineyards, corn,
olives, plenty of fruit and grain, and, in short, every convenience and
property of life, are derived from the Gods; and, indeed, with reason,
since by our virtue we claim applause, and in virtue we justly glory,
which we could have no right to do if it was the gift of the Gods, and
not a personal merit. When we are honored with new dignities, or blessed
with increase of riches; when we are favored by fortune beyond our
expectation, or luckily delivered from any approaching evil, we return
thanks for it to the Gods, and assume no praise to ourselves. But who
ever thanked the Gods that he was a good man? We thank them, indeed, for
riches, health, and honor. For these we invoke the all-good and
all-powerful Jupiter; but not for wisdom, temperance, and justice. No
one ever offered a tenth of his estate to Hercules to be made wise. It
is reported, indeed, of Pythagoras that he sacrificed an ox to the Muses
upon having made some new discovery in geometry;286 but, for my part,
I cannot believe it, because he refused to sacrifice even to Apollo at
Delos, lest he should defile the altar with blood. But to return. It is
universally agreed that good fortune we must ask of the Gods, but wisdom
must arise from ourselves; and though temples have been consecrated to
the Mind, to Virtue, and to Faith, yet that does not contradict their
being 352inherent in us. In regard to hope, safety, assistance, and
victory, we must rely upon the Gods for them; from whence it follows, as
Diogenes said, that the prosperity of the wicked destroys the idea of a
Divine Providence.
XXXVII. But good men have sometimes success. They have so; but we
cannot, with any show of reason, attribute that success to the Gods.
Diagoras, who is called the atheist, being at Samothrace, one of his
friends showed him several pictures287 of people who had endured very
dangerous storms; “See,” says he, “you who deny a providence, how many
have been saved by their prayers to the Gods.” “Ay,” says Diagoras, “I
see those who were saved, but where are those painted who were
shipwrecked?” At another time, he himself was in a storm, when the
sailors, being greatly alarmed, told him they justly deserved that
misfortune for admitting him into their ship; when he, pointing to
others under the like distress, asked them “if they believed Diagoras
was also aboard those ships?” In short, with regard to good or bad
fortune, it matters not what you are, or how you have lived. The Gods,
like kings, regard not everything. What similitude is there between
them? If kings neglect anything, want of knowledge may be pleaded in
their defence; but ignorance cannot be brought as an excuse for the
Gods.
XXXVIII. Your manner of justifying them is somewhat extraordinary, when
you say that if a wicked man dies without suffering for his crimes, the
Gods inflict a punishment on his children, his children’s children, and
all his posterity. O wonderful equity of the Gods! What city would
endure the maker of a law which should condemn a son or a grandson for a
crime committed by the father or the grandfather?
Shall Tantalus’ unhappy offspring know
No end, no close, of this long scene of woe?
When will the dire reward of guilt be o’er,
And Myrtilus demand revenge no more?
288
Whether the poets have corrupted the Stoics, or the Stoics given
authority to the poets, I cannot easily determine. Both alike are to be
condemned. If those persons
353whose names have been branded in the
satires of Hipponax or Archilochus
289 were driven to despair, it did
not proceed from the Gods, but had its origin in their own minds. When
we see Г†gistus and Paris lost in the heat of an impure passion, why are
we to attribute it to a Deity, when the crime, as it were, speaks for
itself? I believe that those who recover from illness are more indebted
to the care of Hippocrates than to the power of Г†sculapius; that Sparta
received her laws from Lycurgus
290 rather than from Apollo; that those
eyes of the maritime coast, Corinth and Carthage, were plucked out, the
one by Critolaus, the other by Hasdrubal, without the assistance of any
divine anger, since you yourselves confess that a Deity cannot possibly
be angry on any provocation.
XXXIX. But could not the Deity have assisted and preserved those eminent
cities? Undoubtedly he could; for, according to your doctrine, his power
is infinite, and without the least labor; and as nothing but the will is
necessary to the motion of our bodies, so the divine will of the Gods,
with the like ease, can create, move, and change all things. This you
hold, not from a mere phantom of superstition, but on natural and
settled principles of reason; for matter, you say, of which all things
are composed and consist, is susceptible of all forms and changes, and
there is nothing which cannot be, or cease to be, in an instant; and
that Divine Providence has the command and disposal of this universal
matter, and consequently can, in any part of the universe, do whatever
she pleases: from whence I conclude that this Providence either knows
not the extent of her power, or neglects human affairs, or cannot judge
what is best for us. Providence, you say, does not extend her care to
particular men; there
354is no wonder in that, since she does not extend
it to cities, or even to nations, or people. If, therefore, she neglects
whole nations, is it not very probable that she neglects all mankind?
But how can you assert that the Gods do not enter into all the little
circumstances of life, and yet hold that they distribute dreams among
men? Since you believe in dreams, it is your part to solve this
difficulty. Besides, you say we ought to call upon the Gods. Those who
call upon the Gods are individuals. Divine Providence, therefore,
regards individuals, which consequently proves that they are more at
leisure than you imagine. Let us suppose the Divine Providence to be
greatly busied; that it causes the revolutions of the heavens, supports
the earth, and rules the seas; why does it suffer so many Gods to be
unemployed? Why is not the superintendence of human affairs given to
some of those idle Deities which you say are innumerable?
This is the purport of what I had to say concerning “the Nature of the
Gods;” not with a design to destroy their existence, but merely to show
what an obscure point it is, and with what difficulties an explanation
of it is attended.
XL. Balbus, observing that Cotta had finished his discourse—You have
been very severe, says he, against a Divine Providence, a doctrine
established by the Stoics with piety and wisdom; but, as it grows too
late, I shall defer my answer to another day. Our argument is of the
greatest importance; it concerns our altars,
291 our hearths, our
temples, nay, even the walls of our city, which you priests hold sacred;
you, who by religion defend Rome better than she is defended by her
ramparts. This is a cause which, while I have life, I think I cannot
abandon without impiety.
There is nothing, replied Cotta, which I desire more than to be
confuted. I have not pretended to decide this point, but to give you my
private sentiments upon it; and am very sensible of your great
superiority in argument.
355No doubt of it, says Velleius; we have much to
fear from one who believes that our dreams are sent from Jupiter, which,
though they are of little weight, are yet of more importance than the
discourse of the Stoics concerning the nature of the Gods. The
conversation ended here, and we parted. Velleius judged that the
arguments of Cotta were truest; but those of Balbus seemed to me to have
the greater probability.
292
357ON THE COMMONWEALTH.
PREFACE BY THE EDITOR.
This work was one of Cicero’s earlier treatises, though one of those
which was most admired by his contemporaries, and one of which he
himself was most proud. It was composed 54
b.c. It was originally in two
books: then it was altered and enlarged into nine, and finally reduced
to six. With the exception of the dream of Scipio, in the last book, the
whole treatise was lost till the year 1822, when the librarian of the
Vatican discovered a portion of them among the palimpsests in that
library. What he discovered is translated here; but it is in a most
imperfect and mutilated state.
The form selected was that of a dialogue, in imitation of those of
Plato; and the several conferences were supposed to have taken place
during the Latin holidays, 129
b.c., in the consulship of Caius
Sempronius, Tuditanus, and Marcus Aquilius. The speakers are Scipio
Africanus the younger, in whose garden the scene is laid; Caius Lælius;
Lucius Furius Philus; Marcus Manilius; Spurius Mummius, the brother of
the taker of Corinth, a Stoic; Quintus Г†lius Tubero, a nephew of
Africanus; Publius Rutilius Rufus; Quintus Mucius Scævola, the tutor of
Cicero; and Caius Fannius, who was absent, however, on the second day of
the conference.
In the first book, the first thirty-three pages are wanting, and there
are chasms amounting to thirty-eight pages more. In this book Scipio
asserts the superiority of an active over a speculative career; and
after analyzing and comparing the monarchical, aristocratic, and
democratic forms of government, gives a preference to the first;
although
358his idea of a perfect constitution would be one compounded of
three kinds in due proportion.
There are a few chasms in the earlier part of the second book, and the
latter part of it is wholly lost. In it Scipio was led on to give an
account of the rise and progress of the Roman Constitution, from which
he passed on to the examination of the great moral obligations which are
the foundations of all political union.
Of the remaining books we have only a few disjointed fragments, with the
exception, as has been before mentioned, of the dream of Scipio in the
sixth.
359INTRODUCTION TO THE FIRST BOOK,
BY THE ORIGINAL TRANSLATOR.
Cicero introduces his subject by showing that men were not born for the
mere abstract study of philosophy, but that the study of philosophic
truth should always be made as practical as possible, and applicable to
the great interests of philanthropy and patriotism. Cicero endeavors to
show the benefit of mingling the contemplative or philosophic with the
political and active life, according to that maxim of Plato—“Happy is
the nation whose philosophers are kings, and whose kings are
philosophers.”
This kind of introduction was the more necessary because many of the
ancient philosophers, too warmly attached to transcendental metaphysics
and sequestered speculations, had affirmed that true philosophers ought
not to interest themselves in the management of public affairs. Thus, as
M. Villemain observes, it was a maxim of the Epicureans, “Sapiens ne
accedat ad rempublicam” (Let no wise man meddle in politics). The
Pythagoreans had enforced the same principle with more gravity.
Aristotle examines the question on both sides, and concludes in favor of
active life. Among Aristotle’s disciples, a writer, singularly elegant
and pure, had maintained the pre-eminence of the contemplative life over
the political or active one, in a work which Cicero cites with
admiration, and to which he seems to have applied for relief whenever he
felt harassed and discouraged in public business. But here this great
man was interested by the subject he discusses, and by the whole course
of his experience and conduct, to refute the dogmas of that
pusillanimous sophistry and selfish indulgence by bringing forward the
most glorious examples and achievements of patriotism. In this strain he
had doubtless commenced his exordium, and in this strain we find him
continuing it at the point in which the palimpsest becomes legible. He
then proceeds to introduce his illustrious interlocutors, and leads them
at first to discourse on the astronomical laws that regulate the
revolutions of our planet. From this, by a very graceful and beautiful
transition, he passes on to the consideration of the best forms of
political constitutions that had prevailed in different nations, and
those modes of government which had produced the greatest benefits in
the commonwealths of antiquity.
This first book is, in fact, a splendid epitome of the political science
of the age of Cicero, and probably the most eloquent plea in favor of
mixed monarchy to be found in all literature.
360BOOK I.
I. [
Without the virtue of patriotism], neither Caius Duilius, nor Aulus
Atilius,
293 nor Lucius Metellus, could have delivered Rome by their
courage from the terror of Carthage; nor could the two Scipios, when the
fire of the second Punic War was kindled, have quenched it in their
blood; nor, when it revived in greater force, could either Quintus
Maximus
294 have enervated it, or Marcus Marcellus have crushed it;
nor, when it was repulsed from the gates of our own city, would Scipio
have confined it within the walls of our enemies.
But Cato, at first a new and unknown man, whom all we who aspire to the
same honors consider as a pattern to lead us on to industry and virtue,
was undoubtedly at liberty to enjoy his repose at Tusculum, a most
salubrious and convenient retreat. But he, mad as some people think him,
though no necessity compelled him, preferred being tossed about amidst
the tempestuous waves of politics, even till extreme old age, to living
with all imaginable luxury in that tranquillity and relaxation. I omit
innumerable men who have separately devoted themselves to the protection
of our Commonwealth; and those whose lives are within the memory of the
present generation I will not mention, lest any one should complain that
I had invidiously forgotten himself or some one of his family. This only
I insist on—that so great is the necessity of this virtue which nature
has implanted in man, and so great is the desire to defend the common
safety of our country, that its energy has continually overcome all the
blandishments of pleasure and repose.
II. Nor is it sufficient to possess this virtue as if it were some kind
of art, unless we put it in practice. An art, indeed, though not
exercised, may still be retained in knowledge; but virtue consists
wholly in its proper use
361and action. Now, the noblest use of virtue is
the government of the Commonwealth, and the carrying-out in real action,
not in words only, of all those identical theories which those
philosophers discuss at every corner. For nothing is spoken by
philosophers, so far as they speak correctly and honorably, which has
not been discovered and confirmed by those persons who have been the
founders of the laws of states. For whence comes piety, or from whom has
religion been derived? Whence comes law, either that of nations, or that
which is called the civil law? Whence comes justice, faith, equity?
Whence modesty, continence, the horror of baseness, the desire of praise
and renown? Whence fortitude in labors and perils? Doubtless, from those
who have instilled some of these moral principles into men by education,
and confirmed others by custom, and sanctioned others by laws.
Moreover, it is reported of Xenocrates, one of the sublimest
philosophers, that when some one asked him what his disciples learned,
he replied, “To do that of their own accord which they might be
compelled to do by law.” That citizen, therefore, who obliges all men to
those virtuous actions, by the authority of laws and penalties, to which
the philosophers can scarcely persuade a few by the force of their
eloquence, is certainly to be preferred to the sagest of the doctors who
spend their lives in such discussions. For which of their exquisite
orations is so admirable as to be entitled to be preferred to a
well-constituted government, public justice, and good customs?
Certainly, just as I think that magnificent and imperious cities (as
Ennius says) are superior to castles and villages, so I imagine that
those who regulate such cities by their counsel and authority are far
preferable, with respect to real wisdom, to men who are unacquainted
with any kind of political knowledge. And since we are strongly prompted
to augment the prosperity of the human race, and since we do endeavor by
our counsels and exertions to render the life of man safer and
wealthier, and since we are incited to this blessing by the spur of
nature herself, let us hold on that course which has always been pursued
by all the best men, and not listen for a moment to the signals of those
who sound a retreat so loudly that they
362sometimes call back even those
who have made considerable progress.
III. These reasons, so certain and so evident, are opposed by those who,
on the other side, argue that the labors which must necessarily be
sustained in maintaining the Commonwealth form but a slight impediment
to the vigilant and industrious, and are only a contemptible obstacle in
such important affairs, and even in common studies, offices, and
employments. They add the peril of life, that base fear of death, which
has ever been opposed by brave men, to whom it appears far more
miserable to die by the decay of nature and old age than to be allowed
an opportunity of gallantly sacrificing that life for their country
which must otherwise be yielded up to nature.
On this point, however, our antagonists esteem themselves copious and
eloquent when they collect all the calamities of heroic men, and the
injuries inflicted on them by their ungrateful countrymen. For on this
subject they bring forward those notable examples among the Greeks; and
tell us that Miltiades, the vanquisher and conqueror of the Persians,
before even those wounds were healed which he had received in that most
glorious victory, wasted away in the chains of his fellow-citizens that
life which had been preserved from the weapons of the enemy. They cite
Themistocles, expelled and proscribed by the country which he had
rescued, and forced to flee, not to the Grecian ports which he had
preserved, but to the bosom of the barbarous power which he had
defeated. There is, indeed, no deficiency of examples to illustrate the
levity and cruelty of the Athenians to their noblest citizens—examples
which, originating and multiplying among them, are said at different
times to have abounded in our own most august empire. For we are told:
of the exile of Camillus, the disgrace of Ahala, the unpopularity of
Nasica, the expulsion of Lænas,
295 the condemnation of
363Opimius, the
flight of Metellus, the cruel destruction of Caius Marius, the massacre
of our chieftains, and the many atrocious crimes which followed. My own
history is by no means free from such calamities; and I imagine that
when they recollect that by my counsel and perils they were preserved in
life and liberty, they are led by that consideration to bewail my
misfortunes more deeply and affectionately. But I cannot tell why those
who sail over the seas for the sake of knowledge and experience [should
wonder at seeing still greater hazards braved in the service of the
Commonwealth].
IV. [Since], on my quitting the consulship, I swore in the assembly of
the Roman people, who re-echoed my words, that I had saved the
Commonwealth, I console myself with this remembrance for all my cares,
troubles, and injuries. Although my misfortune had more of honor than
misfortune, and more of glory than disaster; and I derive greater
pleasure from the regrets of good men than sorrow from the exultation of
the worthless. But even if it had happened otherwise, how could I have
complained, as nothing befell me which was either unforeseen, or more
painful than I expected, as a return for my illustrious actions? For I
was one who, though it was in my power to reap more profit from leisure
than most men, on account of the diversified sweetness of my studies, in
which I had lived from boyhood—or, if any public calamity had happened,
to have borne no more than an equal share with the rest of my countrymen
in the misfortune—I nevertheless did not hesitate to oppose myself to
the most formidable tempests and torrents of sedition, for the sake of
saving my countrymen, and at my own proper danger to secure the common
safety of all the rest. For our country did not beget and educate us
with the expectation of receiving no support, as I may call it, from us;
nor for the purpose of consulting nothing but our convenience, to supply
us with a secure refuge for idleness and a tranquil spot for rest; but
rather with a view of turning to her own advantage the nobler portion of
our genius, heart, and counsel; giving us back for our private service
only what she can spare from the public interests.
V. Those apologies, therefore, in which men take refuge
364as an excuse
for their devoting themselves with more plausibility to mere inactivity
do certainly not deserve to be listened to; when, for instance, they
tell us that those who meddle with public affairs are generally
good-for-nothing men, with whom it is discreditable to be compared, and
miserable and dangerous to contend, especially when the multitude is in
an excited state. On which account it is not the part of a wise man to
take the reins, since he cannot restrain the insane and unregulated
movements of the common people. Nor is it becoming to a man of liberal
birth, say they, thus to contend with such vile and unrefined
antagonists, or to subject one’s self to the lashings of contumely, or
to put one’s self in the way of injuries which ought not to be borne by
a wise man. As if to a virtuous, brave, and magnanimous man there could
be a juster reason for seeking the government than this—to avoid being
subjected to worthless men, and to prevent the Commonwealth from being
torn to pieces by them; when, even if they were then desirous to save
her, they would not have the power.
VI. But this restriction who can approve, which would interdict the wise
man from taking any share in the government beyond such as the occasion
and necessity may compel him to? As if any greater necessity could
possibly happen to any man than happened to me. In which, how could I
have acted if I had not been consul at the time? and how could I have
been a consul unless I had maintained that course of life from my
childhood which raised me from the order of knights, in which I was
born, to the very highest station? You cannot produce
extempore, and
just when you please, the power of assisting a commonwealth, although it
may be severely pressed by dangers, unless you have attained the
position which enables you legally to do so. And what most surprises me
in the discourses of learned men, is to hear those persons who confess
themselves incapable of steering the vessel of the State in smooth seas
(which, indeed, they never learned, and never cared to know) profess
themselves ready to assume the helm amidst the fiercest tempests. For
those men are accustomed to say openly, and indeed to boast greatly,
that they have never learned, and have never taken
365the least pains to
explain, the principles of either establishing or maintaining a
commonwealth; and they look on this practical science as one which
belongs not to men of learning and wisdom, but to those who have made it
their especial study. How, then, can it be reasonable for such men to
promise their assistance to the State, when they shall be compelled to
it by necessity, while they are ignorant how to govern the republic when
no necessity presses upon it, which is a much more easy task? Indeed,
though it were true that the wise man loves not to thrust himself of his
own accord into the administration of public affairs, but that if
circumstances oblige him to it, then he does not refuse the office, yet
I think that this science of civil legislation should in no wise be
neglected by the philosopher, because all resources ought to be ready to
his hand, which he knows not how soon he may be called on to use.
VII. I have spoken thus at large for this reason, because in this work I
have proposed to myself and undertaken a discussion on the government of
a state; and in order to render it useful, I was bound, in the first
place, to do away with this pusillanimous hesitation to mingle in public
affairs. If there be any, therefore, who are too much influenced by the
authority of the philosophers, let them consider the subject for a
moment, and be guided by the opinions of those men whose authority and
credit are greatest among learned men; whom I look upon, though some of
them have not personally governed any state, as men who have
nevertheless discharged a kind of office in the republic, inasmuch as
they have made many investigations into, and left many writings
concerning, state affairs. As to those whom the Greeks entitle the Seven
Wise Men, I find that they almost all lived in the middle of public
business. Nor, indeed, is there anything in which human virtue can more
closely resemble the divine powers than in establishing new states, or
in preserving those already established.
VIII. And concerning these affairs, since it has been our good fortune
to achieve something worthy of memorial in the government of our
country, and also to have acquired some facility of explaining the
powers and resources of politics, we can treat of this subject with the
weight of
366personal experience and the habit of instruction and
illustration. Whereas before us many have been skilful in theory, though
no exploits of theirs are recorded; and many others have been men of
consideration in action, but unfamiliar with the arts of exposition.
Nor, indeed, is it at all our intention to establish a new and
self-invented system of government; but our purpose is rather to recall
to memory a discussion of the most illustrious men of their age in our
Commonwealth, which you and I, in our youth, when at Smyrna, heard
mentioned by Publius Rutilius Rufus, who reported to us a conference of
many days in which, in my opinion, there was nothing omitted that could
throw light on political affairs.
IX. For when, in the year of the consulship of Tuditanus and Aquilius,
Scipio Africanus, the son of Paulus Г†milius, formed the project of
spending the Latin holidays at his country-seat, where his most intimate
friends had promised him frequent visits during this season of
relaxation, on the first morning of the festival, his nephew, Quintus
Tubero, made his appearance; and when Scipio had greeted him heartily
and embraced him—How is it, my dear Tubero, said he, that I see you so
early? For these holidays must afford you a capital opportunity of
pursuing your favorite studies. Ah! replied Tubero, I can study my books
at any time, for they are always disengaged; but it is a great
privilege, my Scipio, to find you at leisure, especially in this
restless period of public affairs. You certainly have found me so, said
Scipio, but, to speak truth, I am rather relaxing from business than
from study. Nay, said Tubero, you must try to relax from your studies
too, for here are several of us, as we have appointed, all ready, if it
suits your convenience, to aid you in getting through this leisure time
of yours. I am very willing to consent, answered Scipio, and we may be
able to compare notes respecting the several topics that interest us.
X. Be it so, said Tubero; and since you invite me to discussion, and
present the opportunity, let us first examine, before any one else
arrives, what can be the nature of the parhelion, or double sun, which
was mentioned in the senate. Those that affirm they witnessed this
prodigy
367are neither few nor unworthy of credit, so that there is more
reason for investigation than incredulity.
296
Ah! said Scipio, I wish we had our friend Panætius with us, who is fond
of investigating all things of this kind, but especially all celestial
phenomena. As for my opinion, Tubero, for I always tell you just what I
think, I hardly agree in these subjects with that friend of mine, since,
respecting things of which we can scarcely form a conjecture as to their
character, he is as positive as if he had seen them with his own eyes
and felt them with his own hands. And I cannot but the more admire the
wisdom of Socrates, who discarded all anxiety respecting things of this
kind, and affirmed that these inquiries concerning the secrets of nature
were either above the efforts of human reason, or were absolutely of no
consequence at all to human life.
But, then, my Africanus, replied Tubero, of what credit is the tradition
which states that Socrates rejected all these physical investigations,
and confined his whole attention to men and manners? For, with respect
to him what better authority can we cite than Plato? in many passages of
whose works Socrates speaks in such a manner that even when he is
discussing morals, and virtues, and even public affairs and politics, he
endeavors to interweave, after the fashion of Pythagoras, the doctrines
of arithmetic, geometry, and harmonic proportions with them.
That is true, replied Scipio; but you are aware, I believe, that Plato,
after the death of Socrates, was induced to visit Egypt by his love of
science, and that after that he proceeded to Italy and Sicily, from his
desire of understanding the Pythagorean dogmas; that he conversed much
with Archytas of Tarentum and Timæus of Locris;
368that he collected the
works of Philolaus; and that, finding in these places the renown of
Pythagoras flourishing, he addicted himself exceedingly to the disciples
of Pythagoras, and their studies; therefore, as he loved Socrates with
his whole heart, and wished to attribute all great discoveries to him,
he interwove the Socratic elegance and subtlety of eloquence with
somewhat of the obscurity of Pythagoras, and with that notorious gravity
of his diversified arts.
XI. When Scipio had spoken thus, he suddenly saw Lucius Furius
approaching, and saluting him, and embracing him most affectionately, he
gave him a seat on his own couch. And as soon as Publius Rutilius, the
worthy reporter of the conference to us, had arrived, when we had
saluted him, he placed him by the side of Tubero. Then said Furius, What
is it that you are about? Has our entrance at all interrupted any
conversation of yours? By no means, said Scipio, for you yourself too
are in the habit of investigating carefully the subject which Tubero was
a little before proposing to examine; and our friend Rutilius, even
under the walls of Numantia, was in the habit at times of conversing
with me on questions of the same kind. What, then, was the subject of
your discussion? said Philus. We were talking, said Scipio, of the
double suns that recently appeared, and I wish, Philus, to hear what you
think of them.
XII. Just as he was speaking, a boy announced that Lælius was coming to
call on him, and that he had already left his house. Then Scipio,
putting on his sandals and robes, immediately went forth from his
chamber, and when he had walked a little time in the portico, he met
Lælius, and welcomed him and those that accompanied him, namely, Spurius
Mummius, to whom he was greatly attached, and C. Fannius and Quintus
Scævola, sons-in-law of Lælius, two very intelligent young men, and now
of the quæstorian age.
297
When he had saluted them all, he returned through the portico, placing
Lælius in the middle; for there was in their friendship a sort of law of
reciprocal courtesy, so
369that in the camp Lælius paid Scipio almost
divine honors, on account of his eminent renown in war and in private
life; in his turn Scipio reverenced Lælius, even as a father, because he
was older than himself.
Then after they had exchanged a few words, as they walked up and down,
Scipio, to whom their visit was extremely welcome and agreeable, wished
to assemble them in a sunny corner of the gardens, because it was still
winter; and when they had agreed to this, there came in another friend,
a learned man, much beloved and esteemed by all of them, M. Manilius,
who, after having been most warmly welcomed by Scipio and the rest,
seated himself next to Lælius.
XIII. Then Philus, commencing the conversation, said: It does not appear
to me that the presence of our new guests need alter the subject of our
discussion, but only that it should induce us to treat it more
philosophically, and in a manner more worthy of our increased audience.
What do you allude to? said Lælius; or what was the discussion we broke
in upon? Scipio was asking me, replied Philus, what I thought of the
parhelion, or mock sun, whose recent apparition was so strongly
attested.
Lælius. Do you say then, my Philus, that we have sufficiently examined
those questions which concern our own houses and the Commonwealth, that
we begin to investigate the celestial mysteries?
And Philus replied: Do you think, then, that it does not concern our
houses to know what happens in that vast home which is not included in
walls of human fabrication, but which embraces the entire universe—a
home which the Gods share with us, as the common country of all
intelligent beings? Especially when, if we are ignorant of these things,
there are also many great practical truths which result from them, and
which bear directly on the welfare of our race, of which we must be also
ignorant. And here I can speak for myself, as well as for you, Lælius,
and all men who are ambitious of wisdom, that the knowledge and
consideration of the facts of nature are by themselves very delightful.
Lælius. I have no objection to the discussion, especially as it is
holiday-time with us. But cannot we have the
370pleasure of hearing you
resume it, or are we come too late?
Philus. We have not yet commenced the discussion, and since the
question remains entire and unbroken, I shall have the greatest
pleasure, my Lælius, in handing over the argument to you.
Lælius. No, I had much rather hear you, unless, indeed, Manilius
thinks himself able to compromise the suit between the two suns, that
they may possess heaven as joint sovereigns without intruding on each
other’s empire.
Then Manilius said: Are you going, Lælius, to ridicule a science in
which, in the first place, I myself excel; and, secondly, without which
no one can distinguish what is his own, and what is another’s? But to
return to the point. Let us now at present listen to Philus, who seems
to me to have started a greater question than any of those that have
engaged the attention of either Publius Mucius or myself.
XIV. Then Philus said: I am not about to bring you anything new, or
anything which has been thought over or discovered by me myself. But I
recollect that Caius Sulpicius Gallus, who was a man of profound
learning, as you are aware, when this same thing was reported to have
taken place in his time, while he was staying in the house of Marcus
Marcellus, who had been his colleague in the consulship, asked to see a
celestial globe which Marcellus’s grandfather had saved after the
capture of Syracuse from that magnificent and opulent city, without
bringing to his own home any other memorial out of so great a booty;
which I had often heard mentioned on account of the great fame of
Archimedes; but its appearance, however, did not seem to me particularly
striking. For that other is more elegant in form, and more generally
known, which was made by the same Archimedes, and deposited by the same
Marcellus in the Temple of Virtue at Rome. But as soon as Gallus had
begun to explain, in a most scientific manner, the principle of this
machine, I felt that the Sicilian geometrician must have possessed a
genius superior to anything we usually conceive to belong to our nature.
For Gallus assured us that that other solid and compact globe was a very
ancient invention, and that the first
371model had been originally made by
Thales of Miletus. That afterward Eudoxus of Cnidus, a disciple of
Plato, had traced on its surface the stars that appear in the sky, and
that many years subsequently, borrowing from Eudoxus this beautiful
design and representation, Aratus had illustrated it in his verses, not
by any science of astronomy, but by the ornament of poetic description.
He added that the figure of the globe, which displayed the motions of
the sun and moon, and the five planets, or wandering stars, could not be
represented by the primitive solid globe; and that in this the invention
of Archimedes was admirable, because he had calculated how a single
revolution should maintain unequal and diversified progressions in
dissimilar motions. In fact, when Gallus moved this globe, we observed
that the moon succeeded the sun by as many turns of the wheel in the
machine as days in the heavens. From whence it resulted that the
progress of the sun was marked as in the heavens, and that the moon
touched the point where she is obscured by the earth’s shadow at the
instant the sun appears opposite.
298 *В *В *
XV. *В *В *
299 I had myself a great affection for this Gallus, and I
know that he was very much beloved and esteemed by my father Paulus. I
recollect that when I was very young, when my father, as consul,
commanded in Macedonia, and we were in the camp, our army was seized
with a pious terror, because suddenly, in a clear night, the bright and
full moon became eclipsed. And Gallus, who was then our lieutenant, the
year before that in which he was elected consul, hesitated not, next
morning, to state in the camp that it was no prodigy, and that the
phenomenon which had then appeared would always appear at certain
periods, when the sun was so placed that he could not affect the moon
with his light.
372But do you mean, said Tubero, that he dared to speak thus to men almost
entirely uneducated and ignorant?
Scipio. He did, and with great *В *В * for his opinion was no result of
insolent ostentation, nor was his language unbecoming the dignity of so
wise a man: indeed, he performed a very noble action in thus freeing his
countrymen from the terrors of an idle superstition.
XVI. And they relate that in a similar way, in the great war in which
the Athenians and Lacedæmonians contended with such violent resentment,
the famous Pericles, the first man of his country in credit, eloquence,
and political genius, observing the Athenians overwhelmed with an
excessive alarm during an eclipse of the sun which caused a sudden
darkness, told them, what he had learned in the school of Anaxagoras,
that these phenomena necessarily happened at precise and regular periods
when the body of the moon was interposed between the sun and the earth,
and that if they happened not before every new moon, still they could
not possibly happen except at the exact time of the new moon. And when
he had proved this truth by his reasonings, he freed the people from
their alarms; for at that period the doctrine was new and unfamiliar
that the sun was accustomed to be eclipsed by the interposition of the
moon, which fact they say that Thales of Miletus was the first to
discover. Afterward my friend Ennius appears to have been acquainted
with the same theory, who, writing about 350
300 years after the
foundation of Rome, says, “In the nones of June the sun was covered by
the moon and night.” The calculations in the astronomical art have
attained such perfection that from that day, thus described to us by
Ennius and recorded in the pontifical registers, the anterior eclipses
of the sun have been computed as far back as the nones of July in the
reign of Romulus, when that eclipse took place, in the obscurity of
which it was affirmed that Virtue bore Romulus to heaven, in spite of
the perishable nature which carried him off by the common fate of
humanity.
373XVII. Then said Tubero: Do not you think, Scipio, that this
astronomical science, which every day proves so useful, just now
appeared in a different light to you,
301 *В *В * which the rest may see.
Moreover, who can think anything in human affairs of brilliant
importance who has penetrated this starry empire of the gods? Or who can
think anything connected with mankind long who has learned to estimate
the nature of eternity? or glorious who is aware of the insignificance
of the size of the earth, even in its whole extent, and especially in
the portion which men inhabit? And when we consider that almost
imperceptible point which we ourselves occupy unknown to the majority of
nations, can we still hope that our name and reputation can be widely
circulated? And then our estates and edifices, our cattle, and the
enormous treasures of our gold and silver, can they be esteemed or
denominated as desirable goods by him who observes their perishable
profit, and their contemptible use, and their uncertain domination,
often falling into the possession of the very worst men? How happy,
then, ought we to esteem that man who alone has it in his power, not by
the law of the Romans, but by the privilege of philosophers, to enjoy
all things as his own; not by any civil bond, but by the common right of
nature, which denies that anything can really be possessed by any one
but him who understands its true nature and use; who reckons our
dictatorships and consulships rather in the rank of necessary offices
than desirable employments, and thinks they must be endured rather as
acquittances of our debt to our country than sought for the sake of
emolument or glory—the man, in short, who can apply to himself the
sentence which Cato tells us my ancestor Africanus loved to repeat,
“that he was never so busy as when he did nothing, and never less
solitary than when alone.”
For who can believe that Dionysius, when after every possible effort he
ravished from his fellow-citizens their liberty, had performed a nobler
work than Archimedes, when, without appearing to be doing anything, he
manufactured the globe which we have just been describing?
374Who does not
see that those men are in reality more solitary who, in the midst of a
crowd, find no one with whom they can converse congenially than those
who, without witnesses, hold communion with themselves, and enter into
the secret counsels of the sagest philosophers, while they delight
themselves in their writings and discoveries? And who would think any
one richer than the man who is in want of nothing which nature requires;
or more powerful than he who has attained all that she has need of; or
happier than he who is free from all mental perturbation; or more secure
in future than he who carries all his property in himself, which is thus
secured from shipwreck? And what power, what magistracy, what royalty,
can be preferred to a wisdom which, looking down on all terrestrial
objects as low and transitory things, incessantly directs its attention
to eternal and immutable verities, and which is persuaded that though
others are called men, none are really so but those who are refined by
the appropriate acts of humanity?
In this sense an expression of Plato or some other philosopher appears
to me exceedingly elegant, who, when a tempest had driven his ship on an
unknown country and a desolate shore, during the alarms with which their
ignorance of the region inspired his companions, observed, they say,
geometrical figures traced in the sand, on which he immediately told
them to be of good cheer, for he had observed the indications of Man. A
conjecture he deduced, not from the cultivation of the soil which he
beheld, but from the symbols of science. For this reason, Tubero,
learning and learned men, and these your favorite studies, have always
particularly pleased me.
XVIII. Then Lælius replied: I cannot venture, Scipio, to answer your
arguments, or to [maintain the discussion either against] you, Philus,
or Manilius.
302 *В *В *
We had a friend in Tubero’s father’s family, who in these respects may
serve him as a model.
Sextus so wise, and ever on his guard.
Wise and cautious indeed he was, as Ennius justly describes him—not
because he searched for what he could
375never find, but because he knew
how to answer those who prayed for deliverance from cares and
difficulties. It is he who, reasoning against the astronomical studies
of Gallus, used frequently to repeat these words of Achilles in the
Iphigenia
303:
They note the astrologic signs of heaven,
Whene’er the goats or scorpions of great Jove,
Or other monstrous names of brutal forms,
Rise in the zodiac; but not one regards
The sensible facts of earth, on which we tread,
While gazing on the starry prodigies.
He used, however, to say (and I have often listened to him with
pleasure) that for his part he thought that Zethus, in the piece of
Pacuvius, was too inimical to learning. He much preferred the
Neoptolemus of Ennius, who professes himself desirous of philosophizing
only in moderation; for that he did not think it right to be wholly
devoted to it. But though the studies of the Greeks have so many charms
for you, there are others, perhaps, nobler and more extensive, which we
may be better able to apply to the service of real life, and even to
political affairs. As to these abstract sciences, their utility, if they
possess any, lies principally in exciting and stimulating the abilities
of youth, so that they more easily acquire more important
accomplishments.
XIX. Then Tubero said: I do not mean to disagree with you, Lælius; but,
pray, what do you call more important studies?
Lælius. I will tell you frankly, though perhaps you will think lightly
of my opinion, since you appeared so eager in interrogating Scipio
respecting the celestial phenomena; but I happen to think that those
things which are every day before our eyes are more particularly
deserving of our attention. Why should the child of Paulus Г†milius, the
nephew of Г†milius, the descendant of such a noble family and so glorious
a republic, inquire how there can be two suns in heaven, and not ask how
there can be two senates in one Commonwealth, and, as it were, two
distinct peoples?
376For, as you see, the death of Tiberius Gracchus, and
the whole system of his tribuneship, has divided one people into two
parties. But the slanderers and the enemies of Scipio, encouraged by P.
Crassus and Appius Claudius, maintained, after the death of these two
chiefs, a division of nearly half the senate, under the influence of
Metellus and Mucius. Nor would they permit the man
304 who alone could
have been of service to help us out of our difficulties during the
movement of the Latins and their allies towards rebellion, violating all
our treaties in the presence of factious triumvirs, and creating every
day some fresh intrigue, to the disturbance of the worthier and
wealthier citizens. This is the reason, young men, if you will listen to
me, why you should regard this new sun with less alarm; for, whether it
does exist, or whether it does not exist, it is, as you see, quite
harmless to us. As to the manner of its existence, we can know little or
nothing; and even if we obtained the most perfect understanding of it,
this knowledge would make us but little wiser or happier. But that there
should exist a united people and a united senate is a thing which
actually may be brought about, and it will be a great evil if it is not;
and that it does not exist at present we are aware; and we see that if
it can be effected, our lives will be both better and happier.
XX. Then Mucius said: What, then, do you consider, my Lælius, should be
our best arguments in endeavoring to bring about the object of your
wishes?
Lælius. Those sciences and arts which teach us how we may be most
useful to the State; for I consider that the most glorious office of
wisdom, and the noblest proof and business of virtue. In order,
therefore, that we may consecrate these holidays as much as possible to
conversations which may be profitable to the Commonwealth, let us beg
Scipio to explain to us what in his estimation appears to be the best
form of government. Then let us pass on to other points, the knowledge
of which may lead us, as I hope, to sound political views, and unfold
the causes of the dangers which now threaten us.
XXI. When Philus, Manilius, and Mummius had all expressed
377their great
approbation of this idea
305 *В *В * I have ventured [to open our
discussion] in this way, not only because it is but just that on State
politics the chief man in the State should be the principal speaker, but
also because I recollect that you, Scipio, were formerly very much in
the habit of conversing with Panætius and Polybius, two Greeks,
exceedingly learned in political questions, and that you are master of
many arguments by which you prove that by far the best condition of
government is that which our ancestors have handed down to us. And as
you, therefore, are familiar with this subject, if you will explain to
us your views respecting the general principles of a state (I speak for
my friends as well as myself), we shall feel exceedingly obliged to you.
XXII. Then Scipio said: I must acknowledge that there is no subject of
meditation to which my mind naturally turns with more ardor and
intensity than this very one which Lælius has proposed to us. And,
indeed, as I see that in every profession, every artist who would
distinguish himself, thinks of, and aims at, and labors for no other
object but that of attaining perfection in his art, should not I, whose
main business, according to the example of my father and my ancestors,
is the advancement and right administration of government, be confessing
myself more indolent than any common mechanic if I were to bestow on
this noblest of sciences less attention and labor than they devote to
their insignificant trades? However, I am neither entirely satisfied
with the decisions which the greatest and wisest men of Greece have left
us; nor, on the other hand, do I venture to prefer my own opinions to
theirs. Therefore, I must request you not to consider me either entirely
ignorant of the Grecian literature, nor yet disposed, especially in
political questions, to yield it the pre-eminence over our own; but
rather to regard me as a true-born Roman, not illiberally instructed by
the care of my father, and inflamed with the desire of knowledge, even
from my boyhood, but still even more familiar with domestic precepts and
practices than the literature of books.
XXIII. On this Philus said: I have no doubt, my Scipio, that no one is
superior to you in natural genius,
378and that you are very far superior
to every one in the practical experience of national government and of
important business. We are also acquainted with the course which your
studies have at all times taken; and if, as you say, you have given so
much attention to this science and art of politics, we cannot be too
much obliged to Lælius for introducing the subject: for I trust that
what we shall hear from you will be far more useful and available than
all the writings put together which the Greeks have written for us.
Then Scipio replied: You are raising a very high expectation of my
discourse, such as is a most oppressive burden to a man who is required
to discuss grave subjects.
And Philus said: Although that may be a difficulty, my Scipio, still you
will be sure to conquer it, as you always do; nor is there any danger of
eloquence failing you, when you begin to speak on the affairs of a
commonwealth.
XXIV. Then Scipio proceeded: I will do what you wish, as far as I can;
and I shall enter into the discussion under favor of that rule which, I
think, should be adopted by all persons in disputations of this kind, if
they wish to avoid being misunderstood; namely, that when men have
agreed respecting the proper name of the matter under discussion, it
should be stated what that name exactly means, and what it legitimately
includes. And when that point is settled, then it is fit to enter on the
discussion; for it will never be possible to arrive at an understanding
of what the character of the subject of the discussion is, unless one
first understands exactly what it is. Since, then, our investigations
relate to a commonwealth, we must first examine what this name properly
signifies.
And when Lælius had intimated his approbation of this course, Scipio
continued:
I shall not adopt, said he, in so clear and simple a manner that system
of discussion which goes back to first principles; as learned men often
do in this sort of discussion, so as to go back to the first meeting of
male and female, and then to the first birth and formation of the first
family, and define over and over again what there is in words, and in
how many manners each thing is stated.
379For, as I am speaking to men of
prudence, who have acted with the greatest glory in the Commonwealth,
both in peace and war, I will take care not to allow the subject of the
discussion itself to be clearer than my explanation of it. Nor have I
undertaken this task with the design of examining all its minuter
points, like a school-master; nor will I promise you in the following
discourse not to omit any single particular.
Then Lælius said: For my part, I am impatient for exactly that kind of
disquisition which you promise us.
XXV. Well, then, said Africanus, a commonwealth is a constitution of the
entire people. But the people is not every association of men, however
congregated, but the association of the entire number, bound together by
the compact of justice, and the communication of utility. The first
cause of this association is not so much the weakness of man as a
certain spirit of congregation which naturally belongs to him. For the
human race is not a race of isolated individuals, wandering and
solitary; but it is so constituted that even in the affluence of all
things [and without any need of reciprocal assistance, it spontaneously
seeks society].
XXVI. [It is necessary to presuppose] these original seeds, as it were,
since we cannot discover any primary establishment of the other virtues,
or even of a commonwealth itself. These unions, then, formed by the
principle which I have mentioned, established their headquarters
originally in certain central positions, for the convenience of the
whole population; and having fortified them by natural and artificial
means, they called this collection of houses a city or town,
distinguished by temples and public squares. Every people, therefore,
which consists of such an association of the entire multitude as I have
described, every city which consists of an assemblage of the people, and
every commonwealth which embraces every member of these associations,
must be regulated by a certain authority, in order to be permanent.
This intelligent authority should always refer itself to that grand
first principle which established the Commonwealth. It must be deposited
in the hands of one supreme person, or intrusted to the administration
of certain delegated
380rulers, or undertaken by the whole multitude. When
the direction of all depends on one person, we call this individual a
king, and this form of political constitution a kingdom. When it is in
the power of privileged delegates, the State is said to be ruled by an
aristocracy; and when the people are all in all, they call it a
democracy, or popular constitution. And if the tie of social affection,
which originally united men in political associations for the sake of
public interest, maintains its force, each of these forms of government
is, I will not say perfect, nor, in my opinion, essentially good, but
tolerable, and such that one may accidentally be better than another:
either a just and wise king, or a selection of the most eminent
citizens, or even the populace itself (though this is the least
commendable form), may, if there be no interference of crime and
cupidity, form a constitution sufficiently secure.
XXVII. But in a monarchy the other members of the State are often too
much deprived of public counsel and jurisdiction; and under the rule of
an aristocracy the multitude can hardly possess its due share of
liberty, since it is allowed no share in the public deliberation, and no
power. And when all things are carried by a democracy, although it be
just and moderate, yet its very equality is a culpable levelling,
inasmuch as it allows no gradations of rank. Therefore, even if Cyrus,
the King of the Persians, was a most righteous and wise monarch, I
should still think that the interest of the people (for this is, as I
have said before, the same as the Commonwealth) could not be very
effectually promoted when all things depended on the beck and nod of one
individual. And though at present the people of Marseilles, our clients,
are governed with the greatest justice by elected magistrates of the
highest rank, still there is always in this condition of the people a
certain appearance of servitude; and when the Athenians, at a certain
period, having demolished their Areopagus, conducted all public affairs
by the acts and decrees of the democracy alone, their State, as it no
longer contained a distinct gradation of ranks, was no longer able to
retain its original fair appearance.
XXVIII. I have reasoned thus on the three forms of government, not
looking on them in their disorganized
381and confused conditions, but in
their proper and regular administration. These three particular forms,
however, contained in themselves, from the first, the faults and defects
I have mentioned; but they have also other dangerous vices, for there is
not one of these three forms of government which has not a precipitous
and slippery passage down to some proximate abuse. For, after thinking
of that endurable, or, as you will have it, most amiable king, Cyrus—to
name him in preference to any one else—then, to produce a change in our
minds, we behold the barbarous Phalaris, that model of tyranny, to which
the monarchical authority is easily abused by a facile and natural
inclination. And, in like manner, along-side of the wise aristocracy of
Marseilles, we might exhibit the oligarchical faction of the thirty
tyrants which once existed at Athens. And, not to seek for other
instances, among the same Athenians, we can show you that when unlimited
power was cast into the hands of the people, it inflamed the fury of the
multitude, and aggravated that universal license which ruined their
State.
306 *В *В *
XXIX. The worst condition of things sometimes results from a confusion
of those factious tyrannies into which kings, aristocrats, and democrats
are apt to degenerate. For thus, from these diverse elements, there
occasionally arises (as I have said before) a new kind of government.
And wonderful indeed are the revolutions and periodical returns in
natural constitutions of such alternations and vicissitudes, which it is
the part of the wise politician to investigate with the closest
attention. But to calculate their approach, and to join to this
foresight the skill which moderates the course of events, and retains in
a steady hand the reins of that authority which safely conducts the
people through all the dangers to which they expose themselves, is the
work of a most illustrious citizen, and of almost divine genius.
There is a fourth kind of government, therefore, which, in my opinion,
is preferable to all these: it is that mixed and moderate government
which is composed of the three particular forms which I have already
noticed.
XXX.
Lælius. I am not ignorant, Scipio, that such is
382your opinion,
for I have often heard you say so. But I do not the less desire, if it
is not giving you too much trouble, to hear which you consider the best
of these three forms of commonwealths. For it may be of some use in
considering
307 *В *В *
XXXI. *В *В * And each commonwealth corresponds to the nature and will of
him who governs it. Therefore, in no other constitution than that in
which the people exercise sovereign power has liberty any sure abode,
than which there certainly is no more desirable blessing. And if it be
not equally established for every one, it is not even liberty at all.
And how can there be this character of equality, I do not say under a
monarchy, where slavery is least disguised or doubtful, but even in
those constitutions in which the people are free indeed in words, for
they give their suffrages, they elect officers, they are canvassed and
solicited for magistracies; but yet they only grant those things which
they are obliged to grant whether they will or not, and which are not
really in their free power, though others ask them for them? For they
are not themselves admitted to the government, to the exercise of public
authority, or to offices of select judges, which are permitted to those
only of ancient families and large fortunes. But in a free people, as
among the Rhodians and Athenians, there is no citizen who
308 *В *В *
XXXII. *В *В * No sooner is one man, or several, elevated by wealth and
power, than they say that *В *В * arise from their pride and arrogance,
when the idle and the timid give way, and bow down to the insolence of
riches. But if the people knew how to maintain its rights, then they say
that nothing could be more glorious and prosperous than democracy;
inasmuch as they themselves would be the sovereign dispensers of laws,
judgments, war, peace, public treaties, and, finally, of the fortune and
life of each individual citizen; and this condition of things is the
only one which, in their opinion, can be really called a commonwealth,
that is to say, a constitution of the people. It is on this principle
that, according to them, a people often vindicates its liberty from the
domination of kings and
383nobles; while, on the other hand, kings are not
sought for among free peoples, nor are the power and wealth of
aristocracies. They deny, moreover, that it is fair to reject this
general constitution of freemen, on account of the vices of the
unbridled populace; but that if the people be united and inclined, and
directs all its efforts to the safety and freedom of the community,
nothing can be stronger or more unchangeable; and they assert that this
necessary union is easily obtained in a republic so constituted that the
good of all classes is the same; while the conflicting interests that
prevail in other constitutions inevitably produce dissensions;
therefore, say they, when the senate had the ascendency, the republic
had no stability; and when kings possess the power, this blessing is
still more rare, since, as Ennius expresses it,
In kingdoms there’s no faith, and little love.
Wherefore, since the law is the bond of civil society, and the justice
of the law equal, by what rule can the association of citizens be held
together, if the condition of the citizens be not equal? For if the
fortunes of men cannot be reduced to this equality—if genius cannot be
equally the property of all—rights, at least, should be equal among
those who are citizens of the same republic. For what is a republic but
an association of rights?
309 *В *В *
XXXIII. But as to the other political constitutions, these democratical
advocates do not think they are worthy of being distinguished by the
name which they claim. For why, say they, should we apply the name of
king, the title of Jupiter the Beneficent, and not rather the title of
tyrant, to a man ambitious of sole authority and power, lording it over
a degraded multitude? For a tyrant may be as merciful as a king may be
oppressive; so that the whole difference to the people is, whether they
serve an indulgent master or a cruel one, since serve some one they
must. But how could Sparta, at the period of the boasted superiority of
her political institution, obtain a constant enjoyment of just and
virtuous kings, when they necessarily received an hereditary monarch,
good, bad, or indifferent, because he happened to be of the blood royal?
As to
384aristocrats, Who will endure, say they, that men should
distinguish themselves by such a title, and that not by the voice of the
people, but by their own votes? For how is such a one judged to be best
either in learning, sciences, or arts?
310 *В *В *
XXXIV. *В *В * If it does so by hap-hazard, it will be as easily upset as
a vessel if the pilot were chosen by lot from among the passengers. But
if a people, being free, chooses those to whom it can trust itself—and,
if it desires its own preservation, it will always choose the
noblest—then certainly it is in the counsels of the aristocracy that
the safety of the State consists, especially as nature has not only
appointed that these superior men should excel the inferior sort in high
virtue and courage, but has inspired the people also with the desire of
obedience towards these, their natural lords. But they say this
aristocratical State is destroyed by the depraved opinions of men, who,
through ignorance of virtue (which, as it belongs to few, can be
discerned and appreciated by few), imagine that not only rich and
powerful men, but also those who are nobly born, are necessarily the
best. And so when, through this popular error, the riches, and not the
virtue, of a few men has taken possession of the State, these chiefs
obstinately retain the title of nobles, though they want the essence of
nobility. For riches, fame, and power, without wisdom and a just method
of regulating ourselves and commanding others, are full of discredit and
insolent arrogance; nor is there any kind of government more deformed
than that in which the wealthiest are regarded as the noblest.
But when virtue governs the Commonwealth, what can be more glorious?
When he who commands the rest is himself enslaved by no lust or passion;
when he himself exhibits all the virtues to which he incites and
educates the citizens; when he imposes no law on the people which he
does not himself observe, but presents his life as a living law to his
fellow-countrymen; if a single individual could thus suffice for all,
there would be no need of more; and if the community could find a chief
ruler thus worthy of all their suffrages, none would require elected
magistrates.
385It was the difficulty of forming plans which transferred the government
from a king into the hands of many; and the error and temerity of the
people likewise transferred it from the hands of the many into those of
the few. Thus, between the weakness of the monarch and the rashness of
the multitude, the aristocrats have occupied the middle place, than
which nothing can be better arranged; and while they superintend the
public interest, the people necessarily enjoy the greatest possible
prosperity, being free from all care and anxiety, having intrusted their
security to others, who ought sedulously to defend it, and not allow the
people to suspect that their advantage is neglected by their rulers.
For as to that equality of rights which democracies so loudly boast of,
it can never be maintained; for the people themselves, so dissolute and
so unbridled, are always inclined to flatter a number of demagogues; and
there is in them a very great partiality for certain men and dignities,
so that their equality, so called, becomes most unfair and iniquitous.
For as equal honor is given to the most noble and the most infamous,
some of whom must exist in every State, then the equity which they
eulogize becomes most inequitable—an evil which never can happen in
those states which are governed by aristocracies. These reasonings, my
Lælius, and some others of the same kind, are usually brought forward by
those that so highly extol this form of political constitution.
XXXV. Then Lælius said: But you have not told us, Scipio, which of these
three forms of government you yourself most approve.
Scipio. You are right to shape your question, which of the three I
most approve, for there is not one of them which I approve at all by
itself, since, as I told you, I prefer that government which is mixed
and composed of all these forms, to any one of them taken separately.
But if I must confine myself to one of these particular forms simply and
exclusively, I must confess I prefer the royal one, and praise that as
the first and best. In this, which I here choose to call the primitive
form of government, I find the title of father attached to that of king,
to express that he watches over the citizens as over his children, and
endeavors
386rather to preserve them in freedom than reduce them to
slavery. So that it is more advantageous for those who are insignificant
in property and capacity to be supported by the care of one excellent
and eminently powerful man. The nobles here present themselves, who
profess that they can do all this in much better style; for they say
that there is much more wisdom in many than in one, and at least as much
faith and equity. And, last of all, come the people, who cry with a loud
voice that they will render obedience neither to the one nor the few;
that even to brute beasts nothing is so dear as liberty; and that all
men who serve either kings or nobles are deprived of it. Thus, the kings
attract us by affection, the nobles by talent, the people by liberty;
and in the comparison it is hard to choose the best.
Lælius. I think so too, but yet it is impossible to despatch the other
branches of the question, if you leave this primary point undetermined.
XXXVI.
Scipio. We must then, I suppose, imitate Aratus, who, when he
prepared himself to treat of great things, thought himself in duty bound
to begin with Jupiter.
Lælius. Wherefore Jupiter? and what is there in this discussion which
resembles that poem?
Scipio. Why, it serves to teach us that we cannot better commence our
investigations than by invoking him whom, with one voice, both learned
and unlearned extol as the universal king of all gods and men.
How so? said Lælius.
Do you, then, asked Scipio, believe in nothing which is not before your
eyes? whether these ideas have been established by the chiefs of states
for the benefit of society, that there might be believed to exist one
Universal Monarch in heaven, at whose nod (as Homer expresses it) all
Olympus trembles, and that he might be accounted both king and father of
all creatures; for there is great authority, and there are many
witnesses, if you choose to call all many, who attest that all nations
have unanimously recognized, by the decrees of their chiefs, that
nothing is better than a king, since they think that all the Gods are
governed by the divine power of one sovereign; or if we suspect
387that
this opinion rests on the error of the ignorant, and should be classed
among the fables, let us listen to those universal testimonies of
erudite men, who have, as it were, seen with their eyes those things to
the knowledge of which we can hardly attain by report.
What men do you mean? said Lælius.
Those, replied Scipio, who, by the investigation of nature, have arrived
at the opinion that the whole universe [is animated] by a single
Mind
311. *В *В *
XXXVII. But if you please, my Lælius, I will bring forward evidences
which are neither too ancient nor in any respect barbarous.
Those, said Lælius, are what I want.
Scipio. You are aware that it is now not four centuries since this
city of ours has been without kings.
Lælius. You are correct; it is less than four centuries.
Scipio. Well, then, what are four centuries in the age of a state or
city? is it a long time?
Lælius. It hardly amounts to the age of maturity.
Scipio. You say truly; and yet not four centuries have elapsed since
there was a king in Rome.
Lælius. And he was a proud king.
Scipio. But who was his predecessor?
Lælius. He was an admirably just one; and, indeed, we must bestow the
same praise on all his predecessors as far back as Romulus, who reigned
about six centuries ago.
Scipio. Even he, then, is not very ancient.
Lælius. No; he reigned when Greece was already becoming old.
Scipio. Agreed. Was Romulus, then, think you, king of a barbarous
people?
Lælius. Why, as to that, if we were to follow the example of the
Greeks, who say that all people are either Greeks or barbarians, I am
afraid that we must confess that he was a king of barbarians; but if
this name belongs rather to manners than to languages, then I believe
the Greeks were just as barbarous as the Romans.
Then Scipio said: But with respect to the present question, we do not so
much need to inquire into the nation as into the disposition. For if
intelligent men, at a period so
388little remote, desired the government
of kings, you will confess that I am producing authorities that are
neither antiquated, rude, nor insignificant.
XXXVIII. Then Lælius said: I see, Scipio, that you are very sufficiently
provided with authorities; but with me, as with every fair judge,
authorities are worth less than arguments.
Scipio replied: Then, Lælius, you shall yourself make use of an argument
derived from your own senses.
Lælius. What senses do you mean?
Scipio. The feelings which you experience when at any time you happen
to feel angry with any one.
Lælius. That happens rather oftener than I could wish.
Scipio. Well, then, when you are angry, do you permit your anger to
triumph over your judgment?
No, by Hercules! said Lælius; I imitate the famous Archytas of Tarentum,
who, when he came to his villa, and found all its arrangements were
contrary to his orders, said to his steward, “Ah! you unlucky scoundrel,
I would flog you to death, if it were not that I am in a rage with you.”
Capital, said Scipio. Archytas, then, regarded unreasonable anger as a
kind of sedition and rebellion of nature which he sought to appease by
reflection. And so, if we examine avarice, the ambition of power or of
glory, or the lusts of concupiscence and licentiousness, we shall find a
certain conscience in the mind of man, which, like a king, sways by the
force of counsel all the inferior faculties and propensities; and this,
in truth, is the noblest portion of our nature; for when conscience
reigns, it allows no resting-place to lust, violence, or temerity.
Lælius. You have spoken the truth.
Scipio. Well, then, does a mind thus governed and regulated meet your
approbation?
Lælius. More than anything upon earth.
Scipio. Then you would not approve that the evil passions, which are
innumerable, should expel conscience, and that lusts and animal
propensities should assume an ascendency over us?
Lælius. For my part, I can conceive nothing more wretched than a mind
thus degraded, or a man animated by a soul so licentious.
389Scipio. You desire, then, that all the faculties of the mind should
submit to a ruling power, and that conscience should reign over them
all?
Lælius. Certainly, that is my wish.
Scipio. How, then, can you doubt what opinion to form on the subject
of the Commonwealth? in which, if the State is thrown into many hands,
it is very plain that there will be no presiding authority; for if power
be not united, it soon comes to nothing.
XXXIX. Then Lælius asked: But what difference is there, I should like to
know, between the one and the many, if justice exists equally in many?
And Scipio said: Since I see, my Lælius, that the authorities I have
adduced have no great influence on you, I must continue to employ you
yourself as my witness in proof of what I am saying.
In what way, said Lælius, are you going to make me again support your
argument?
Scipio. Why, thus: I recollect, when we were lately at Formiæ, that
you told your servants repeatedly to obey the orders of more than one
master only.
Lælius. To be sure, those of my steward.
Scipio. What do you at home? Do you commit your affairs to the hands
of many persons?
Lælius. No, I trust them to myself alone.
Scipio. Well, in your whole establishment, is there any other master
but yourself?
Lælius. Not one.
Scipio. Then I think you must grant me that, as respects the State,
the government of single individuals, provided they are just, is
superior to any other.
Lælius. You have conducted me to this conclusion, and I entertain very
nearly that opinion.
XL. And Scipio said: You would still further agree with me, my Lælius,
if, omitting the common comparisons, that one pilot is better fitted to
steer a ship, and a physician to treat an invalid, provided they be
competent men in their respective professions, than many could be, I
should come at once to more illustrious examples.
Lælius. What examples do you mean?
Scipio. Do not you observe that it was the cruelty and
390pride of one
single Tarquin only that made the title of king unpopular among the
Romans?
Lælius. Yes, I acknowledge that.
Scipio. You are also aware of this fact, on which I think I shall
debate in the course of the coming discussion, that after the expulsion
of King Tarquin, the people was transported by a wonderful excess of
liberty. Then innocent men were driven into banishment; then the estates
of many individuals were pillaged, consulships were made annual, public
authorities were overawed by mobs, popular appeals took place in all
cases imaginable; then secessions of the lower orders ensued, and,
lastly, those proceedings which tended to place all powers in the hands
of the populace.
Lælius. I must confess this is all too true.
All these things now, said Scipio, happened during periods of peace and
tranquillity, for license is wont to prevail when there is little to
fear, as in a calm voyage or a trifling disease. But as we observe the
voyager and the invalid implore the aid of some one competent director,
as soon as the sea grows stormy and the disease alarming, so our nation
in peace and security commands, threatens, resists, appeals from, and
insults its magistrates, but in war obeys them as strictly as kings; for
public safety is, after all, rather more valuable than popular license.
And in the most serious wars, our countrymen have even chosen the entire
command to be deposited in the hands of some single chief, without a
colleague; the very name of which magistrate indicates the absolute
character of his power. For though he is evidently called dictator
because he is appointed (dicitur), yet do we still observe him, my
Lælius, in our sacred books entitled Magister Populi (the master of the
people).
This is certainly the case, said Lælius.
Our ancestors, therefore, said Scipio, acted wisely.
312 *В *В *
XLI. When the people is deprived of a just king, as Ennius says, after
the death of one of the best of monarchs,
They hold his memory dear, and, in the warmth
Of their discourse, they cry, O Romulus!
O prince divine, sprung from the might of Mars
To be thy country’s guardian! O our sire!
Be our protector still, O heaven-begot!
391Not heroes, nor lords alone, did they call those whom they lawfully
obeyed; nor merely as kings did they proclaim them; but they pronounced
them their country’s guardians, their fathers, and their Gods. Nor,
indeed, without cause, for they added,
Thou, Prince, hast brought us to the gates of light.
And truly they believed that life and honor and glory had arisen to them
from the justice of their king. The same good-will would doubtless have
remained in their descendants, if the same virtues had been preserved on
the throne; but, as you see, by the injustice of one man the whole of
that kind of constitution fell into ruin.
I see it indeed, said Lælius, and I long to know the history of these
political revolutions both in our own Commonwealth and in every other.
XLII. And Scipio said: When I shall have explained my opinion respecting
the form of government which I prefer, I shall be able to speak to you
more accurately respecting the revolutions of states, though I think
that such will not take place so easily in the mixed form of government
which I recommend. With respect, however, to absolute monarchy, it
presents an inherent and invincible tendency to revolution. No sooner
does a king begin to be unjust than this entire form of government is
demolished, and he at once becomes a tyrant, which is the worst of all
governments, and one very closely related to monarchy. If this State
falls into the hands of the nobles, which is the usual course of events,
it becomes an aristocracy, or the second of the three kinds of
constitutions which I have described; for it is, as it were, a
royal—that is to say, a paternal—council of the chief men of the State
consulting for the public benefit. Or if the people by itself has
expelled or slain a tyrant, it is moderate in its conduct as long as it
has sense and wisdom, and while it rejoices in its exploit, and applies
itself to maintaining the constitution which it has established. But if
ever the people has raised its forces against a just king and robbed him
of his throne, or, as has frequently happened, has tasted the blood of
its legitimate nobles, and subjected the whole Commonwealth to its own
license, you can imagine 392no flood or conflagration so terrible, or any
whose violence is harder to appease than this unbridled insolence of the
populace.
XLIII. Then we see realized that which Plato so vividly describes, if I
can but express it in our language. It is by no means easy to do it
justice in translation: however, I will try.
When, says Plato, the insatiate jaws of the populace are fired with the
thirst of liberty, and when the people, urged on by evil ministers,
drains in its thirst the cup, not of tempered liberty, but unmitigated
license, then the magistrates and chiefs, if they are not utterly
subservient and remiss, and shameless promoters of the popular
licentiousness, are pursued, incriminated, accused, and cried down under
the title of despots and tyrants. I dare say you recollect the passage.
Yes, said Lælius, it is familiar to me.
Scipio. Plato thus proceeds: Then those who feel in duty bound to obey
the chiefs of the State are persecuted by the insensate populace, who
call them voluntary slaves. But those who, though invested with
magistracies, wish to be considered on an equality with private
individuals, and those private individuals who labor to abolish all
distinctions between their own class and the magistrates, are extolled
with acclamations and overwhelmed with honors, so that it inevitably
happens in a commonwealth thus revolutionized that liberalism abounds in
all directions, due authority is found wanting even in private families,
and misrule seems to extend even to the animals that witness it. Then
the father fears the son, and the son neglects the father. All modesty
is banished; they become far too liberal for that. No difference is made
between the citizen and the alien; the master dreads and cajoles his
scholars, and the scholars despise their masters. The young men assume
the gravity of sages, and sages must stoop to the follies of children,
lest they should be hated and oppressed by them. The very slaves even
are under but little restraint; wives boast the same rights as their
husbands; dogs, horses, and asses are emancipated in this outrageous
excess of freedom, and run about so violently that they frighten the
passengers from the road. At length 393the termination of all this
infinite licentiousness is, that the minds of the citizens become so
fastidious and effeminate, that when they observe even the slightest
exertion of authority they grow angry and seditious, and thus the laws
begin to be neglected, so that the people are absolutely without any
master at all.
Then Lælius said: You have very accurately rendered the opinions which
he expressed.
XLIV. Scipio. Now, to return to the argument of my discourse. It
appears that this extreme license, which is the only liberty in the eyes
of the vulgar, is, according to Plato, such that from it as a sort of
root tyrants naturally arise and spring up. For as the excessive power
of an aristocracy occasions the destruction of the nobles, so this
excessive liberalism of democracies brings after it the slavery of the
people. Thus we find in the weather, the soil, and the animal
constitution the most favorable conditions are sometimes suddenly
converted by their excess into the contrary, and this fact is especially
observable in political governments; and this excessive liberty soon
brings the people collectively and individually to an excessive
servitude. For, as I said, this extreme liberty easily introduces the
reign of tyranny, the severest of all unjust slaveries. In fact, from
the midst of this unbridled and capricious populace, they elect some one
as a leader in opposition to their afflicted and expelled nobles: some
new chief, forsooth, audacious and impure, often insolently persecuting
those who have deserved well of the State, and ready to gratify the
populace at his neighbor’s expense as well as his own. Then, since the
private condition is naturally exposed to fears and alarms, the people
invest him with many powers, and these are continued in his hands. Such
men, like Pisistratus of Athens, will soon find an excuse for
surrounding themselves with body-guards, and they will conclude by
becoming tyrants over the very persons who raised them to dignity. If
such despots perish by the vengeance of the better citizens, as is
generally the case, the constitution is re-established; but if they fall
by the hands of bold insurgents, then the same faction succeeds them,
which is only another species of tyranny. And the same revolution arises
394from the fair system of aristocracy when any corruption has betrayed
the nobles from the path of rectitude. Thus the power is like the ball
which is flung from hand to hand: it passes from kings to tyrants, from
tyrants to the aristocracy, from them to democracy, and from these back
again to tyrants and to factions; and thus the same kind of government
is seldom long maintained.
XLV. Since these are the facts of experience, royalty is, in my opinion,
very far preferable to the three other kinds of political constitutions.
But it is itself inferior to that which is composed of an equal mixture
of the three best forms of government, united and modified by one
another. I wish to establish in a commonwealth a royal and pre-eminent
chief. Another portion of power should be deposited in the hands of the
aristocracy, and certain things should be reserved to the judgment and
wish of the multitude. This constitution, in the first place, possesses
that great equality without which men cannot long maintain their
freedom; secondly, it offers a great stability, while the particular
separate and isolated forms easily fall into their contraries; so that a
king is succeeded by a despot, an aristocracy by a faction, a democracy
by a mob and confusion; and all these forms are frequently sacrificed to
new revolutions. In this united and mixed constitution, however, similar
disasters cannot happen without the greatest vices in public men. For
there can be little to occasion revolution in a state in which every
person is firmly established in his appropriate rank, and there are but
few modes of corruption into which we can fall.
XLVI. But I fear, Lælius, and you, my amiable and learned friends, that
if I were to dwell any longer on this argument, my words would seem
rather like the lessons of a master, and not like the free conversation
of one who is uniting with you in the consideration of truth. I shall
therefore pass on to those things which are familiar to all, and which I
have long studied. And in these matters I believe, I feel, and I affirm
that of all governments there is none which, either in its entire
constitution or the distribution of its parts, or in the discipline of
its manners, is comparable to that which our fathers received from our
earliest ancestors, and which they have handed down to 395us. And since
you wish to hear from me a development of this constitution, with which
you are all acquainted, I shall endeavor to explain its true character
and excellence. Thus keeping my eye fixed on the model of our Roman
Commonwealth, I shall endeavor to accommodate to it all that I have to
say on the best form of government. And by treating the subject in this
way, I think I shall be able to accomplish most satisfactorily the task
which Lælius has imposed on me.
XLVII. Lælius. It is a task most properly and peculiarly your own, my
Scipio; for who can speak so well as you either on the subject of the
institutions of our ancestors, since you yourself are descended from
most illustrious ancestors, or on that of the best form of a
constitution which, if we possess (though at this moment we do not,
still), when we do possess such a thing, who will be more flourishing in
it than you? or on that of providing counsels for the future, as you,
who, by dispelling two mighty perils from our city, have provided for
its safety forever?
FRAGMENTS.
XLVIII. As our country is the source of the greatest benefits, and is a
parent dearer than those who have given us life, we owe her still warmer
gratitude than belongs to our human relations. *В *В *
Nor would Carthage have continued to flourish during six centuries
without wisdom and good institutions. *В *В *
In truth, says Cicero, although the reasonings of those men may contain
most abundant fountains of science and virtue; still, if we compare them
with the achievements and complete actions of statesmen, they will seem
not to have been of so much service in the actual business of men as of
amusement for their leisure.
396INTRODUCTION TO THE SECOND BOOK,
BY THE ORIGINAL TRANSLATOR.
In this second book of his Commonwealth, Cicero gives us a spirited and
eloquent review of the history and successive developments of the Roman
constitution. He bestows the warmest praises on its early kings, points
out the great advantages which had resulted from its primitive
monarchical system, and explains how that system had been gradually
broken up. In order to prove the importance of reviving it, he gives a
glowing picture of the evils and disasters that had befallen the Roman
State in consequence of that overcharge of democratic folly and violence
which had gradually gained an alarming preponderance, and describes,
with a kind of prophetic sagacity, the fruit of his political
experience, the subsequent revolutions of the Roman State, which such a
state of things would necessarily bring about.
BOOK II.
I. [
When, therefore, he observed all his friends kindled with the
de]sire of hearing him, Scipio thus opened the discussion. I will
commence, said Scipio, with a sentiment of old Cato, whom, as you know,
I singularly loved and exceedingly admired, and to whom, in compliance
with the judgment of both my parents, and also by my own desire, I was
entirely devoted during my youth; of whose discourse, indeed, I could
never have enough, so much experience did he possess as a statesman
respecting the republic which he had so long governed, both in peace and
war, with so much success. There was also an admirable propriety in his
style of conversation, in which wit was tempered with gravity; a
wonderful aptitude for acquiring, and at the same time communicating,
information; and his life was in perfect correspondence and unison with
his language. He used to say that the government of Rome was superior to
that of other states for this reason, because in nearly all of them
there had been single individuals, each of whom had regulated their
commonwealth
397according to their own laws and their own ordinances. So
Minos had done in Crete, and Lycurgus in Sparta; and in Athens, which
experienced so many revolutions, first Theseus, then Draco, then Solon,
then Clisthenes, afterward many others; and, lastly, when it was almost
lifeless and quite prostrate, that great and wise man, Demetrius
Phalereus, supported it. But our Roman constitution, on the contrary,
did not spring from the genius of one individual, but from that of many;
and it was established, not in the lifetime of one man, but in the
course of several ages and centuries. For, added he, there never yet
existed any genius so vast and comprehensive as to allow nothing at any
time to escape its attention; and all the geniuses in the world united
in a single mind could never, within the limits of a single life, exert
a foresight sufficiently extensive to embrace and harmonize all, without
the aid of experience and practice.
Thus, according to Cato’s usual habit, I now ascend in my discourse to
the “origin of the people,” for I like to adopt the expression of Cato.
I shall also more easily execute my proposed task if I thus exhibit to
you our political constitution in its infancy, progress, and maturity,
now so firm and fully established, than if, after the example of
Socrates in the books of Plato, I were to delineate a mere imaginary
republic.
II. When all had signified their approbation, Scipio resumed: What
commencement of a political constitution can we conceive more brilliant,
or more universally known, than the foundation of Rome by the hand of
Romulus? And he was the son of Mars: for we may grant this much to the
common report existing among men, especially as it is not merely
ancient, but one also which has been wisely maintained by our ancestors,
in order that those who have done great service to communities may enjoy
the reputation of having received from the Gods, not only their genius,
but their very birth.
It is related, then, that soon after the birth of Romulus and his
brother Remus, Amulius, King of Alba, fearing that they might one day
undermine his authority, ordered that they should be exposed on the
banks of the Tiber; and that in this situation the infant Romulus was
suckled
398by a wild beast; that he was afterward educated by the
shepherds, and brought up in the rough way of living and labors of the
countrymen; and that he acquired, when he grew up, such superiority over
the rest by the vigor of his body and the courage of his soul, that all
the people who at that time inhabited the plains in the midst of which
Rome now stands, tranquilly and willingly submitted to his government.
And when he had made himself the chief of those bands, to come from
fables to facts, he took Alba Longa, a powerful and strong city at that
time, and slew its king, Amulius.
III. Having acquired this glory, he conceived the design (as they tell
us) of founding a new city and establishing a new state. As respected
the site of his new city, a point which requires the greatest foresight
in him who would lay the foundation of a durable commonwealth, he chose
the most convenient possible position. For he did not advance too near
the sea, which he might easily have done with the forces under his
command, either by entering the territory of the Rutuli and Aborigines,
or by founding his citadel at the mouth of the Tiber, where many years
after Ancus Martius established a colony. But Romulus, with admirable
genius and foresight, observed and perceived that sites very near the
sea are not the most favorable positions for cities which would attain a
durable prosperity and dominion. And this, first, because maritime
cities are always exposed, not only to many attacks, but to perils they
cannot provide against. For the continued land gives notice, by many
indications, not only of any regular approaches, but also of any sudden
surprises of an enemy, and announces them beforehand by the mere sound.
There is no adversary who, on an inland territory, can arrive so swiftly
as to prevent our knowing not only his existence, but his character too,
and where he comes from. But a maritime and naval enemy can fall upon a
town on the sea-coast before any one suspects that he is about to come;
and when he does come, nothing exterior indicates who he is, or whence
he comes, or what he wishes; nor can it even be determined and
distinguished on all occasions whether he is a friend or a foe.
IV. But maritime cities are likewise naturally exposed
399to corrupt
influences, and revolutions of manners. Their civilization is more or
less adulterated by new languages and customs, and they import not only
foreign merchandise, but foreign fashions, to such a degree that nothing
can continue unalloyed in the national institutions. Those who inhabit
these maritime towns do not remain in their native place, but are urged
afar from their homes by winged hope and speculation. And even when they
do not desert their country in person, still their minds are always
expatiating and voyaging round the world.
Nor, indeed, was there any cause which more deeply undermined Corinth
and Carthage, and at last overthrew them both, than this wandering and
dispersion of their citizens, whom the passion of commerce and
navigation had induced to abandon the cultivation of their lands and
their attention to military pursuits.
The proximity of the sea likewise administers to maritime cities a
multitude of pernicious incentives to luxury, which are either acquired
by victory or imported by commerce; and the very agreeableness of their
position nourishes many expensive and deceitful gratifications of the
passions. And what I have spoken of Corinth may be applied, for aught I
know, without incorrectness to the whole of Greece. For the Peloponnesus
itself is almost wholly on the sea-coast; nor, besides the Phliasians,
are there any whose lands do not touch the sea; and beyond the
Peloponnesus, the Г†nianes, the Dorians, and the Dolopes are the only
inland people. Why should I speak of the Grecian islands, which, girded
by the waves, seem all afloat, as it were, together with the
institutions and manners of their cities? And these things, I have
before noticed, do not respect ancient Greece only; for which of all
those colonies which have been led from Greece into Asia, Thracia,
Italy, Sicily, and Africa, with the single exception of Magnesia, is
there that is not washed by the sea? Thus it seems as if a sort of
Grecian coast had been annexed to territories of the barbarians. For
among the barbarians themselves none were heretofore a maritime people,
if we except the Carthaginians and Etruscans; one for the sake of
commerce, the other of pillage. And this is one evident reason of the
calamities and revolutions of Greece,
400because she became infected with
the vices which belong to maritime cities, which I just now briefly
enumerated. But yet, notwithstanding these vices, they have one great
advantage, and one which is of universal application, namely, that there
is a great facility for new inhabitants flocking to them. And, again,
that the inhabitants are enabled to export and send abroad the produce
of their native lands to any nation they please, which offers them a
market for their goods.
V. By what divine wisdom, then, could Romulus embrace all the benefits
that could belong to maritime cities, and at the same time avoid the
dangers to which they are exposed, except, as he did, by building his
city on the bank of an inexhaustible river, whose equal current
discharges itself into the sea by a vast mouth, so that the city could
receive all it wanted from the sea, and discharge its superabundant
commodities by the same channel? And in the same river a communication
is found by which it not only receives from the sea all the productions
necessary to the conveniences and elegances of life, but those also
which are brought from the inland districts. So that Romulus seems to me
to have divined and anticipated that this city would one day become the
centre and abode of a powerful and opulent empire; for there is no other
part of Italy in which a city could be situated so as to be able to
maintain so wide a dominion with so much ease.
VI. As to the natural fortifications of Rome, who is so negligent and
unobservant as not to have them depicted and deeply stamped on his
memory? Such is the plan and direction of the walls, which, by the
prudence of Romulus and his royal successors, are bounded on all sides
by steep and rugged hills; and the only aperture between the Esquiline
and Quirinal mountains is enclosed by a formidable rampart, and
surrounded by an immense fosse. And as for our fortified citadel, it is
so secured by a precipitous barrier and enclosure of rocks, that, even
in that horrible attack and invasion of the Gauls, it remained
impregnable and inviolable. Moreover, the site which he selected had
also an abundance of fountains, and was healthy, though it was in the
midst of a pestilential region; for there are hills which at once create
a current
401of fresh air, and fling an agreeable shade over the valleys.
VII. These things he effected with wonderful rapidity, and thus
established the city, which, from his own name Romulus, he determined to
call Rome. And in order to strengthen his new city, he conceived a
design, singular enough, and even a little rude, yet worthy of a great
man, and of a genius which discerned far away in futurity the means of
strengthening his power and his people. The young Sabine females of
honorable birth who had come to Rome, attracted by the public games and
spectacles which Romulus then, for the first time, established as annual
games in the circus, were suddenly carried off at the feast of
Consus
313 by his orders, and were given in marriage to the men of the
noblest families in Rome. And when, on this account, the Sabines had
declared war against Rome, the issue of the battle being doubtful and
undecided, Romulus made an alliance with Tatius, King of the Sabines, at
the intercession of the matrons themselves who had been carried off. By
this compact he admitted the Sabines into the city, gave them a
participation in the religious ceremonies, and divided his power with
their king.
VIII. But after the death of Tatius, the entire government was again
vested in the hands of Romulus, although, besides making Tatius his own
partner, he had also elected some of the chiefs of the Sabines into the
royal council, who on account of their affectionate regard for the
people were called
patres, or fathers. He also divided the people into
three tribes, called after the name of Tatius, and his own name, and
that of Locumo, who had fallen as his ally in the Sabine war; and also
into thirty curiæ, designated by the names of those Sabine virgins, who,
after being carried off at the festivals, generously offered themselves
as the mediators of peace and coalition.
But though these orders were established in the life of Tatius, yet,
after his death, Romulus reigned with still greater power by the counsel
and authority of the senate.
IX. In this respect he approved and adopted the principle which Lycurgus
but little before had applied to the government of Lacedæmon; namely,
that the monarchical
402authority and the royal power operate best in the
government of states when to this supreme authority is joined the
influence of the noblest of the citizens.
Therefore, thus supported, and, as it were, propped up by this council
or senate, Romulus conducted many wars with the neighboring nations in a
most successful manner; and while he refused to take any portion of the
booty to his own palace, he did not cease to enrich the citizens. He
also cherished the greatest respect for that institution of hierarchical
and ecclesiastical ordinances which we still retain to the great benefit
of the Commonwealth; for in the very commencement of his government he
founded the city with religious rites, and in the institution of all
public establishments he was equally careful in attending to these
sacred ceremonials, and associated with himself on these occasions
priests that were selected from each of the tribes. He also enacted that
the nobles should act as patrons and protectors to the inferior
citizens, their natural clients and dependants, in their respective
districts, a measure the utility of which I shall afterward notice.—The
judicial punishments were mostly fines of sheep and oxen; for the
property of the people at that time consisted in their fields and
cattle, and this circumstance has given rise to the expressions which
still designate real and personal wealth. Thus the people were kept in
order rather by mulctations than by bodily inflictions.
X. After Romulus had thus reigned thirty-seven years, and established
these two great supports of government, the hierarchy and the senate,
having disappeared in a sudden eclipse of the sun, he was thought worthy
of being added to the number of the Gods—an honor which no mortal man
ever was able to attain to but by a glorious pre-eminence of virtue. And
this circumstance was the more to be admired in the case of Romulus
because most of the great men that have been deified were so exalted to
celestial dignities by the people, in periods very little enlightened,
when fiction was easy and ignorance went hand-in-hand with credulity.
But with respect to Romulus we know that he lived less than six
centuries ago, at a time when science and literature were already
advanced, and had got rid of many of the ancient errors that had
403prevailed among less civilized peoples. For if, as we consider proved
by the Grecian annals, Rome was founded in the seventh Olympiad, the
life of Romulus was contemporary with that period in which Greece
already abounded in poets and musicians—an age when fables, except
those concerning ancient matters, received little credit.
For, one hundred and eight years after the promulgation of the laws of
Lycurgus, the first Olympiad was established, which indeed, through a
mistake of names, some authors have supposed constituted, by Lycurgus
likewise. And Homer himself, according to the best computation, lived
about thirty years before the time of Lycurgus. We must conclude,
therefore, that Homer flourished very many years before the date of
Romulus. So that, as men had now become learned, and as the times
themselves were not destitute of knowledge, there was not much room left
for the success of mere fictions. Antiquity indeed has received fables
that have at times been sufficiently improbable: but this epoch, which
was already so cultivated, disdaining every fiction that was impossible,
rejected
314 *В *В * We may therefore, perhaps, attach some credit to
this story of Romulus’s immortality, since human life was at that time
experienced, cultivated, and instructed. And doubtless there was in him
such energy of genius and virtue that it is not altogether impossible to
believe the report of Proculus Julius, the husbandman, of that
glorification having befallen Romulus which for many ages we have denied
to less illustrious men. At all events, Proculus is reported to have
stated in the council, at the instigation of the senators, who wished to
free themselves from all suspicion of having been accessaries to the
death of Romulus, that he had seen him on that hill which is now called
the Quirinal, and that he had commanded him to inform the people that
they should build him a temple on that same hill, and offer him
sacrifices under the name of Quirinus.
XI. You see, therefore, that the genius of this great man did not merely
establish the constitution of a new people, and then leave them, as it
were, crying in their cradle; but he still continued to superintend
their education
404till they had arrived at an adult and wellnigh a mature
age.
Then Lælius said: We now see, my Scipio, what you meant when you said
that you would adopt a new method of discussing the science of
government, different from any found in the writings of the Greeks. For
that prime master of philosophy, whom none ever surpassed in eloquence,
I mean Plato, chose an open plain on which to build an imaginary city
after his own taste—a city admirably conceived, as none can deny, but
remote enough from the real life and manners of men. Others, without
proposing to themselves any model or type of government whatever, have
argued on the constitutions and forms of states. You, on the contrary,
appear to be about to unite these two methods; for, as far as you have
gone, you seem to prefer attributing to others your discoveries, rather
than start new theories under your own name and authority, as Socrates
has done in the writings of Plato. Thus, in speaking of the site of
Rome, you refer to a systematic policy, to the acts of Romulus, which
were many of them the result of necessity or chance; and you do not
allow your discourse to run riot over many states, but you fix and
concentrate it on our own Commonwealth. Proceed, then, in the course you
have adopted; for I see that you intend to examine our other kings, in
your pursuit of a perfect republic, as it were.
XII. Therefore, said Scipio, when that senate of Romulus which was
composed of the nobles, whom the king himself respected so highly that
he designated them
patres, or fathers, and their children patricians,
attempted after the death of Romulus to conduct the government without a
king, the people would not suffer it, but, amidst their regret for
Romulus, desisted not from demanding a fresh monarch. The nobles then
prudently resolved to establish an interregnum—a new political form,
unknown to other nations. It was not without its use, however, since,
during the interval which elapsed before the definitive nomination of
the new king, the State was not left without a ruler, nor subjected too
long to the same governor, nor exposed to the fear lest some one, in
consequence of the prolonged enjoyment of power, should become more
unwilling
405to lay it aside, or more powerful if he wished to secure it
permanently for himself. At which time this new nation discovered a
political provision which had escaped the Spartan Lycurgus, who
conceived that the monarch ought not to be elective—if indeed it is
true that this depended on Lycurgus—but that it was better for the
Lacedæmonians to acknowledge as their sovereign the next heir of the
race of Hercules, whoever he might be: but our Romans, rude as they
were, saw the importance of appointing a king, not for his family, but
for his virtue and experience.
XIII. And fame having recognized these eminent qualities in Numa
Pompilius, the Roman people, without partiality for their own citizens,
committed itself, by the counsel of the senators, to a king of foreign
origin, and summoned this Sabine from the city of Cures to Rome, that he
might reign over them. Numa, although the people had proclaimed him king
in their Comitia Curiata, did nevertheless himself pass a Lex Curiata
respecting his own authority; and observing that the institutions of
Romulus had too much excited the military propensities of the people, he
judged it expedient to recall them from this habit of warfare by other
employments.
XIV. And, in the first place, he divided severally among the citizens
the lands which Romulus had conquered, and taught them that even without
the aid of pillage and devastation they could, by the cultivation of
their own territories, procure themselves all kinds of commodities. And
he inspired them with the love of peace and tranquillity, in which faith
and justice are likeliest to flourish, and extended the most powerful
protection to the people in the cultivation of their fields and the
enjoyment of their produce. Pompilius likewise having created
hierarchical institutions of the highest class, added two augurs to the
old number. He intrusted the superintendence of the sacred rites to five
pontiffs, selected from the body of the nobles; and by those laws which
we still preserve on our monuments he mitigated, by religious
ceremonials, the minds that had been too long inflamed by military
enthusiasm and enterprise.
He also established the Flamines and the Salian priests
406and the Vestal
Virgins, and regulated all departments of our ecclesiastical policy with
the most pious care. In the ordinance of sacrifices, he wished that the
ceremonial should be very arduous and the expenditure very light. He
thus appointed many observances, whose knowledge is extremely important,
and whose expense far from burdensome. Thus in religious worship he
added devotion and removed costliness. He was also the first to
introduce markets, games, and the other usual methods of assembling and
uniting men. By these establishments, he inclined to benevolence and
amiability spirits whom the passion for war had rendered savage and
ferocious. Having thus reigned in the greatest peace and concord
thirty-nine years—for in dates we mainly follow our Polybius, than whom
no one ever gave more attention to the investigation of the history of
the times—he departed this life, having corroborated the two grand
principles of political stability, religion and clemency.
XV. When Scipio had concluded these remarks, Is it not, said Manilius, a
true tradition which is current, that our king Numa was a disciple of
Pythagoras himself, or that at least he was a Pythagorean in his
doctrines? For I have often heard this from my elders, and we know that
it is the popular opinion; but it does not seem to be clearly proved by
the testimony of our public annals.
Then Scipio replied: The supposition is false, my Manilius; it is not
merely a fiction, but a ridiculous and bungling one too; and we should
not tolerate those statements, even in fiction, relating to facts which
not only did not happen, but which never could have happened. For it was
not till the fourth year of the reign of Tarquinius Superbus that
Pythagoras is ascertained to have come to Sybaris, Crotona, and this
part of Italy. And the sixty-second Olympiad is the common date of the
elevation of Tarquin to the throne, and of the arrival of Pythagoras.
>From which it appears, when we calculate the duration of the reigns of
the kings, that about one hundred and forty years must have elapsed
after the death of Numa before Pythagoras first arrived in Italy. And
this fact, in the minds of men who have carefully studied the annals of
time, has never been at all doubted.
407O ye immortal Gods! said Manilius, how deep and how inveterate is this
error in the minds of men! However, it costs me no effort to concede
that our Roman sciences were not imported from beyond the seas, but that
they sprung from our own indigenous and domestic virtues.
XVI. You will become still more convinced of this fact, said Africanus,
when tracing the progress of our Commonwealth as it became gradually
developed to its best and maturest condition. And you will find yet
further occasion to admire the wisdom of our ancestors on this very
account, since you will perceive, that even those things which they
borrowed from foreigners received a much higher improvement among us
than they possessed in the countries from whence they were imported
among us; and you will learn that the Roman people was aggrandized, not
by chance or hazard, but rather by counsel and discipline, to which
fortune indeed was by no means unfavorable.
XVII. After the death of King Pompilius, the people, after a short
period of interregnum, chose Tullus Hostilius for their king, in the
Comitia Curiata; and Tullus, after Numa’s example, consulted the people
in their curias to procure a sanction for his government. His excellence
chiefly appeared in his military glory and great achievements in war. He
likewise, out of his military spoils, constructed and decorated the
House of Comitia and the Senate-house. He also settled the ceremonies of
the proclamation of hostilities, and consecrated their righteous
institution by the religious sanction of the Fetial priests, so that
every war which was not duly announced and declared might be adjudged
illegal, unjust, and impious. And observe how wisely our kings at that
time perceived that certain rights ought to be allowed to the people, of
which we shall have a good deal to say hereafter. Tullus did not even
assume the ensigns of royalty without the approbation of the people; and
when he appointed twelve lictors, with their axes to go before him
315 *В *В *
XVIII. *В *В * [
Manilius.] This Commonwealth of Rome, which you are so
eloquently describing, did not creep towards perfection; it rather flew
at once to the maturity of its grandeur.
408[
Scipio.] After Tullus, Ancus Martius, a descendant of Numa by his
daughter, was appointed king by the people. He also procured the passing
of a law
316 through the Comitia Curiata respecting his government.
This king having conquered the Latins, admitted them to the rights of
citizens of Rome. He added to the city the Aventine and Cælian hills; he
distributed the lands he had taken in war; he bestowed on the public all
the maritime forests he had acquired; and he built the city Ostia, at
the mouth of the Tiber, and colonized it. When he had thus reigned
twenty-three years, he died.
Then said Lælius: Doubtless this king deserves our praises, but the
Roman history is obscure. We possess, indeed, the name of this monarch’s
mother, but we know nothing of his father.
It is so, said Scipio; but in those ages little more than the names of
the kings were recorded.
XIX. For the first time at this period, Rome appears to have become more
learned by the study of foreign literature; for it was no longer a
little rivulet, flowing from Greece towards the walls of our city, but
an overflowing river of Grecian sciences and arts. This is generally
attributed to Demaratus, a Corinthian, the first man of his country in
reputation, honor, and wealth; who, not being able to bear the despotism
of Cypselus, tyrant of Corinth, fled with large treasures, and arrived
at Tarquinii, the most flourishing city in Etruria. There, understanding
that the domination of Cypselus was thoroughly established, he, like a
free and bold-hearted man, renounced his country, and was admitted into
the number of the citizens of Tarquinii, and fixed his residence in that
city. And having married a woman of the city, he instructed his two
sons, according to the method of Greek education, in all kinds of
sciences and arts.
317 *В *В *
XX. *В *В * [One of these sons] was easily admitted to
409the rights of
citizenship at Rome; and on account of his accomplished manners and
learning, he became a favorite of our king Ancus to such a degree that
he was a partner in all his counsels, and was looked upon almost as his
associate in the government. He, besides, possessed wonderful
affability, and was very kind in assistance, support, protection, and
even gifts of money, to the citizens.
When, therefore, Ancus died, the people by their unanimous suffrages
chose for their king this Lucius Tarquinius (for he had thus transformed
the Greek name of his family, that he might seem in all respects to
imitate the customs of his adopted countrymen). And when he, too, had
procured the passing of a law respecting his authority, he commenced his
reign by doubling the original number of the senators. The ancient
senators he called patricians of the major families (
patres majorum
gentium), and he asked their votes first; and those new senators whom
he himself had added, he entitled patricians of minor families. After
this, he established the order of knights, on the plan which we maintain
to this day. He would not, however, change the denomination of the
Tatian, Rhamnensian, and Lucerian orders, though he wished to do so,
because Attus Nævius, an augur of the highest reputation, would not
sanction it. And, indeed, I am aware that the Corinthians were
remarkably attentive to provide for the maintenance and good condition
of their cavalry by taxes levied on the inheritance of widows and
orphans. To the first equestrian orders Lucius also added new ones,
composing a body of three hundred knights. And this number he doubled,
after having conquered the Г†quicoli, a large and ferocious people, and
dangerous enemies of the Roman State. Having likewise repulsed from our
walls an invasion of the Sabines, he routed them by the aid of his
cavalry, and subdued them. He also was the first person who instituted
the grand games which are now called the Roman Games. He fulfilled his
vow to build a temple to the all-good and all-powerful Jupiter in the
Capitol—a vow which he made during a battle in the Sabine war—and died
after a reign of thirty-eight years.
XXI. Then Lælius said: All that you have been relating corroborates the
saying of Cato, that the constitution
410of the Roman Commonwealth is not
the work of one man, or one age; for we can clearly see what a great
progress in excellent and useful institutions was continued under each
successive king. But we are now arrived at the reign of a monarch who
appears to me to have been of all our kings he who had the greatest
foresight in matters of political government.
So it appears to me, said Scipio; for after Tarquinius Priscus comes
Servius Sulpicius, who was the first who is reported to have reigned
without an order from the people. He is supposed to have been the son of
a female slave at Tarquinii, by one of the soldiers or clients of King
Priscus; and as he was educated among the servants of this prince, and
waiting on him at table, the king soon observed the fire of his genius,
which shone forth even from his childhood, so skilful was he in all his
words and actions. Therefore, Tarquin, whose own children were then very
young, so loved Servius that he was very commonly believed to be his own
son, and he instructed him with the greatest care in all the sciences
with which he was acquainted, according to the most exact discipline of
the Greeks.
But when Tarquin had perished by the plots of the sons of Ancus, and
Servius (as I have said) had begun to reign, not by the order, but yet
with the good-will and consent, of the citizens—because, as it was
falsely reported that Priscus was recovering from his wounds, Servius,
arrayed in the royal robes, delivered judgment, freed the debtors at his
own expense, and, exhibiting the greatest affability, announced that he
delivered judgment at the command of Priscus—he did not commit himself
to the senate; but, after Priscus was buried, he consulted the people
respecting his authority, and, being authorized by them to assume the
dominion, he procured a law to be passed through the Comitia Curiata,
confirming his government.
He then, in the first place, avenged the injuries of the Etruscans by
arms. After which
318 *В *В *
XXII. *В *В * he enrolled eighteen centuries of knights of the first
order. Afterward, having created a great number of knights from the
common mass of the people, he
411divided the rest of the people into five
classes, distinguishing between the seniors and the juniors. These he so
constituted as to place the suffrages, not in the hands of the
multitude, but in the power of the men of property. And he took care to
make it a rule of ours, as it ought to be in every government, that the
greatest number should not have the greatest weight. You are well
acquainted with this institution, otherwise I would explain it to you;
but you are familiar with the whole system, and know how the centuries
of knights, with six suffrages, and the first class, comprising eighty
centuries, besides one other century which was allotted to the
artificers, on account of their utility to the State, produce
eighty-nine centuries. If to these there are added twelve centuries—for
that is the number of the centuries of the knights which
remain
319—the entire force of the State is summed up; and the
arrangement is such that the remaining and far more numerous multitude,
which is distributed through the ninety-six last centuries, is not
deprived of a right of suffrage, which would be an arrogant measure;
nor, on the other hand, permitted to exert too great a preponderance in
the government, which would be dangerous.
In this arrangement, Servius was very cautious in his choice of terms
and denominations. He called the rich
assidui, because they afforded
pecuniary succor
320 to the State. As to those whoso fortune did not
exceed 1500 pence, or those who had nothing but their labor, he called
them
proletarii classes, as if the State should expect from them a
hardy progeny
321 and population.
Even a single one of the ninety-six last centuries contained numerically
more citizens than the entire first class. Thus, no one was excluded
from his right of voting, yet the preponderance of votes was secured to
those who had the deepest stake in the welfare of the State. Moreover,
with reference to the accensi, velati, trumpeters, hornblowers,
proletarii
322 *В *В *
XXIII. *В *В * That that republic is arranged in the best manner which,
being composed in due proportions of those
412three elements, the
monarchical, the aristocratical, and the democratic, does not by
punishment irritate a fierce and savage mind. *В *В * [A similar
institution prevailed at Carthage], which was sixty-five years more
ancient than Rome, since it was founded thirty-nine years before the
first Olympiad; and that most ancient law-giver Lycurgus made nearly the
same arrangements. Thus the system of regular subordination, and this
mixture of the three principal forms of government, appear to me common
alike to us and them. But there is a peculiar advantage in our
Commonwealth, than which nothing can be more excellent, which I shall
endeavor to describe as accurately as possible, because it is of such a
character that nothing analogous can be discovered in ancient states;
for these political elements which I have noticed were so united in the
constitutions of Rome, of Sparta, and of Carthage, that they were not
counterbalanced by any modifying power. For in a state in which one man
is invested with a perpetual domination, especially of the monarchical
character, although there be a senate in it, as there was in Rome under
the kings, and in Sparta, by the laws of Lycurgus, or even where the
people exercise a sort of jurisdiction, as they used in the days of our
monarchy, the title of king must still be pre-eminent; nor can such a
state avoid being, and being called, a kingdom. And this kind of
government is especially subject to frequent revolutions, because the
fault of a single individual is sufficient to precipitate it into the
most pernicious disasters.
In itself, however, royalty is not only not a reprehensible form of
government, but I do not know whether it is not far preferable to all
other simple constitutions, if I approved of any simple constitution
whatever. But this preference applies to royalty so long only as it
maintains its appropriate character; and this character provides that
one individual’s perpetual power, and justice, and universal wisdom
should regulate the safety, equality, and tranquillity of the whole
people. But many privileges must be wanting to communities that live
under a king; and, in the first place, liberty, which does not consist
in slavery to a just master, but in slavery to no master at all
323 *В *В *
413XXIV. *В *В * [Let us now pass on to the reign of the seventh and last
king of Rome, Tarquinius Superbus.] And even this unjust and cruel
master had good fortune for his companion for some time in all his
enterprises. For he subdued all Latium; he captured Suessa Pometia, a
powerful and wealthy city, and, becoming possessed of an immense spoil
of gold and silver, he accomplished his father’s vow by the building of
the Capitol. He established colonies, and, faithful to the institutions
of those from whom he sprung, he sent magnificent presents, as tokens of
gratitude for his victories, to Apollo at Delphi.
XXV. Here begins the revolution of our political system of government,
and I must beg your attention to its natural course and progression. For
the grand point of political science, the object of our discourses, is
to know the march and the deviations of governments, that when we are
acquainted with the particular courses and inclinations of
constitutions, we may be able to restrain them from their fatal
tendencies, or to oppose adequate obstacles to their decline and fall.
For this Tarquinius Superbus, of whom I am speaking, being first of all
stained with the blood of his admirable predecessor on the throne, could
not be a man of sound conscience and mind; and as he feared himself the
severest punishment for his enormous crime, he sought his protection in
making himself feared. Then, in the glory of his victories and his
treasures, he exulted in insolent pride, and could neither regulate his
own manners nor the passions of the members of his family.
When, therefore, his eldest son had offered violence to Lucretia,
daughter of Tricipitinus and wife of Collatinus, and this chaste and
noble lady had stabbed herself to death on account of the injury she
could not survive—then a man eminent for his genius and virtue, Lucius
Brutus, dashed from his fellow-citizens this unjust yoke of odious
servitude; and though he was but a private man, he sustained the
government of the entire Commonwealth, and was the first that taught the
people in this State that no one was a private man when the preservation
of our liberties was concerned. Beneath his authority and command our
city rose against tyranny, and, stirred by the recent
414grief of the
father and relatives of Lucretia, and with the recollections of
Tarquin’s haughtiness, and the numberless crimes of himself and his
sons, they pronounced sentence of banishment against him and his
children, and the whole race of the Tarquins.
XXVI. Do you not observe, then, how the king sometimes degenerates into
the despot, and how, by the fault of one individual, a form of
government originally good is abused to the worst of purposes? Here is a
specimen of that despot over the people whom the Greeks denominate a
tyrant. For, according to them, a king is he who, like a father,
consults the interests of his people, and who preserves those whom he is
set over in the very best condition of life. This indeed is, as I have
said, an excellent form of government, yet still liable, and, as it
were, inclined, to a pernicious abuse. For as soon as a king assumes an
unjust and despotic power, he instantly becomes a tyrant, than which
nothing baser or fouler, than which no imaginable animal can be more
detestable to gods or men; for though in form a man, he surpasses the
most savage monsters in ferocious cruelty. For who can justly call him a
human being, who admits not between himself and his fellow-countrymen,
between himself and the whole human race, any communication of justice,
any association of kindness? But we shall find some fitter occasion of
speaking of the evils of tyranny when the subject itself prompts us to
declare against them who, even in a state already liberated, have
affected these despotic insolencies.
XXVII. Such is the first origin and rise of a tyrant. For this was the
name by which the Greeks choose to designate an unjust king; and by the
title king our Romans universally understand every man who exercises
over the people a perpetual and undivided domination. Thus Spurius
Cassius, and Marcus Manlius, and Spurius Mælius, are said to have wished
to seize upon the kingly power, and lately [Tiberius Gracchus incurred
the same accusation].
324 *В *В *
XXVIII. *В *В * [Lycurgus, in Sparta, formed, under the name of Elders,] a
small council consisting of twenty-eight members only; to these he
allotted the supreme legislative
415authority, while the king held the
supreme executive authority. Our Romans, emulating his example, and
translating his terms, entitled those whom he had called Elders,
Senators, which, as we have said, was done by Romulus in reference to
the elect patricians. In this constitution, however, the power, the
influence, and name of the king is still pre-eminent. You may
distribute, indeed, some show of power to the people, as Lycurgus and
Romulus did, but you inflame them, with the thirst of liberty by
allowing them even the slightest taste of its sweetness; and still their
hearts will be overcast with alarm lest their king, as often happens,
should become unjust. The prosperity of the people, therefore, can be
little better than fragile, when placed at the disposal of any one
individual, and subjected to his will and caprices.
XXIX. Thus the first example, prototype, and original of tyranny has
been discovered by us in the history of our own Roman State, religiously
founded by Romulus, without applying to the theoretical Commonwealth
which, according to Plato’s recital, Socrates was accustomed to describe
in his peripatetic dialogues. We have observed Tarquin, not by the
usurpation of any new power, but by the unjust abuse of the power which
he already possessed, overturn the whole system of our monarchical
constitution.
Let us oppose to this example of the tyrant another, a virtuous
king—wise, experienced, and well informed respecting the true interest
and dignity of the citizens—a guardian, as it were, and superintendent
of the Commonwealth; for that is a proper name for every ruler and
governor of a state. And take you care to recognize such a man when you
meet him, for he is the man who, by counsel and exertion, can best
protect the nation. And as the name of this man has not yet been often
mentioned in our discourse, and as the character of such a man must be
often alluded to in our future conversations, [I shall take an early
opportunity of describing it.]
325 *В *В *
XXX. *В *В * [Plato has chosen to suppose a territory and establishments
of citizens, whose fortunes] were precisely equal. And he has given us a
description of a city, rather to be desired than expected; and he has
made out
416not such a one as can really exist, but one in which the
principles of political affairs may be discerned. But for me, if I can
in any way accomplish it, while I adopt the same general principles as
Plato, I am seeking to reduce them to experience and practice, not in
the shadow and picture of a state, but in a real and actual
Commonwealth, of unrivalled amplitude and power; in order to be able to
point out, with the most graphic precision, the causes of every
political good and social evil.
For after Rome had flourished more than two hundred and forty years
under her kings and interreges, and after Tarquin was sent into
banishment, the Roman people conceived as much detestation of the name
of king as they had once experienced regret at the death, or rather
disappearance, of Romulus. Therefore, as in the first instance they
could hardly bear the idea of losing a king, so in the latter, after the
expulsion of Tarquin, they could not endure to hear the name of a
king.
326 *В *В *
XXXI. *В *В * Therefore, when that admirable constitution of Romulus had
lasted steadily about two hundred and forty years. *В *В * The whole of
that law was abolished. In this humor, our ancestors banished
Collatinus, in spite of his innocence, because of the suspicion that
attached to his family, and all the rest of the Tarquins, on account of
the unpopularity of their name. In the same humor, Valerius Publicola
was the first to lower the fasces before the people, when he spoke in
the assembly of the people. He also had the materials of his house
conveyed to the foot of Mount Velia, having observed that the
commencement of his edifice on the summit of this hill, where King
Tullius had once dwelt, excited the suspicions of the people.
It was the same man, who in this respect pre-eminently deserved the name
of Publicola, who carried in favor of the people the first law received
in the Comitia Centuriata, that no magistrate should sentence to death
or scourging a Roman citizen who appealed from his authority to the
people. And the pontifical books attest that the right of appeal had
existed, even against the decision of the kings. Our augural books
affirm the same thing. And the Twelve
417Tables prove, by a multitude of
laws, that there was a right of appeal from every judgment and penalty.
Besides, the historical fact that the decemviri who compiled the laws
were created with the privilege of judging without appeal, sufficiently
proves that the other magistrates had not the same power. And a consular
law, passed by Lucius Valerius Politus and Marcus Horatius Barbatus, men
justly popular for promoting union and concord, enacted that no
magistrate should thenceforth be appointed with authority to judge
without appeal; and the Portian laws, the work of three citizens of the
name of Portius, as you are aware, added nothing new to this edict but a
penal sanction.
Therefore Publicola, having promulgated this law in favor of appeal to
the people, immediately ordered the axes to be removed from the fasces,
which the lictors carried before the consuls, and the next day appointed
Spurius Lucretius for his colleague. And as the new consul was the
oldest of the two, Publicola ordered his lictors to pass over to him;
and he was the first to establish the rule, that each of the consuls
should be preceded by the lictors in alternate months, that there should
be no greater appearance of imperial insignia among the free people than
they had witnessed in the days of their kings. Thus, in my opinion, he
proved himself no ordinary man, as, by so granting the people a moderate
degree of liberty, he more easily maintained the authority of the
nobles.
Nor is it without reason that I have related to you these ancient and
almost obsolete events; but I wished to adduce my instances of men and
circumstances from illustrious persons and times, as it is to such
events that the rest of my discourse will be directed.
XXXII. At that period, then, the senate preserved the Commonwealth in
such a condition that though the people were really free, yet few acts
were passed by the people, but almost all, on the contrary, by the
authority, customs, and traditions of the senate. And over all the
consuls exercised a power—in time, indeed, only annual, but in nature
and prerogative completely royal.
The consuls maintained, with the greatest energy, that rule which so
much conduces to the power of our nobles and great men, that the acts of
the commons of the people
418shall not be binding, unless the authority of
the patricians has approved them. About the same period, and scarcely
ten years after the first consuls, we find the appointment of the
dictator in the person of Titus Lartius. And this new kind of
power—namely, the dictatorship—appears exceedingly similar to the
monarchical royalty. All his power, however, was vested in the supreme
authority of the senate, to which the people deferred; and in these
times great exploits were performed in war by brave men invested with
the supreme command, whether dictators or consuls.
XXXIII. But as the nature of things necessarily brought it to pass that
the people, once freed from its kings, should arrogate to itself more
and more authority, we observe that after a short interval of only
sixteen years, in the consulship of Postumus Cominius and Spurius
Cassius, they attained their object; an event explicable, perhaps, on no
distinct principle, but, nevertheless, in a manner independent of any
distinct principle. For recollect what I said in commencing our
discourse, that if there exists not in the State a just distribution and
subordination of rights, offices, and prerogatives, so as to give
sufficient domination to the chiefs, sufficient authority to the counsel
of the senators, and sufficient liberty to the people, this form of the
government cannot be durable.
For when the excessive debts of the citizens had thrown the State into
disorder, the people first retired to Mount Sacer, and next occupied
Mount Aventine. And even the rigid discipline of Lycurgus could not
maintain those restraints in the case of the Greeks. For in Sparta
itself, under the reign of Theopompus, the five magistrates whom they
term Ephori, and in Crete ten whom they entitle Cosmi, were established
in opposition to the royal power, just as tribunes were added among us
to counterbalance the consular authority.
XXXIV. There might have been a method, indeed, by which our ancestors
could have been relieved from the pressure of debt, a method with which
Solon the Athenian, who lived at no very distant period before, was
acquainted, and which our senate did not neglect when, in the
indignation which the odious avarice of one individual excited,
419all the
bonds of the citizens were cancelled, and the right of arrest for a
while suspended. In the same way, when the plebeians were oppressed by
the weight of the expenses occasioned by public misfortunes, a cure and
remedy were sought for the sake of public security. The senate, however,
having forgotten their former decision, gave an advantage to the
democracy; for, by the creation of two tribunes to appease the sedition
of the people, the power and authority of the senate were diminished;
which, however, still remained dignified and august, inasmuch as it was
still composed of the wisest and bravest men, who protected their
country both with their arms and with their counsels; whose authority
was exceedingly strong and flourishing, because in honor they were as
much before their fellow-citizens as they were inferior in
luxuriousness, and, as a general rule, not superior to them in wealth.
And their public virtues were the more agreeable to the people, because
even in private matters they were ready to serve every citizen, by their
exertions, their counsels, and their liberality.
XXXV. Such was the situation of the Commonwealth when the quæstor
impeached Spurius Cassius of being so much emboldened by the excessive
favor of the people as to endeavor to make himself master of monarchical
power. And, as you have heard, his own father, having said that he had
found that his son was really guilty of this crime, condemned him to
death at the instance of the people. About fifty-four years after the
first consulate, Spurius Tarpeius and Aulus Aternius very much gratified
the people by proposing, in the Comitia Centuriata, the substitution of
fines instead of corporal punishments. Twenty years afterward, Lucius
Papirius and Publius Pinarius, the censors, having by a strict levy of
fines confiscated to the State the entire flocks and herds of many
private individuals, a light tax on the cattle was substituted for the
law of fines in the consulship of Caius Julius and Publius Papirius.
XXXVI. But, some years previous to this, at a period when the senate
possessed the supreme influence, and the people were submissive and
obedient, a new system was adopted. At that time both the consuls and
tribunes of
420the people abdicated their magistracies, and the decemviri
were appointed, who were invested with great authority, from which there
was no appeal whatever, so as to exercise the chief domination, and to
compile the laws. After having composed, with much wisdom and equity,
the Ten Tables of laws, they nominated as their successors in the
ensuing year other decemviri, whose good faith and justice do not
deserve equal praise. One member of this college, however, merits our
highest commendation. I allude to Caius Julius, who declared respecting
the nobleman Lucius Sestius, in whose chamber a dead body had been
exhumed under his own eyes, that though as decemvir he held the highest
power without appeal, he still required bail, because he was unwilling
to neglect that admirable law which permitted no court but the Comitia
Centuriata to pronounce final sentence on the life of a Roman citizen.
XXXVII. A third year followed under the authority of the same decemvirs,
and still they were not disposed to appoint their successors. In a
situation of the Commonwealth like this, which, as I have often
repeated, could not be durable, because it had not an equal operation
with respect to all the ranks of the citizens, the whole public power
was lodged in the hands of the chiefs and decemvirs of the highest
nobility, without the counterbalancing authority of the tribunes of the
people, without the sanction of any other magistracies, and without
appeal to the people in the case of a sentence of death or scourging.
Thus, out of the injustice of these men, there was suddenly produced a
great revolution, which changed the entire condition of the government,
or they added two tables of very tyrannical laws, and though matrimonial
alliances had always been permitted, even with foreigners, they forbade,
by the most abominable and inhuman edict, that any marriages should take
place between the nobles and the commons—an order which was afterward
abrogated by the decree of Canuleius. Besides, they introduced into all
their political measures corruption, cruelty, and avarice. And indeed
the story is well known, and celebrated in many literary compositions,
that a certain Decimus Virginius was obliged, on account of the
libidinous violence of one of these decemvirs, to stab his virgin
daughter
421in the midst of the forum. Then, when he in his desperation
had fled to the Roman army which was encamped on Mount Algidum, the
soldiers abandoned the war in which they were engaged, and took
possession of the Sacred Mount, as they had done before on a similar
occasion, and next invested Mount Aventine in their arms.
327 Our
ancestors knew how to prove most thoroughly, and to retain most wisely.
*В *В *
XXXVIII. And when Scipio had spoken in this manner, and all his friends
were awaiting in silence the rest of his discourse, then said Tubero:
Since these men who are older than I, my Scipio, make no fresh demands
on you, I shall take the liberty to tell you what I particularly wish
you would explain in your subsequent remarks.
Do so, said Scipio, and I shall be glad to hear.
Then Tubero said: You appear to me to have spoken a panegyric on our
Commonwealth of Rome exclusively, though Lælius requested your views not
only of the government of our own State, but of the policy of states in
general. I have not, therefore, yet sufficiently learned from your
discourse, with respect to that mixed form of government you most
approve, by what discipline, moral and legal, we may be best able to
establish and maintain it.
XXXIX. Africanus replied: I think that we shall soon find an occasion
better adapted to the discussion you have proposed, respecting the
constitution and conservatism of states. As to the best form of
government, I think on this point I have sufficiently answered the
question of Lælius. For in answering him, I, in the first place,
specifically noticed the three simple forms of government—monarchy,
aristocracy, and democracy; and the three vicious constitutions contrary
to them, into which they often degenerate; and I said that none of these
forms, taken separately, was absolutely good; but I described as
preferable to either of them that mixed government which is composed of
a proper amalgamation of these simple ingredients. If I have since
depicted our own Roman constitution as an example, it was not in order
to define the very best form of government, for that may be understood
without an example; but I wished, in the exhibition of a
422mighty
commonwealth actually in existence, to render distinct and visible what
reason and discourse would vainly attempt to display without the
assistance of experimental illustration. Yet, if you still require me to
describe the best form of government, independent of all particular
examples, we must consult that exactly proportioned and graduated image
of government which nature herself presents to her investigators. Since
you *В *В * this model of a city and people
328 *В *В *
XL. *В *В * which I also am searching for, and which I am anxious to
arrive at.
Lælius. You mean the model that would be approved by the truly
accomplished politician?
Scipio. The same.
Lælius. You have plenty of fair patterns even now before you, if you
would but begin with yourself.
Then Scipio said: I wish I could find even one such, even in the entire
senate. For he is really a wise politician who, as we have often seen in
Africa, while seated on a huge and unsightly elephant, can guide and
rule the monster, and turn him whichever way he likes by a slight
admonition, without any actual exertion.
Lælius. I recollect, and when I was your lieutenant I often saw, one
of these drivers.
Scipio. Thus an Indian or Carthaginian regulates one of these huge
animals, and renders him docile and familiar with human manners. But the
genius which resides in the mind of man, by whatever name it may be
called, is required to rein and tame a monster far more multiform and
intractable, whenever it can accomplish it, which indeed is seldom. It
is necessary to hold in with a strong hand that ferocious
329 *В *В *
XLI. *В *В * [beast, denominated the mob, which thirsts after blood] to
such a degree that it can scarcely be sated with the most hideous
massacres of men. *В *В *
But to a man who is greedy, and grasping, and lustful, and fond of
wallowing in voluptuousness.
423The fourth kind of anxiety is that which is prone to mourning and
melancholy, and which is constantly worrying itself.
XLII. *В *В * can be said.
Then Lælius said: I now see the sort of politician you require, on whom
you would impose the office and task of government, which is what I
wished to understand.
He must be an almost unique specimen, said Africanus, for the task which
I set him comprises all others. He must never cease from cultivating and
studying himself, that he may excite others to imitate him, and become,
through the splendor of his talents and enterprises, a living mirror to
his countrymen. For as in flutes and harps, and in all vocal
performances, a certain unison and harmony must be preserved amidst the
distinctive tones, which cannot be broken or violated without offending
experienced ears; and as this concord and delicious harmony is produced
by the exact gradation and modulation of dissimilar notes; even so, by
means of the just apportionment of the highest, middle, and lower
classes, the State is maintained in concord and peace by the harmonic
subordination of its discordant elements: and thus, that which is by
musicians called harmony in song answers and corresponds to what we call
concord in the State—concord, the strongest and loveliest bond of
security in every commonwealth, being always accompanied by justice and
equity.
XLIII. And after this, when Scipio had discussed with considerable
breadth of principle and felicity of illustration the great advantage
that justice is to a state, and the great injury which would arise if it
were
424wanting, Pilus, one of those who were present at the discussion,
took up the matter and demanded that this question should be argued more
carefully, and that something more should be said about justice, on
account of a sentiment that was now obtaining among people in general,
that political affairs could not be wholly carried on without some
disregard of justice.
XLIV. *В *В * to be full of justice.
Then Scipio replied: I certainly think so. And I declare to you that I
consider that all I have spoken respecting the government of the State
is worth nothing, and that it will be useless to proceed further, unless
I can prove that it is a false assertion that political business cannot
be conducted without injustice and corruption; and, on the other hand,
establish as a most indisputable fact that without the strictest justice
no government whatever can last long.
But, with your permission, we have had discussion enough for the day.
The rest—and much remains for our consideration—we will defer till
to-morrow. When they had all agreed to this, the debate of the day was
closed.
INTRODUCTION TO THE THIRD BOOK,
BY THE ORIGINAL TRANSLATOR.
Cicero here enters on the grand question of Political Justice, and
endeavors to evince throughout the absolute verity of that inestimable
proverb, “Honesty is the best policy,” in all public as well as in all
private affairs. St. Augustine, in his City of God, has given the
following analysis of this magnificent disquisition:
“In the third book of Cicero’s Commonwealth” (says he) “the question of
Political Justice is most earnestly discussed. Philus is appointed to
support, as well as he can, the sophistical arguments of those who think
that political government cannot be carried on without the aid of
injustice and chicanery. He denies holding any such opinion himself;
yet, in order to exhibit the truth more vividly through the force of
contrast, he pleads with the utmost ingenuity the cause of injustice
against justice; and endeavors to show, by plausible examples and
specious dialectics, that injustice is as useful to a statesman as
justice would be injurious. Then Lælius, at the general request, takes
up the plea for justice, and maintains with all his eloquence that
nothing could be so ruinous to states as injustice and dishonesty, and
that 425without a supreme justice, no political government could expect a
long duration. This point being sufficiently proved, Scipio returns to
the principal discussion. He reproduces and enforces the short
definition that he had given of a commonwealth—that it consisted in the
welfare of the entire people, by which word �people’ he does not mean
the mob, but the community, bound together by the sense of common rights
and mutual benefits. He notices how important such just definitions are
in all debates whatever, and draws this conclusion from the preceding
arguments—that the Commonwealth is the common welfare whenever it is
swayed with justice and wisdom, whether it be subordinated to a king, an
aristocracy, or a democracy. But if the king be unjust, and so becomes a
tyrant; and the aristocracy unjust, which makes them a faction; or the
democrats unjust, and so degenerate into revolutionists and
destructives—then not only the Commonwealth is corrupted, but in fact
annihilated. For it can be no longer the common welfare when a tyrant or
a faction abuse it; and the people itself is no longer the people when
it becomes unjust, since it is no longer a community associated by a
sense of right and utility, according to the definition.”—Aug. Civ.
Dei. 3-21.
This book is of the utmost importance to statesmen, as it serves to
neutralize the sophistries of Machiavelli, which are still repeated in
many cabinets.
BOOK III.
I. *В *В *
331 Cicero, in the third book of his treatise On a
Commonwealth, says that nature has treated man less like a mother than a
step-dame, for she has cast him into mortal life with a body naked,
fragile, and infirm, and with a mind agitated by troubles, depressed by
fears, broken by labors, and exposed to passions. In this mind, however,
there lies hidden, and, as it were, buried, a certain divine spark of
genius and intellect.
Though man is born a frail and powerless being, nevertheless he is safe
from all animals destitute of voice; and at the same time those other
animals of greater strength, although they bravely endure the violence
of weather, cannot be safe from man. And the result is, that reason does
more for man than nature does for brutes; since, in the latter, neither
the greatness of their strength nor the firmness of their bodies can
save them from being oppressed by us, and made subject to our power. *В *В *
426Plato returned thanks to nature that he had been born a man.
II. *В *В * aiding our slowness by carriages, and when it had taught men
to utter the elementary and confused sounds of unpolished expression,
articulated and distinguished them into their proper classes, and, as
their appropriate signs, attached certain words to certain things, and
thus associated, by the most delightful bond of speech, the once divided
races of men.
And by a similar intelligence, the inflections of the voice, which
appeared infinite, are, by the discovery of a few alphabetic characters,
all designated and expressed; by which we maintain converse with our
absent friends, by which also indications of our wishes and monuments of
past events are preserved. Then came the use of numbers—a thing
necessary to human life, and at the same time immutable and eternal; a
science which first urged us to raise our views to heaven, and not gaze
without an object on the motions of the stars, and the distribution of
days and nights.
III. *В *В *
332 [Then appeared the sages of philosophy], whose minds
took a higher flight, and who were able to conceive and to execute
designs worthy of the gifts of the Gods. Wherefore let those men who
have left us sublime essays on the principles of living be regarded as
great men—which indeed they are—as learned men, as masters of truth
and virtue; provided that these principles of civil government, this
system of governing people, whether it be a thing discovered by men who
have lived amidst a variety of political events, or one discussed amidst
their opportunities of literary tranquillity, is remembered to be, as
indeed it is, a thing by no means to be despised, being one which causes
in first-rate minds, as we not unfrequently see, an incredible and
almost divine virtue. And when to these high faculties of soul, received
from nature and expanded by social institutions, a politician adds
learning and extensive information concerning things in general, like
those illustrious personages who conduct the dialogue in the present
treatise, none will refuse to confess the superiority of such persons to
all others; for, in fact, what
427can be more admirable than the study and
practice of the grand affairs of state, united to a literary taste and a
familiarity with the liberal arts? or what can we imagine more perfect
than a Scipio, a Lælius, or a Philus, who, not to omit anything which
belonged to the most perfect excellence of the greatest men, joined to
the examples of our ancestors and the traditions of our countrymen the
foreign philosophy of Socrates?
Wherefore he who had both the desire and the power to acquaint himself
thoroughly both with the customs and the learning of his ancestors
appears to me to have attained to the very highest glory and honor. But
if we cannot combine both, and are compelled to select one of these two
paths to wisdom—though to some people the tranquil life spent in the
research of literature and arts may appear to be the most happy and
delectable—yet, doubtless, the science of politics is more laudable and
illustrious, for in this political field of exertion our greatest men
have reaped their honors, like the invincible Curius,
Whom neither gold nor iron could subdue.
IV. *В *В *
333 that wisdom existed still. There existed this general
difference between these two classes, that among the one the development
of the principles of nature is the subject of their study and eloquence,
and among the other national laws and institutions form the principal
topics of investigation.
In honor of our country, we may assert that she has produced within
herself a great number, I will not say of sages (since philosophy is so
jealous of this name), but of men worthy of the highest celebrity,
because by them the precepts and discoveries of the sages have been
carried out into actual practice. And, moreover, though there have
existed, and still do exist, many great and glorious empires, yet since
the noblest masterpiece of genius in the world is the establishment of a
state and commonwealth which shall be a lasting one, even if we reckon
but a single legislator for each empire, the number of these excellent
men will appear very numerous. To be convinced of this, we have only to
turn our eyes on any nation of Italy, Latium, the
428Sabines, the
Volscians, the Samnites, or the Etrurians, and then direct our attention
to that mighty nation of the Greeks, and then to the Assyrians,
Persians, and Carthaginians, and
334 *В *В *
V. *В *В * [Scipio and his friends having again assembled, Scipio spoke as
follows: In our last conversation, I promised to prove that honesty is
the best policy in all states and commonwealths whatsoever. But if I am
to plead in favor of strict honesty and justice in all public affairs,
no less than in private, I must request Philus, or some one else, to
take up the advocacy of the other side; the truth will then become more
manifest, from the collision of opposite arguments, as we see every day
exemplified at the Bar.]
And Philus replied: In good truth, you have allotted me a very
creditable cause when you wish me to undertake the defence of vice.
Perhaps, said Lælius, you are afraid, lest, in reproducing the ordinary
objections made to justice in politics, you should seem to express your
own sentiments; though you are universally respected as an almost unique
example of the ancient probity and good faith; nor is it unknown how
familiar you are with the lawyer-like habit of disputing on both sides
of a question, because you think that this is the best way of getting at
the truth.
And Philus said: Very well; I obey you, and wilfully, with my eyes open,
I will undertake this dirty business; because, since those who seek for
gold do not flinch at the sight of the mud, so we who are searching for
justice, which is far more precious than gold, are bound to shrink from
no annoyance. And I wish, as I am about to make use of the antagonist
arguments of a foreigner, I might also employ a foreign language. The
pleas, therefore, now to be urged by Lucius Furius Philus are those
[once employed by] the Greek Carneades, a man who was accustomed to
express whatever [served his turn].
335 *В *В *
336429Let it be understood,
therefore, that I by no means express my own sentiments, but those of
Carneades, in order that you may refute this philosopher, who was wont
to turn the best causes into joke, through the mere wantonness of wit.
VI. He was a philosopher of the Academic School; and if any one is
ignorant of his great power, and eloquence, and acuteness in
arguing, he may learn it from the mention made of him by Cicero or
by Lucilius, when Neptune, discoursing on a very difficult subject,
declares that it cannot be explained, not even if hell were to
restore Carneades himself for the purpose. This philosopher, having
been sent by the Athenians to Rome as an ambassador, discussed the
subject of justice very amply in the hearing of Galba and Cato the
Censor, who were the greatest orators of the day. And the next day
he overturned all his arguments by others of a contrary tendency,
and disparaged justice, which the day before he had extolled;
speaking not indeed with the gravity of a philosopher whose wisdom
ought to be steady, and whose opinions unchangeable, but in a kind
of rhetorical exercise of arguing on each side—a practice which he
was accustomed to adopt, in order to be able to refute others who
were asserting anything. The arguments by which he disparaged
justice are mentioned by Lucius Furius in Cicero; I suppose, since
he was discussing the Commonwealth, in order to introduce a defence
and panegyric of that quality without which he did not think a
commonwealth could be administered. But Carneades, in order to
refute Aristotle and Plato, the advocates of justice, collected in
his first argument everything that was in the habit of being
advanced on behalf of justice, in order afterward to be able to
overturn it, as he did.
VII. Many philosophers indeed, and especially Plato and Aristotle,
have spoken a great deal of justice, inculcating that virtue, and
extolling it with the highest praise, as giving to every one what
belongs to him, as preserving equity in all things, and urging that
while the other virtues are, as it were, silent and shut up,
justice is the only one which
430is not absorbed in considerations of
self-interest, and which is not secret, but finds its whole field
for exercise out-of-doors, and is desirous of doing good and
serving as many people as possible; as if, forsooth, justice ought
to exist in judges only, and in men invested with a certain
authority, and not in every one! But there is no one, not even a
man of the lowest class, or a beggar, who is destitute of
opportunities of displaying justice. But because these philosophers
knew not what its essence was, or whence it proceeded, or what its
employment was, they attributed that first of all virtues, which is
the common good of all men, to a few only, and asserted that it
aimed at no advantage of its own, but was anxious only for that of
others. So it was well that Carneades, a man of the greatest genius
and acuteness, refuted their assertions, and overthrew that justice
which had no firm foundation; not because he thought justice itself
deserving of blame, but in order to show that those its defenders
had brought forward no trustworthy or strong arguments in its
behalf.
Justice looks out-of-doors, and is prominent and conspicuous in its
whole essence.
Which virtue, beyond all others, wholly devotes and dedicates
itself to the advantage of others.
VIII. *В *В * Both to discover and maintain. While the other, Aristotle,
has filled four large volumes with a discussion on abstract justice. For
I did not expect anything grand or magnificent from Chrysippus, who,
after his usual fashion, examines everything rather by the signification
of words than the reality of things. But it was surely worthy of those
heroes of philosophy to ennoble by their genius a virtue so eminently
beneficent and liberal, which everywhere exalts the social interests
above the selfish, and teaches us to love others rather than ourselves.
It was worthy of their genius, we say, to elevate this virtue to a
divine throne, not far from that of Wisdom. And certainly they neither
wanted the will to accomplish this (for what else could be the cause of
their writing on the subject, or what could have been their design?) nor
the genius, in which they excelled all men. But the weakness of their
cause was too great for either their intention or their eloquence to
make it popular. In fact, this justice on which we reason is a civil
right, but no natural one; for if it were natural and universal, then
justice and injustice would be recognized similarly by all men, just as
the heat and cold, sweetness and bitterness.
IX. Now, if any one, carried in that chariot of winged serpents of which
the poet Pacuvius makes mention, could
431take his flight over all nations
and cities, and accurately observe their proceedings, he would see that
the sense of justice and right varies in different regions. In the first
place, he would behold among the unchangeable people of Egypt, which
preserves in its archives the memory of so many ages and events, a bull
adored as a Deity, under the name of Apis, and a multitude of other
monsters, and all kinds of animals admitted by the same nation into the
number of the Gods.
In the next place, he would see in Greece, as among ourselves,
magnificent temples consecrated by images in human form, which the
Persians regarded as impious; and it is affirmed that the sole motive of
Xerxes for commanding the conflagration of the Athenian temples was the
belief that it was a superstitious sacrilege to keep confined within
narrow walls the Gods, whose proper home was the entire universe. But
afterward Philip, in his hostile projects against the Persians, and
Alexander, who carried them into execution, alleged this plea for war,
that they were desirous to avenge the temples of Greece, which the
Greeks had thought proper never to rebuild, that this monument of the
impiety of the Persians might always remain before the eyes of their
posterity.
How many—such as the inhabitants of Taurica along the Euxine Sea; as
the King of Egypt, Busiris; as the Gauls and the Carthaginians—have
thought it exceedingly pious and agreeable to the Gods to sacrifice men!
And, besides, the customs of life are so various that the Cretans and
Ætolians regard robbery as honorable. And the Lacedæmonians say that
their territory extends to all places which they can touch with a lance.
The Athenians had a custom of swearing, by a public proclamation, that
all the lands which produced olives and corn were their own. The Gauls
consider it a base employment to raise corn by agricultural labor, and
go with arms in their hands, and mow down the harvests of neighboring
peoples. But we ourselves, the most equitable of all nations, who, in
order to raise the value of our vines and olives, do not permit the
races beyond the Alps to cultivate either vineyards or oliveyards, are
said in this matter to act with prudence, but not with justice. You see,
then, that wisdom
432and policy are not always the same as equity. And
Lycurgus, that famous inventor of a most admirable jurisprudence and
most wholesome laws, gave the lands of the rich to be cultivated by the
common people, who were reduced to slavery.
X. If I were to describe the diverse kinds of laws, institutions,
manners, and customs, not only as they vary in the numerous nations, but
as they vary likewise in single cities—in this one of ours, for
example—I could prove that they have had a thousand revolutions. For
instance, that eminent expositor of our laws who sits in the present
company—I mean Manilius—if you were to consult him relative to the
legacies and inheritances of women, he would tell you that the present
law is quite different from that he was accustomed to plead in his
youth, before the Voconian enactment came into force—an edict which was
passed in favor of the interests of the men, but which is evidently full
of injustice with regard to women. For why should a woman be disabled
from inheriting property? Why can a vestal virgin become an heir, while
her mother cannot? And why, admitting that it is necessary to set some
limit to the wealth of women, should Crassus’s daughter, if she be his
only child, inherit thousands without offending the law, while my
daughter can only receive a small share in a bequest.
337 *В *В *
XI. *В *В * [If this justice were natural, innate, and universal, all men
would admit the same] law and right, and the same men would not enact
different laws at different times. If a just man and a virtuous man is
bound to obey the laws, I ask, what laws do you mean? Do you intend all
the laws indifferently? But neither does virtue permit this inconstancy
in moral obligation, nor is such a variation compatible with natural
conscience. The laws are, therefore, based not on our sense of justice,
but on our fear of punishment. There is, therefore, no natural justice;
and hence it follows that men cannot be just by nature.
Are men, then, to say that variations indeed do exist in the laws, but
that men who are virtuous through natural conscience follow that which
is really justice, and not a mere semblance and disguise, and that it is
the distinguishing
433characteristic of the truly just and virtuous man to
render every one his due rights? Are we, then, to attribute the first of
these characteristics to animals? For not only men of moderate
abilities, but even first-rate sages and philosophers, as Pythagoras and
Empedocles, declare that all kinds of living creatures have a right to
the same justice. They declare that inexpiable penalties impend over
those who have done violence to any animal whatsoever. It is, therefore,
a crime to injure an animal, and the perpetrator of such crime
338 *В *В *
XII. For when he
339 inquired of a pirate by what right he dared
to infest the sea with his little brigantine: “By the same right,”
he replied, “which is your warrant for conquering the world.” * * *
Wisdom and prudence instruct us by all means to increase our power,
riches, and estates. For by what means could this same Alexander, that
illustrious general, who extended his empire over all Asia, without
violating the property of other men, have acquired such universal
dominion, enjoyed so many pleasures, such great power, and reigned
without bound or limit?
But justice commands us to have mercy upon all men, to consult the
interests of the whole human race, to give to every one his due, and
injure no sacred, public, or foreign rights, and to forbear touching
what does not belong to us. What is the result, then? If you obey the
dictates of wisdom, then wealth, power, riches, honors, provinces, and
kingdoms, from all classes, peoples, and nations, are to be aimed at.
However, as we are discussing public matters, those examples are more
illustrious which refer to what is done publicly. And since the question
between justice and policy applies equally to private and public
affairs, I think it well to speak of the wisdom of the people. I will
not, however, mention other nations, but come at once to our own Roman
people, whom Africanus, in his discourse yesterday, traced from the
cradle, and whose empire now embraces the whole world. Justice is
340 *В *В *
434XIII. How far utility is at variance with justice we may learn from
the Roman people itself, which, declaring war by means of the
fecials, and committing injustice with all legal formality, always
coveting and laying violent hands on the property of others,
acquired the possession of the whole world.
What is the advantage of one’s own country but the disadvantage of
another state or nation, by extending one’s dominions by
territories evidently wrested from others, increasing one’s power,
improving one’s revenues, etc.? Therefore, whoever has obtained
these advantages for his country—that is to say, whoever has
overthrown cities, subdued nations, and by these means filled the
treasury with money, taken lands, and enriched his
fellow-citizens—such a man is extolled to the skies; is believed
to be endowed with consummate and perfect virtue; and this mistake
is fallen into not only by the populace and the ignorant, but by
philosophers, who even give rules for injustice.
XIV. *В *В * For all those who have the right of life and death over the
people are in fact tyrants; but they prefer being called by the title of
king, which belongs to the all-good Jupiter. But when certain men, by
favor of wealth, birth, or any other means, get possession of the entire
government, it is a faction; but they choose to denominate themselves an
aristocracy. If the people gets the upper hand, and rules everything
after its capricious will, they call it liberty, but it is in fact
license. And when every man is a guard upon his neighbor, and every
class is a guard upon every other class, then because no one trusts in
his own strength, a kind of compact is formed between the great and the
little, from whence arises that mixed kind of government which Scipio
has been commending. Thus justice, according to these facts, is not the
daughter of nature or conscience, but of human imbecility. For when it
becomes necessary to choose between these three predicaments, either to
do wrong without retribution, or to do wrong with retribution, or to do
no wrong at all, it is best to do wrong with impunity; next, neither to
do wrong nor to suffer for it; but nothing is more wretched than to
struggle incessantly between the wrong we inflict and that we receive.
Therefore, he who attains to that first end
341 *В *В *
XV. This was the sum of the argument of Carneades: that men had
established laws among themselves from considerations of advantage,
435varying them according to their different customs, and altering
them often so as to adapt them to the times; but that there was no
such thing as natural law; that all men and all other animals are
led to their own advantage by the guidance of nature; that there is
no such thing as justice, or, if there be, that it is extreme
folly, since a man would injure himself while consulting the
interests of others. And he added these arguments, that all nations
who were flourishing and dominant, and even the Romans themselves,
who were the masters of the whole world, if they wished to be
just—that is to say, if they restored all that belonged to
others—would have to return to their cottages, and to lie down in
want and misery.
Except, perhaps, of the Arcadians and Athenians, who, I presume,
dreading that this great act of retribution might one day arrive,
pretend that they were sprung from the earth, like so many field-mice.
XVI. In reply to these statements, the following arguments are often
adduced by those who are not unskilful in discussions, and who, in this
question, have all the greater weight of authority, because, when we
inquire, Who is a good man?—understanding by that term a frank and
single-minded man—we have little need of captious casuists, quibblers,
and slanderers. For those men assert that the wise man does not seek
virtue because of the personal gratification which the practice of
justice and beneficence procures him, but rather because the life of the
good man is free from fear, care, solicitude, and peril; while, on the
other hand, the wicked always feel in their souls a certain suspicion,
and always behold before their eyes images of judgment and punishment.
Do not you think, therefore, that there is any benefit, or that there is
any advantage which can be procured by injustice, precious enough to
counterbalance the constant pressure of remorse, and the haunting
consciousness that retribution awaits the sinner, and hangs over his
devoted head.
342 *В *В *
XVII. [Our philosophers, therefore, put a case. Suppose, say they, two
men, one of whom is an excellent and admirable person, of high honor and
remarkable integrity; the latter is distinguished by nothing but his
vice and audacity. And suppose that their city has so mistaken their
characters as to imagine the good man to be a scandalous, impious, and
audacious criminal, and to esteem the wicked
436man, on the contrary, as a
pattern of probity and fidelity. On account of this error of their
fellow-citizens, the good man is arrested and tormented, his hands are
cut off, his eyes are plucked out, he is condemned, bound, burned,
exterminated, reduced to want, and to the last appears to all men to be
most deservedly the most miserable of men. On the other hand, the
flagitious wretch is exalted, worshipped, loved by all, and honors,
offices, riches, and emoluments are all conferred on him, and he shall
be reckoned by his fellow-citizens the best and worthiest of mortals,
and in the highest degree deserving of all manner of prosperity. Yet,
for all this, who is so mad as to doubt which of these two men he would
rather be?
XVIII. What happens among individuals happens also among nations. There
is no state so absurd and ridiculous as not to prefer unjust dominion to
just subordination. I need not go far for examples. During my own
consulship, when you were my fellow-counsellors, we consulted respecting
the treaty of Numantia. No one was ignorant that Quintus Pompey had
signed a treaty, and that Mancinus had done the same. The latter, being
a virtuous man, supported the proposition which I laid before the
people, after the decree of the senate. The former, on the other side,
opposed it vehemently. If modesty, probity, or faith had been regarded,
Mancinus would have carried his point; but in reason, counsel, and
prudence, Pompey surpassed him. Whether
343 *В *В *
XIX. If a man should have a faithless slave, or an unwholesome house,
with whose defect he alone was acquainted, and he advertised them for
sale, would he state the fact that his servant was infected with
knavery, and his house with malaria, or would he conceal these
objections from the buyer? If he stated those facts, he would be honest,
no doubt, because he would deceive nobody; but still he would be thought
a fool, because he would either get very little for his property, or
else fail to sell it at all. By concealing these defects, on the other
hand, he will be called a shrewd man—as one who has taken care of his
own interest; but he will be a rogue, notwithstanding, because he will
be deceiving his neighbors. Again,
437let us suppose that one man meets
another, who sells gold and silver, conceiving them to be copper or
lead; shall he hold his peace that he may make a capital bargain, or
correct the mistake, and purchase at a fair rate? He would evidently be
a fool in the world’s opinion if he preferred the latter.
XX. It is justice, beyond all question, neither to commit murder nor
robbery. What, then, would your just man do, if, in a case of shipwreck,
he saw a weaker man than himself get possession of a plank? Would he not
thrust him off, get hold of the timber himself, and escape by his
exertions, especially as no human witness could be present in the
mid-sea? If he acted like a wise man of the world, he would certainly do
so, for to act in any other way would cost him his life. If, on the
other hand, he prefers death to inflicting unjustifiable injury on his
neighbor, he will be an eminently honorable and just man, but not the
less a fool, because he saved another’s life at the expense of his own.
Again, if in case of a defeat and rout, when the enemy were pressing in
the rear, this just man should find a wounded comrade mounted on a
horse, shall he respect his right at the risk of being killed himself,
or shall he fling him from the horse in order to preserve his own life
from the pursuers? If he does so, he is a wise man, but at the same time
a wicked one; if he does not, he is admirably just, but at the same time
stupid.
XXI.
Scipio. I might reply at great length to these sophistical
objections of Philus, if it were not, my Lælius, that all our friends
are no less anxious than myself to hear you take a leading part in the
present debate, especially as you promised yesterday that you would
plead at large on my side of the argument. If you cannot spare time for
this, at any rate do not desert us; we all ask it of you.
Lælius. This Carneades ought not to be even listened to by our young
men. I think all the while that I am hearing him that he must be a very
impure person; if he be not, as I would fain believe, his discourse is
not less pernicious.
XXII.
344 True law is right reason conformable to nature,
438universal,
unchangeable, eternal, whose commands urge us to duty, and whose
prohibitions restrain us from evil. Whether it enjoins or forbids, the
good respect its injunctions, and the wicked treat them with
indifference. This law cannot be contradicted by any other law, and is
not liable either to derogation or abrogation. Neither the senate nor
the people can give us any dispensation for not obeying this universal
law of justice. It needs no other expositor and interpreter than our own
conscience. It is not one thing at Rome, and another at Athens; one
thing to-day, and another to-morrow; but in all times and nations this
universal law must forever reign, eternal and imperishable. It is the
sovereign master and emperor of all beings. God himself is its author,
its promulgator, its enforcer. And he who does not obey it flies from
himself, and does violence to the very nature of man. And by so doing he
will endure the severest penalties even if he avoid the other evils
which are usually accounted punishments.
XXIII. I am aware that in the third book of Cicero’s treatise on
the Commonwealth (unless I am mistaken) it is argued that no war is
ever undertaken by a well-regulated commonwealth unless it be one
either for the sake of keeping faith, or for safety; and what he
means by a war for safety, and what safety he wishes us to
understand, he points out in another passage, where he says, “But
private men often escape from these penalties, which even the most
stupid persons feel—want, exile, imprisonment, and stripes—by
embracing the opportunity of a speedy death; but to states death
itself is a penalty, though it appears to deliver individuals from
punishment. For a state ought to be established so as to be
eternal: therefore, there is no natural decease for a state, as
there is for a man, in whose case death is not only inevitable, but
often even desirable; but when a state is put an end to, it is
destroyed, extinguished. It is in some degree, to compare small
things with great, as if this whole world were to perish and fall
to pieces.”
In his treatise on the Commonwealth, Cicero says those wars are
unjust which are undertaken without reason. Again, after a few
sentences, he adds, No war is considered just unless it be formally
announced and declared, and unless it be to obtain restitution of
what has been taken away.
But our nation, by defending its allies, has now become the master
of all the whole world.
XXIV. Also, in that same treatise on the Commonwealth, he argues
most strenuously and vigorously in the cause of justice against
injustice. And since, when a little time before the part of
injustice was upheld against justice, and the doctrine was urged
that a republic could not
439prosper and flourish except by
injustice, this was put forward as the strongest argument, that it
was unjust for men to serve other men as their masters; but that
unless a dominant state, such as a great republic, acted on this
injustice, it could not govern its provinces; answer was made on
behalf of justice, that it was just that it should be so, because
slavery is advantageous to such men, and their interests are
consulted by a right course of conduct—that is, by the license of
doing injury being taken from the wicked—and they will fare better
when subjugated, because when not subjugated they fared worse: and
to confirm this reasoning, a noble instance, taken, as it were,
from nature, was added, and it was said, Why, then, does God govern
man, and why does the mind govern the body, and reason govern lust,
and the other vicious parts of the mind?
XXV. Hear what Tully says more plainly still in the third book of
his treatise on the Commonwealth, when discussing the reasons for
government. Do we not, says he, see that nature herself has given
the power of dominion to everything that is best, to the extreme
advantage of what is subjected to it? Why, then, does God govern
man, and why does the mind govern the body, and reason govern lust
and passion and the other vicious parts of the same mind? Listen
thus far; for presently he adds, But still there are
dissimilarities to be recognized in governing and in obeying. For
as the mind is said to govern the body, and also to govern lust,
still it governs the body as a king governs his subjects, or a
parent his children; but it governs lust as a master governs his
slaves, because it restrains and breaks it. The authority of kings,
of generals, of magistrates, of fathers, and of nations, rules
their subjects and allies as the mind rules bodies; but masters
control their slaves, as the best part of the mind—that is to say,
wisdom—controls the vicious and weak parts of itself, such as
lust, passion, and the other perturbations.
For there is a kind of unjust slavery when those belong to some one
else who might be their own masters; but when those are slaves who
cannot govern themselves, there is no injury done.
XXVI. If, says Carneades, you were to know that an asp was lying
hidden anywhere, and that some one who did not know it was going to
sit upon it, whose death would be a gain to you, you would act
wickedly if you did not warn him not to sit down. Still, you would
not be liable to punishment; for who could prove that you had
known? But we are bringing forward too many instances; for it is
plain that unless equity, good faith, and justice proceed from
nature, and if all these things are referred to interest, a good
man cannot be found. And on these topics a great deal is said by
Lælius in our treatise on the Republic.
If, as we are reminded by you, we have spoken well in that
treatise, when we said that nothing is good excepting what is
honorable, and nothing bad excepting what is disgraceful. *В *В *
XXVII. I am glad that you approve of the doctrine that the
affection borne to our children is implanted by nature; indeed, if
it be not, there can be no conection between man and man which has
its origin in nature. And if there be not, then there is an end of
all society in life. May it turn out well, says Carneades, speaking
shamelessly, but still
440more sensibly than my friend Lucius or
Patro: for, as they refer everything to themselves, do they think
that anything is ever done for the sake of another? And when they
say that a man ought to be good, in order to avoid misfortune, not
because it is right by nature, they do not perceive that they are
speaking of a cunning man, not of a good one. But these arguments
are argued, I think, in those books by praising which you have
given me spirits.
In which I agree that an anxious and hazardous justice is not that
of a wise man.
XXVIII. And again, in Cicero, that same advocate of justice,
Lælius, says, Virtue is clearly eager for honor, nor has she any
other reward; which, however, she accepts easily, and exacts
without bitterness. And in another place the same Lælius says:
When a man is inspired by virtue such as this, what bribes can you offer
him, what treasures, what thrones, what empires? He considers these but
mortal goods, and esteems his own divine. And if the ingratitude of the
people, and the envy of his competitors, or the violence of powerful
enemies, despoil his virtue of its earthly recompense, he still enjoys a
thousand consolations in the approbation of conscience, and sustains
himself by contemplating the beauty of moral rectitude.
XXIX. *В *В * This virtue, in order to be true, must be universal.
Tiberius Gracchus continued faithful to his fellow-citizens, but he
violated the rights and treaties guaranteed to our allies and the Latin
peoples. But if this habit of arbitrary violence begins to extend itself
further, and perverts our authority, leading it from right to violence,
so that those who had voluntarily obeyed us are only restrained by fear,
then, although we, during our days, may escape the peril, yet am I
solicitous respecting the safety of our posterity and the immortality of
the Commonwealth itself, which, doubtless, might become perpetual and
invincible if our people would maintain their ancient institutions and
manners.
XXX. When Lælius had ceased to speak, all those that were present
expressed the extreme pleasure they found in his discourse. But Scipio,
more affected than the rest, and ravished with the delight of sympathy,
exclaimed: You have pleaded, my Lælius, many causes with an eloquence
superior to that of Servius Galba, our colleague, whom you used during
his life to prefer to all others, even to the Attic orators [and never
did I hear you speak with
441more energy than to-day, while pleading the
cause of justice]
345 *В *В *
*В *В * That two things were wanting to enable him to speak in public
and in the forum, confidence and voice.
XXXI. *В *В * This justice, continued Scipio, is the very foundation of
lawful government in political constitutions. Can we call the State of
Agrigentum a commonwealth, where all men are oppressed by the cruelty of
a single tyrant—where there is no universal bond of right, nor social
consent and fellowship, which should belong to every people, properly so
named? It is the same in Syracuse—that illustrious city which Timæus
calls the greatest of the Grecian towns. It was indeed a most beautiful
city; and its admirable citadel, its canals distributed through all its
districts, its broad streets, its porticoes, its temples, and its walls,
gave Syracuse the appearance of a most flourishing state. But while
Dionysius its tyrant reigned there, nothing of all its wealth belonged
to the people, and the people were nothing better than the slaves of one
master. Thus, wherever I behold a tyrant, I know that the social
constitution must be not merely vicious and corrupt, as I stated
yesterday, but in strict truth no social constitution at all.
XXXII.
Lælius. You have spoken admirably, my Scipio, and I see the
point of your observations.
Scipio. You grant, then, that a state which is entirely in the power
of a faction cannot justly be entitled a political community?
Lælius. That is evident.
Scipio. You judge most correctly. For what was the State of Athens
when, during the great Peloponnesian war, she fell under the unjust
domination of the thirty tyrants? The antique glory of that city, the
imposing aspect of its edifices, its theatre, its gymnasium, its
porticoes, its temples, its citadel, the admirable sculptures of
Phidias, and the magnificent harbor of Piræus—did they constitute it a
commonwealth?
Lælius. Certainly not, because these did not constitute the real
welfare of the community.
442Scipio. And at Rome, when the decemvirs ruled without appeal from
their decisions, in the third year of their power, had not liberty lost
all its securities and all its blessings?
Lælius. Yes; the welfare of the community was no longer consulted, and
the people soon roused themselves, and recovered their appropriate
rights.
XXXIII.
Scipio. I now come to the third, or democratical, form of
government, in which a considerable difficulty presents itself, because
all things are there said to lie at the disposition of the people, and
are carried into execution just as they please. Here the populace
inflict punishments at their pleasure, and act, and seize, and keep
possession, and distribute property, without let or hinderance. Can you
deny, my Lælius, that this is a fair definition of a democracy, where
the people are all in all, and where the people constitute the State?
Lælius. There is no political constitution to which I more absolutely
deny the name of a
commonwealth than that in which all things lie in
the power of the multitude. If a commonwealth, which implies the welfare
of the entire community, could not exist in Agrigentum, Syracuse, or
Athens when tyrants reigned over them—if it could not exist in Rome
when under the oligarchy of the decemvirs—neither do I see how this
sacred name of commonwealth can be applied to a democracy and the sway
of the mob; because, in the first place, my Scipio, I build on your own
admirable definition, that there can be no community, properly so
called, unless it be regulated by a combination of rights. And, by this
definition, it appears that a multitude of men may be just as tyrannical
as a single despot; and it is so much the worse, since no monster can be
more barbarous than the mob, which assumes the name and appearance of
the people. Nor is it at all reasonable, since the laws place the
property of madmen in the hands of their sane relations, that we should
do the [very reverse in politics, and throw the property of the sane
into the hands of the mad multitude]
346 *В *В *
XXXIV. *В *В * [It is far more rational] to assert that a wise and
virtuous aristocratical government deserves
443the title of a
commonwealth, as it approaches to the nature of a kingdom.
And much more so in my opinion, said Mummius. For the unity of power
often exposes a king to become a despot; but when an aristocracy,
consisting of many virtuous men, exercise power, that is the most
fortunate circumstance possible for any state. However this be, I much
prefer royalty to democracy; for that is the third kind of government
which you have remaining, and a most vicious one it is.
XXXV. Scipio replied: I am well acquainted, my Mummius, with your
decided antipathy to the democratical system. And, although, we may
speak of it with rather more indulgence than you are accustomed to
accord it, I must certainly agree with you, that of all the three
particular forms of government, none is less commendable than democracy.
I do not agree with you, however, when you would imply that aristocracy
is preferable to royalty. If you suppose that wisdom governs the State,
is it not as well that this wisdom should reside in one monarch as in
many nobles?
But we are led away by a certain incorrectness of terms in a discussion
like the present. When we pronounce the word “aristocracy,” which, in
Greek, signifies the government of the best men, what can be conceived
more excellent? For what can be thought better than the best? But when,
on the other hand, the title “king” is mentioned, we begin to imagine a
tyrant; as if a king must be necessarily unjust. But we are not speaking
of an unjust king when we are examining the true nature of royal
authority. To this name of king, therefore, do but attach the idea of a
Romulus, a Numa, a Tullus, and perhaps you will be less severe to the
monarchical form of constitution.
Mummius. Have you, then, no commendation at all for any kind of
democratical government?
Scipio. Why, I think some democratical forms less objectionable than
others; and, by way of illustration, I will ask you what you thought of
the government in the isle of Rhodes, where we were lately together; did
it appear to you a legitimate and rational constitution?
444Mummius. It did, and not much liable to abuse.
Scipio. You say truly. But, if you recollect, it was a very
extraordinary experiment. All the inhabitants were alternately senators
and citizens. Some months they spent in their senatorial functions, and
some months they spent in their civil employments. In both they
exercised judicial powers; and in the theatre and the court, the same
men judged all causes, capital and not capital. And they had as much
influence, and were of as much importance as *В *В *
FRAGMENTS.
XXXVI. There is therefore some unquiet feeling in individuals,
which either exults in pleasure or is crushed by annoyance.
No war can be undertaken by a just and wise state unless for faith or
self-defence. This self-defence of the State is enough to insure its
perpetuity, and this perpetuity is what all patriots desire. Those
afflictions which even the hardiest spirits smart under—poverty, exile,
prison, and torment—private individuals seek to escape from by an
instantaneous death. But for states, the greatest calamity of all is
that of death, which to individuals appears a refuge. A state should be
so constituted as to live forever. For a commonwealth there is no
natural dissolution as there is for a man, to whom death not only
becomes necessary, but often desirable. And when a state once decays and
falls, it is so utterly revolutionized, that, if we may compare great
things with small, it resembles the final wreck of the universe.
All wars undertaken without a proper motive are unjust. And no war can
be reputed just unless it be duly announced and proclaimed, and if it be
not preceded by a rational demand for restitution.
Our Roman Commonwealth, by defending its allies, has got possession of
the world.
446INTRODUCTION TO THE FOURTH BOOK,
BY THE ORIGINAL TRANSLATOR.
In this fourth book Cicero treats of morals and education, and the
use and abuse of stage entertainments. We retain nothing of this
important book save a few scattered fragments, the beauty of which
fills us with the greater regret for the passages we have lost.
BOOK IV.
FRAGMENTS.
I. *В *В * Since mention has been made of the body and of the mind, I
will endeavor to explain the theory of each as well as the weakness
of my understanding is able to comprehend it—a duty which I think
it the more becoming in me to undertake, because Marcus Tullius, a
man of singular genius, after having attempted to perform it in the
fourth book of his treatise on the Commonwealth, compressed a
subject of wide extent within narrow limits, only touching lightly
on all the principal points. And that there might be no excuse
alleged for his not having followed out this topic, he himself has
assured us that he was not wanting either in inclination or in
anxiety to do so; for, in the first book of his treatise on Laws,
when he was touching briefly on the same subject, he speaks thus:
“This topic Scipio, in my opinion, has sufficiently discussed in
those books which you have read.”
And the mind itself, which sees the future, remembers the past.
Well did Marcus Tullius say, In truth, if there is no one who would
not prefer death to being changed into the form of some beast,
although he were still to retain the mind of a man, how much more
wretched is it to have the mind of a beast in the form of a man! To
me this fate appears as much worse than the other as the mind is
superior to the body.
Tullius says somewhere that he does not think the good of a ram and
of Publius Africanus identical.
And also by its being interposed, it causes shade and night, which
is adapted both to the numbering of days and to rest from labor.
And as in the autumn he has opened the earth to receive seeds, in
winter relaxed it that it may digest them, and by the ripening
powers of summer softened some and burned up others.
When the shepherds use *В *В * for cattle.
Cicero, in the fourth book of his Commonwealth, uses the word
“armentum,” and “armentarius,” derived from it.
447II. The great law of just and regular subordination is the basis of
political prosperity. There is much advantage in the harmonious
succession of ranks and orders and classes, in which the suffrages of
the knights and the senators have their due weight. Too many have
foolishly desired to destroy this institution, in the vain hope of
receiving some new largess, by a public decree, out of a distribution of
the property of the nobility.
III. Consider, now, how wisely the other provisions have been adopted,
in order to secure to the citizens the benefits of an honest and happy
life; for that is, indeed, the grand object of all political
association, and that which every government should endeavor to procure
for the people, partly by its institutions, and partly by its laws.
Consider, in the first place, the national education of the people—a
matter on which the Greeks have expended much labor in vain, and which
is the only point on which Polybius, who settled among us, accuses the
negligence of our institutions. For our countrymen have thought that
education ought not to be fixed, nor regulated by laws, nor be given
publicly and uniformly to all classes of society. For
347 *В *В *
According to Tully, who says that men going to serve in the army
have guardians assigned to them, by whom they are governed the
first year.
IV. [In our ancient laws, young men were prohibited from appearing]
naked in the public baths, so far back were the principles of modesty
traced by our ancestors. Among the Greeks, on the contrary, what an
absurd system of training youth is exhibited in their gymnasia! What a
frivolous preparation for the labors and hazards of war! what indecent
spectacles, what impure and licentious amours are permitted! I do not
speak only of the Eleans and Thebans, among whom, in all love affairs,
passion is allowed to run into shameless excesses; but the Spartans,
while they permit every kind of license to their young men, save that of
violation, fence off, by a very slight wall, the very exception on which
they insist, besides other crimes which I will not mention.
448Then Lælius said: I see, my Scipio, that on the subject of the Greek
institutions, which you censure, you prefer attacking the customs of the
most renowned peoples to contending with your favorite Plato, whose name
you have avoided citing, especially as * * *
V. So that Cicero, in his treatise on the Commonwealth, says that
it was a reproach to young men if they had no lovers.
Not only as at Sparta, where boys learn to steal and plunder.
And our master Plato, even more than Lycurgus, who would have
everything to be common, so that no one should be able to call
anything his own property.
I would send him to the same place whither he sends Homer, crowned
with chaplets and anointed with perfumes, banishing him from the
city which he is describing.
VI. The judgment of the censor inflicts scarcely anything more than
a blush on the man whom he condemns. Therefore as all that
adjudication turns solely on the name (
nomen), the punishment is
called ignominy.
Nor should a prefect be set over women, an officer who is created
among the Greeks; but there should be a censor to teach husbands to
manage their wives.
So the discipline of modesty has great power. All women abstain
from wine.
And also if any woman was of bad character, her relations used not
to kiss her.
So petulance is derived from asking (
petendo); wantonness
(
procacitas) from
procando, that is, from demanding.
VII. For I do not approve of the same nation being the ruler and
the farmer of lands. But both in private families and in the
affairs of the Commonwealth I look upon economy as a revenue.
Faith (
fides) appears to me to derive its name from that being
done (
fit) which is said.
In a citizen of rank and noble birth, caressing manners, display,
and ambition are marks of levity.
Examine for a while the books on the Republic, and learn that good
men know no bound or limit in consulting the interests of their
country. See in that treatise with what praises frugality, and
continency, and fidelity to the marriage tie, and chaste,
honorable, and virtuous manners are extolled.
VIII. I marvel at the elegant choice, not only of the facts, but of
the language. If they dispute (
jurgant). It is a contest between
well-wishers, not a quarrel between enemies, that is called a
dispute (
jurgium),
Therefore the law considers that neighbors dispute (
jurgare)
rather than quarrel (
litigare) with one another.
The bounds of man’s care and of man’s life are the same; so by the
pontifical law the sanctity of burial * * *
They put them to death, though innocent, because they had left
those men unburied whom they could not rescue from the sea because
of the violence of the storm.
449Nor in this discussion have I advocated the cause of the populace,
but of the good.
For one cannot easily resist a powerful people if one gives them
either no rights at all or very little.
In which case I wish I could augur first with truth and fidelity * * *
IX. Cicero saying this in vain, when speaking of poets, “And when
the shouts and approval of the people, as of some great and wise
teacher, has reached them, what darkness do they bring on! what
alarms do they cause! what desires do they excite!”
Cicero says that if his life were extended to twice its length, he
should not have time to read the lyric poets.
X. As Scipio says in Cicero, “As they thought the whole histrionic
art, and everything connected with the theatre, discreditable, they
thought fit that all men of that description should not only be
deprived of the honors belonging to the rest of the citizens, but
should also be deprived of their franchise by the sentence of the
censors.”
And what the ancient Romans thought on this subject Cicero informs
us, in those books which he wrote on the Commonwealth, where Scipio
argues and says *В *В *
Comedies could never (if it had not been authorized by the common
customs of life) have made theatres approve of their scandalous
exhibitions. And the more ancient Greeks provided a certain correction
for the vicious taste of the people, by making a law that it should be
expressly defined by a censorship what subjects comedy should treat, and
how she should treat them.
Whom has it not attacked? or, rather, whom has it not wounded? and whom
has it spared? In this, no doubt, it sometimes took the right side, and
lashed the popular demagogues and seditious agitators, such as Cleon,
Cleophon, and Hyperbolus. We may tolerate that; though indeed the
censure of the magistrate would, in these cases, have been more
efficacious than the satire of the poet. But when Pericles, who governed
the Athenian Commonwealth for so many years with the highest authority,
both in peace and war, was outraged by verses, and these were acted on
the stage, it was hardly more decent than if, among us, Plautus and
Nævius had attacked Publius and Cnæus, or Cæcilius had ventured to
revile Marcus Cato.
Our laws of the Twelve Tables, on the contrary—so careful to attach
capital punishment to a very few crimes only—have included in this
class of capital offences the offence of composing or publicly reciting
verses of libel, slander, and defamation, in order to cast dishonor and
infamy
450on a fellow-citizen. And they have decided wisely; for our life
and character should, if suspected, be submitted to the sentence of
judicial tribunals and the legal investigations of our magistrates, and
not to the whims and fancies of poets. Nor should we be exposed to any
charge of disgrace which we cannot meet by legal process, and openly
refute at the bar.
In our laws, I admire the justice of their expressions, as well as their
decisions. Thus the word
pleading signifies rather an amicable suit
between friends than a quarrel between enemies.
It is not easy to resist a powerful people, if you allow them no rights,
or next to none.
The old Romans would not allow any living man to be either praised
or blamed on the stage.
XI. Cicero says that comedy is an imitation of life; a mirror of
customs, an image of truth.
Since, as is mentioned in that book on the Commonwealth, not only
did Г†schines the Athenian, a man of the greatest eloquence, who,
when a young man, had been an actor of tragedies, concern himself
in public affairs, but the Athenians often sent Aristodemus, who
was also a tragic actor, to Philip as an ambassador, to treat of
the most important affairs of peace and war.
INTRODUCTION TO THE FIFTH BOOK,
BY THE ORIGINAL TRANSLATOR.
In this fifth book Cicero explains and enforces the duties of
magistrates, and the importance of practical experience to all who
undertake their important functions. Only a few fragments have
survived the wreck of ages and descended to us.
BOOK V.
FRAGMENTS.
I.
Ennius has told us—
Of men and customs mighty Rome consists;
which verse, both for its precision and its verity, appears to me as if
it had issued from an oracle; for neither the 451men, unless the State had
adopted a certain system of manners—nor the manners, unless they had
been illustrated by the men—could ever have established or maintained
for so many ages so vast a republic, or one of such righteous and
extensive sway.
Thus, long before our own times, the force of hereditary manners of
itself moulded most eminent men; and admirable citizens, in return, gave
new weight to the ancient customs and institutions of our ancestors. But
our age, on the contrary, having received the Commonwealth as a finished
picture of another century, but one already beginning to fade through
the lapse of years, has not only neglected to renew the colors of the
original painting, but has not even cared to preserve its general form
and prominent lineaments.
For what now remains of those antique manners, of which the poet said
that our Commonwealth consisted? They have now become so obsolete and
forgotten that they are not only not cultivated, but they are not even
known. And as to the men, what shall I say? For the manners themselves
have only perished through a scarcity of men; of which great misfortune
we are not only called to give an account, but even, as men accused of
capital offences, to a certain degree to plead our own cause in
connection with it. For it is owing to our vices, rather than to any
accident, that we have retained the name of republic when we have long
since lost the reality.
II. *В *В * There is no employment so essentially royal as the exposition
of equity, which comprises the true interpretation of all laws. This
justice subjects used generally to expect from their kings. For this
reason, lands, fields, woods, and pastures were reserved as the property
of kings, and cultivated for them, without any labor on their part, in
order that no anxiety on account of their personal interests might
distract their attention from the welfare of the State. Nor was any
private man allowed to be the judge or arbitrator in any suit; but all
disputes were terminated by the royal sentence.
And of all our Roman monarchs, Numa appears to me to have best preserved
this ancient custom of the kings of Greece. For the others, though they
also discharged this 452duty, were for the main part employed in
conducting military enterprises, and in attending to those rights which
belonged to war. But the long peace of Numa’s reign was the mother of
law and religion in this city. And he was himself the author of those
admirable laws which, as you are aware, are still extant. And this
character is precisely what belongs to the man of whom we are speaking.
*В *В *
III. [Scipio. Ought not a farmer] to be acquainted with the nature of
plants and seeds?
Manilius. Certainly, provided he attends to his practical business
also.
Scipio. Do you think that knowledge only fit for a steward?
Manilius. Certainly not, inasmuch as the cultivation of land often
fails for want of agricultural labor.
Scipio. Therefore, as the steward knows the nature of a field, and the
scribe knows penmanship, and as both of them seek, in their respective
sciences, not mere amusement only, but practical utility, so this
statesman of ours should have studied the science of jurisprudence and
legislation; he should have investigated their original sources; but he
should not embarrass himself in debating and arguing, reading and
scribbling. He should rather employ himself in the actual administration
of government, and become a sort of steward of it, being perfectly
conversant with the principles of universal law and equity, without
which no man can be just: not unfamiliar with the civil laws of states;
but he will use them for practical purposes, even as a pilot uses
astronomy, and a physician natural philosophy. For both these men bring
their theoretical science to bear on the practice of their arts; and our
statesman [should do the same with the science of politics, and make it
subservient to the actual interests of philanthropy and patriotism]. *В *В *
IV. *В *В * In states in which good men desire glory and approbation, and
shun disgrace and ignominy. Nor are such men so much alarmed by the
threats and penalties of the law as by that sentiment of shame with
which nature has endowed man, which is nothing else than a certain fear
of deserved censure. The wise director of a government 453strengthens this
natural instinct by the force of public opinion, and perfects it by
education and manners. And thus the citizens are preserved from vice and
corruption rather by honor and shame than by fear of punishment. But
this argument will be better illustrated when we treat of the love of
glory and praise, which we shall discuss on another occasion.
V. As respects the private life and the manners of the citizens, they
are intimately connected with the laws that constitute just marriages
and legitimate offspring, under the protection of the guardian deities
around the domestic hearths. By these laws, all men should be maintained
in their rights of public and private property. It is only under a good
government like this that men can live happily—for nothing can be more
delightful than a well-constituted state.
On which account it appears to me a very strange thing what this *В *В *
VI. I therefore consume all my time in considering what is the
power of that man, whom, as you think, we have described carefully
enough in our books. Do you, then, admit our idea of that governor
of a commonwealth to whom we wish to refer everything? For thus, I
imagine, does Scipio speak in the fifth book: “For as a fair voyage
is the object of the master of a ship, the health of his patient
the aim of a physician, and victory that of a general, so the
happiness of his fellow-citizens is the proper study of the ruler
of a commonwealth; that they may be stable in power, rich in
resources, widely known in reputation, and honorable through their
virtue. For a ruler ought to be one who can perfect this, which is
the best and most important employment among mankind.”
And works in your literature rightly praise that ruler of a country
who consults the welfare of his people more than their
inclinations.
VII. Tully, in those books which he wrote upon the Commonwealth,
could not conceal his opinions, when he speaks of appointing a
chief of the State, who, he says, must be maintained by glory; and
afterward he relates that his ancestors did many admirable and
noble actions from a desire of glory.
Tully, in his treatise on the Commonwealth, wrote that the chief of
a state must be maintained by glory, and that a commonwealth would
last as long as honor was paid by every one to the chief.
INTRODUCTION TO THE SIXTH BOOK.
In this last book of his Commonwealth, Cicero labors to show that
truly pious philanthropical and patriotic statesmen will not only
be rewarded on earth by the approval of conscience and the applause
of all good citizens, but that they may expect hereafter immortal
glory in new forms of being. To illustrate this, he introduces the
“Dream of Scipio,” in which he explains the resplendent doctrines
of Plato respecting the immortality of the soul with inimitable
dignity and elegance. This Somnium Scipionis, for which we are
indebted to the citation of Macrobius, is the most beautiful thing
of the kind ever written. It has been intensely admired by all
European scholars, and will be still more so. There are two
translations of it in our language; one attached to Oliver’s
edition of Cicero’s Thoughts, the other by Mr. Danby, published in
1829. Of these we have freely availed ourselves, and as freely we
express our acknowledgments.
BOOK VI.
SCIPIO’S DREAM.
I.
Therefore you rely upon all the prudence of this rule, which has
derived its very name (
prudentia) from foreseeing (
a
providendo). Wherefore the citizen must so prepare himself as to
be always armed against those things which trouble the constitution
of a state. And that
455dissension of the citizens, when one party
separates from and attacks another, is called sedition.
And in truth in civil dissensions, as the good are of more
importance than the many, I think that we should regard the weight
of the citizens, and not their number.
For the lusts, being severe mistresses of the thoughts, command and
compel many an unbridled action. And as they cannot be satisfied or
appeased by any means, they urge those whom they have inflamed with
their allurements to every kind of atrocity.
II. Which indeed was so much the greater in him because though the
cause of the colleagues was identical, not only was their
unpopularity not equal, but the influence of Gracchus was employed
in mitigating the hatred borne to Claudius.
Who encountered the number of the chiefs and nobles with these
words, and left behind him that mournful and dignified expression
of his gravity and influence.
That, as he writes, a thousand men might every day descend into the
forum with cloaks dyed in purple.
IX. When I had arrived in Africa, where I was, as you are aware,
military tribune of the fourth legion under the consul Manilius, there
was nothing of which I was more earnestly desirous than to see King
Masinissa, who, for very just reasons, had been always the especial
friend of our family. When I was introduced to him, the old man embraced
me, shed tears, and then, looking up to heaven, exclaimed—I thank thee,
O supreme Sun, and ye also, ye other celestial beings, that before I
depart from this life I behold in my kingdom, and in this my palace,
Publius Cornelius Scipio, by whose mere name I seem to be reanimated; so
completely and indelibly is the recollection of that best and most
invincible of men, Africanus, imprinted in my mind.
After this, I inquired of him concerning the affairs of his kingdom. He,
on the other hand, questioned me about the condition of our
Commonwealth, and in this mutual interchange of conversation we passed
the whole of that day.
X. In the evening we were entertained in a manner worthy the
magnificence of a king, and carried on our discourse for a considerable
part of the night. And during all this time the old man spoke of nothing
but Africanus, all whose actions, and even remarkable sayings, he
remembered distinctly. At last, when we retired to bed, I fell into a
more profound sleep than usual, both because I was fatigued with my
journey, and because I had sat up the greatest part of the night.
Here I had the following dream, occasioned, as I verily believe, by our
preceding conversation; for it frequently happens that the thoughts and
discourses which have employed us in the daytime produce in our sleep an
effect somewhat similar to that which Ennius writes happened to him
about Homer, of whom, in his waking hours, he used frequently
458to think
and speak.
Africanus, I thought, appeared to me in that shape, with which I was
better acquainted from his picture than from any personal knowledge of
him. When I perceived it was he, I confess I trembled with
consternation; but he addressed me, saying, Take courage, my Scipio; be
not afraid, and carefully remember what I shall say to you.
XI. Do you see that city Carthage, which, though brought under the Roman
yoke by me, is now renewing former wars, and cannot live in peace? (and
he pointed to Carthage from a lofty spot, full of stars, and brilliant,
and glittering)—to attack which city you are this day arrived in a
station not much superior to that of a private soldier. Before two
years, however, are elapsed, you shall be consul, and complete its
overthrow; and you shall obtain, by your own merit, the surname of
Africanus, which as yet belongs to you no otherwise than as derived from
me. And when you have destroyed Carthage, and received the honor of a
triumph, and been made censor, and, in quality of ambassador, visited
Egypt, Syria, Asia, and Greece, you shall be elected a second time
consul in your absence, and, by utterly destroying Numantia, put an end
to a most dangerous war.
But when you have entered the Capitol in your triumphal car, you shall
find the Roman Commonwealth all in a ferment, through the intrigues of
my grandson Tiberius Gracchus.
XII. It is on this occasion, my dear Africanus, that you show your
country the greatness of your understanding, capacity, and prudence. But
I see that the destiny, however, of that time is, as it were, uncertain;
for when your age shall have accomplished seven times eight revolutions
of the sun, and your fatal hours shall be marked put by the natural
product of these two numbers, each of which is esteemed a perfect one,
but for different reasons, then shall the whole city have recourse to
you alone, and place its hopes in your auspicious name. On you the
senate,
459all good citizens, the allies, the people of Latium, shall cast
their eyes; on you the preservation of the State shall entirely depend.
In a word,
if you escape the impious machinations of your relatives,
you will, in quality of dictator, establish order and tranquillity in
the Commonwealth.
When on this Lælius made an exclamation, and the rest of the company
groaned loudly, Scipio, with a gentle smile, said, I entreat you, do not
wake me out of my dream, but have patience, and hear the rest.
XIII. Now, in order to encourage you, my dear Africanus, continued the
shade of my ancestor, to defend the State with the greater cheerfulness,
be assured that, for all those who have in any way conduced to the
preservation, defence, and enlargement of their native country, there is
a certain place in heaven where they shall enjoy an eternity of
happiness. For nothing on earth is more agreeable to God, the Supreme
Governor of the universe, than the assemblies and societies of men
united together by laws, which are called states. It is from heaven
their rulers and preservers came, and thither they return.
XIV. Though at these words I was extremely troubled, not so much at the
fear of death as at the perfidy of my own relations, yet I recollected
myself enough to inquire whether he himself, my father Paulus, and
others whom we look upon as dead, were really living.
Yes, truly, replied he, they all enjoy life who have escaped from the
chains of the body as from a prison. But as to what you call life on
earth, that is no more than one form of death. But see; here comes your
father Paulus towards you! And as soon as I observed him, my eyes burst
out into a flood of tears; but he took me in his arms, embraced me, and
bade me not weep.
XV. When my first transports subsided, and I regained the liberty of
speech, I addressed my father thus: Thou best and most venerable of
parents, since this, as I am informed by Africanus, is the only
substantial life, why do I linger on earth, and not rather haste to come
hither where you are?
That, replied he, is impossible: unless that God, whose temple is all
that vast expanse you behold, shall free you
460from the fetters of the
body, you can have no admission into this place. Mankind have received
their being on this very condition, that they should labor for the
preservation of that globe which is situated, as you see, in the midst
of this temple, and is called earth.
Men are likewise endowed with a soul, which is a portion of the eternal
fires which you call stars and constellations; and which, being round,
spherical bodies, animated by divine intelligences, perform their cycles
and revolutions with amazing rapidity. It is your duty, therefore, my
Publius, and that of all who have any veneration for the Gods, to
preserve this wonderful union of soul and body; nor without the express
command of Him who gave you a soul should the least thought be
entertained of quitting human life, lest you seem to desert the post
assigned you by God himself.
But rather follow the examples of your grandfather here, and of me, your
father, in paying a strict regard to justice and piety; which is due in
a great degree to parents and relations, but most of all to our country.
Such a life as this is the true way to heaven, and to the company of
those, who, after having lived on earth and escaped from the body,
inhabit the place which you now behold.
XVI. This was the shining circle, or zone, whose remarkable brightness
distinguishes it among the constellations, and which, after the Greeks,
you call the Milky Way.
From thence, as I took a view of the universe, everything appeared
beautiful and admirable; for there those stars are to be seen that are
never visible from our globe, and everything appears of such magnitude
as we could not have imagined. The least of all the stars was that
removed farthest from heaven, and situated next to the earth; I mean our
moon, which shines with a borrowed light. Now, the globes of the stars
far surpass the magnitude of our earth, which at that distance appeared
so exceedingly small that I could not but be sensibly affected on seeing
our whole empire no larger than if we touched the earth, as it were, at
a single point.
XVII. And as I continued to observe the earth with great attention, How
long, I pray you, said Africanus,
461will your mind be fixed on that
object? why don’t you rather take a view of the magnificent temples
among which you have arrived? The universe is composed of nine circles,
or rather spheres, one of which is the heavenly one, and is exterior to
all the rest, which it embraces; being itself the Supreme God, and
bounding and containing the whole. In it are fixed those stars which
revolve with never-varying courses. Below this are seven other spheres,
which revolve in a contrary direction to that of the heavens. One of
these is occupied by the globe which on earth they call Saturn. Next to
that is the star of Jupiter, so benign and salutary to mankind. The
third in order is that fiery and terrible planet called Mars. Below
this, again, almost in the middle region, is the sun—the leader,
governor, and prince of the other luminaries; the soul of the world,
which it regulates and illumines; being of such vast size that it
pervades and gives light to all places. Then follow Venus and Mercury,
which attend, as it were, on the sun. Lastly, the moon, which shines
only in the reflected beams of the sun, moves in the lowest sphere of
all. Below this, if we except that gift of the Gods, the soul, which has
been given by the liberality of the Gods to the human race, everything
is mortal, and tends to dissolution; but above the moon all is eternal.
For the earth, which is the ninth globe, and occupies the centre, is
immovable, and, being the lowest, all others gravitate towards it.
XVIII. When I had recovered myself from the astonishment occasioned by
such a wonderful prospect, I thus addressed Africanus: Pray what is this
sound that strikes my ears in so loud and agreeable a manner? To which
he replied: It is that which is called the
music of the spheres, being
produced by their motion and impulse; and being formed by unequal
intervals, but such as are divided according to the justest proportion,
it produces, by duly tempering acute with grave sounds, various concerts
of harmony. For it is impossible that motions so great should be
performed without any noise; and it is agreeable to nature that the
extremes on one side should produce sharp, and on the other flat sounds.
For which reason the sphere of the fixed stars, being the highest, and
being
462carried with a more rapid velocity, moves with a shrill and acute
sound; whereas that of the moon, being the lowest, moves with a very
flat one. As to the earth, which makes the ninth sphere, it remains
immovably fixed in the middle or lowest part of the universe. But those
eight revolving circles, in which both Mercury and Venus are moved with
the same celerity, give out sounds that are divided by seven distinct
intervals, which is generally the regulating number of all things.
This celestial harmony has been imitated by learned musicians both on
stringed instruments and with the voice, whereby they have opened to
themselves a way to return to the celestial regions, as have likewise
many others who have employed their sublime genius while on earth in
cultivating the divine sciences.
By the amazing noise of this sound the ears of mankind have been in some
degree deafened; and indeed hearing is the dullest of all the human
senses. Thus, the people who dwell near the cataracts of the Nile, which
are called Catadupa
348, are, by the excessive roar which that river
makes in precipitating itself from those lofty mountains, entirely
deprived of the sense of hearing. And so inconceivably great is this
sound which is produced by the rapid motion of the whole universe, that
the human ear is no more capable of receiving it than the eye is able to
look steadfastly and directly on the sun, whose beams easily dazzle the
strongest sight.
While I was busied in admiring the scene of wonders, I could not help
casting my eyes every now and then on the earth.
XIX. On which Africanus said, I perceive that you are still employed in
contemplating the seat and residence of mankind. But if it appears to
you so small, as in fact it really is, despise its vanities, and fix
your attention forever on these heavenly objects. Is it possible that
you should attain any human applause or glory that is worth the
contending for? The earth, you see, is peopled but in a very few places,
and those, too, of small extent; and they appear like so many little
spots of green scattered through vast, uncultivated deserts. And those
who inhabit the
463earth are not only so remote from each other as to be
cut off from all mutual correspondence, but their situation being in
oblique or contrary parts of the globe, or perhaps in those
diametrically opposite to yours, all expectation of universal fame must
fall to the ground.
XX. You may likewise observe that the same globe of the earth is girt
and surrounded with certain zones, whereof those two that are most
remote from each other, and lie under the opposite poles of heaven, are
congealed with frost; but that one in the middle, which is far the
largest, is scorched with the intense heat of the sun. The other two are
habitable, one towards the south, the inhabitants of which are your
antipodes, with whom you have no connection; the other, towards the
north, is that which you inhabit, whereof a very small part, as you may
see, falls to your share. For the whole extent of what you see is, as it
were, but a little island, narrow at both ends and wide in the middle,
which is surrounded by the sea which on earth you call the great
Atlantic Ocean, and which, notwithstanding this magnificent name, you
see is very insignificant. And even in these cultivated and well-known
countries, has yours, or any of our names, ever passed the heights of
the Caucasus or the currents of the Ganges? In what other parts to the
north or the south, or where the sun rises and sets, will your names
ever be heard? And if we leave these out of the question, how small a
space is there left for your glory to spread itself abroad; and how long
will it remain in the memory of those whose minds are now full of it?
XXI. Besides all this, if the progeny of any future generation should
wish to transmit to their posterity the praises of any one of us which
they have heard from their forefathers, yet the deluges and combustions
of the earth, which must necessarily happen at their destined periods,
will prevent our obtaining, not only an eternal, but even a durable
glory. And, after all, what does it signify whether those who shall
hereafter be born talk of you, when those who have lived before you,
whose number was perhaps not less, and whose merit certainly greater,
were not so much as acquainted with your name?
XXII. Especially since not one of those who shall hear
464of us is able to
retain in his memory the transactions of a single year. The bulk of
mankind, indeed, measure their year by the return of the sun, which is
only one star. But when all the stars shall have returned to the place
whence they set out, and after long periods shall again exhibit the same
aspect of the whole heavens, that is what ought properly to be called
the revolution of a year, though I scarcely dare attempt to enumerate
the vast multitude of ages contained in it. For as the sun in old time
was eclipsed, and seemed to be extinguished, at the time when the soul
of Romulus penetrated into these eternal mansions, so, when all the
constellations and stars shall revert to their primary position, and the
sun shall at the same point and time be again eclipsed, then you may
consider that the grand year is completed. Be assured, however, that the
twentieth part of it is not yet elapsed.
XXIII. Wherefore, if you have no hopes of returning to this place where
great and good men enjoy all that their souls can wish for, of what
value, pray, is all that human glory, which can hardly endure for a
small portion of one year?
If, then, you wish to elevate your views to the contemplation of this
eternal seat of splendor, you will not be satisfied with the praises of
your fellow-mortals, nor with any human rewards that your exploits can
obtain; but Virtue herself must point out to you the true and only
object worthy of your pursuit. Leave to others to speak of you as they
may, for speak they will. Their discourses will be confined to the
narrow limits of the countries you see, nor will their duration be very
extensive; for they will perish like those who utter them, and will be
no more remembered by their posterity.
XXIV. When he had ceased to speak in this manner, I said, O Africanus,
if indeed the door of heaven is open to those who have deserved well of
their country, although, indeed, from my childhood I have always
followed yours and my father’s steps, and have not neglected to imitate
your glory, still, I will from henceforth strive to follow them more
closely.
Follow them, then, said he, and consider your body only, not yourself,
as mortal. For it is not your outward form
465which constitutes your
being, but your mind; not that substance which is palpable to the
senses, but your spiritual nature.
Know, then, that you are a God—for
a God it must be, which flourishes, and feels, and recollects, and
foresees, and governs, regulates and moves the body over which it is
set, as the Supreme Ruler does the world which is subject to him. For as
that Eternal Being moves whatever is mortal in this world, so the
immortal mind of man moves the frail body with which it is connected.
XXV. For whatever is always moving must be eternal; but that which
derives its motion from a power which is foreign to itself, when that
motion ceases must itself lose its animation.
That alone, then, which moves itself can never cease to be moved,
because it can never desert itself. Moreover, it must be the source, and
origin, and principle of motion in all the rest. There can be nothing
prior to a principle, for all things must originate from it; and it
cannot itself derive its existence from any other source, for if it did
it would no longer be a principle. And if it had no beginning, it can
have no end; for a beginning that is put an end to will neither be
renewed by any other cause, nor will it produce anything else of itself.
All things, therefore, must originate from one source. Thus it follows
that motion must have its source in something which is moved by itself,
and which can neither have a beginning nor an end. Otherwise all the
heavens and all nature must perish, for it is impossible that they can
of themselves acquire any power of producing motion in themselves.
XXVI. As, therefore, it is plain that what is moved by itself must be
eternal, who will deny that this is the general condition and nature of
minds? For as everything is inanimate which is moved by an impulse
exterior to itself, so what is animated is moved by an interior impulse
of its own; for this is the peculiar nature and power of mind. And if
that alone has the power of self-motion, it can neither have had a
beginning, nor can it have an end.
Do you, therefore, exercise this mind of yours in the best pursuits. And
the best pursuits are those which consist in promoting the good of your
country. Such employments will speed the flight of your mind to this its
466proper abode; and its flight will be still more rapid, if, even while
it is enclosed in the body, it will look abroad, and disengage itself as
much as possible from its bodily dwelling, by the contemplation of
things which are external to itself.
This it should do to the utmost of its power. For the minds of those who
have given themselves up to the pleasures of the body, paying, as it
were, a servile obedience to their lustful impulses, have violated the
laws of God and man; and therefore, when they are separated from their
bodies, flutter continually round the earth on which they lived, and are
not allowed to return to this celestial region till they have been
purified by the revolution of many ages.
Thus saying, he vanished, and I awoke from my dream.
A FRAGMENT.
And although it is most desirable that fortune should remain forever in
the most brilliant possible condition, nevertheless, the equability of
life excites less interest than those changeable conditions wherein
prosperity suddenly revives out of the most desperate and ruinous
circumstances.
THE END.
FOOTNOTES:
1 Archilochus was a native of Paros, and flourished about
714-676
b.c. His poems were chiefly Iambics of bitter satire. Horace
speaks of him as the inventor of Iambics, and calls himself his pupil.
Parios ego primus Iambos
Ostendi Latio, numeros animosque secutus
Archilochi, non res et agentia verba Lycamben.
Epist. I. xix. 25.
And in another place he says,
Archilochum proprio rabies armavit Iambo—A.P. 74.
2 This was Livius Andronicus: he is supposed to have been a
native of Tarentum, and he was made prisoner by the Romans, during their
wars in Southern Italy; owing to which he became the slave of M. Livius
Salinator. He wrote both comedies and tragedies, of which Cicero (Brutus
18) speaks very contemptuously, as “Livianæ fabulæ non satis dignæ quæ
iterum legantur”—not worth reading a second time. He also wrote a Latin
Odyssey, and some hymns, and died probably about 221
b.c.
3 C. Fabius, surnamed Pictor, painted the temple of Salus,
which the dictator C. Junius Brutus Bubulus dedicated 302
b.c. The
temple was destroyed by fire in the reign of Claudius. The painting is
highly praised by Dionysius, xvi. 6.
4 For an account of the ancient Greek philosophers, see the
sketch at the end of the Disputations.
5 Isocrates was born at Athens 436
b.c. He was a pupil of
Gorgias, Prodicus, and Socrates. He opened a school of rhetoric, at
Athens, with great success. He died by his own hand at the age of
ninety-eight.
6 So Horace joins these two classes as inventors of all kinds
of improbable fictions:
Pictoribus atque poetis
Quidlibet audendi semper fuit æqua potestas.—A. P. 9.
Which Roscommon translates:
Painters and poets have been still allow’d
Their pencil and their fancies unconfined.
7 Epicharmus was a native of Cos, but lived at Megara, in
Sicily, and when Megara was destroyed, removed to Syracuse, and lived at
the court of Hiero, where he became the first writer of comedies, so
that Horace ascribes the invention of comedy to him, and so does
Theocritus. He lived to a great age.
8 Pherecydes was a native of Scyros, one of the Cyclades; and
is said to have obtained his knowledge from the secret books of the
PhЕ“nicians. He is said also to have been a pupil of Pittacus, the rival
of Thales, and the master of Pythagoras. His doctrine was that there
were three principles (
О–ОµбЅєП‚, or Г†ther;
О§ОёбЅјОЅ, or Chaos; and
О§ПЃбЅ№ОЅОїП‚, or
Time) and four elements (Fire, Earth, Air, and Water), from which
everything that exists was formed.—
Vide Smith’s Dict. Gr. and Rom.
Biog.
9 Archytas was a native of Tarentum, and is said to have
saved the life of Plato by his influence with the tyrant Dionysius. He
was especially great as a mathematician and geometrician, so that Horace
calls him
Maris et terra numeroque carentis arenæ
Mensorem.
Od. i. 28.1.
Plato is supposed to have learned some of his views from him, and
Aristotle to have borrowed from him every idea of the Categories.
10 This was not Timæus the historian, but a native of Locri,
who is said also in the De Finibus (c. 29) to have been a teacher of
Plato. There is a treatise extant bearing his name, which is, however,
probably spurious, and only an abridgment of Plato’s dialogue Timæus.
11 Dicæarchus was a native of Messana, in Sicily, though he
lived chiefly in Greece. He was one of the later disciples of Aristotle.
He was a great geographer, politician, historian, and philosopher, and
died about 285
b.c.
12 Aristoxenus was a native of Tarentum, and also a pupil of
Aristotle. We know nothing of his opinions except that he held the soul
to be a
harmony of the body; a doctrine which had been already
discussed by Plato in the Phædo, and combated by Aristotle. He was a
great musician, and the chief portions of his works which have come down
to us are fragments of some musical treatises.—Smith’s Dict. Gr. and
Rom. Biog.; to which source I must acknowledge my obligation for nearly
the whole of these biographical notes.
13 The Simonides here meant is the celebrated poet of Ceos,
the perfecter of elegiac poetry among the Greeks. He flourished about
the time of the Persian war. Besides his poetry, he is said to have been
the inventor of some method of aiding the memory. He died at the court
of Hiero, 467
b.c.
14 Theodectes was a native of Phaselis, in Pamphylia, a
distinguished rhetorician and tragic poet, and flourished in the time of
Philip of Macedon. He was a pupil of Isocrates, and lived at Athens, and
died there at the age of forty-one.
15 Cineas was a Thessalian, and (as is said in the text) came
to Rome as ambassador from Pyrrhus after the battle of Heraclea, 280
b.c., and his memory is said to have been so great that on the day after
his arrival he was able to address all the senators and knights by name.
He probably died before Pyrrhus returned to Italy, 276
b.c.
16 Charmadas, called also Charmides, was a fellow-pupil with
Philo, the Larissæan of Clitomachus, the Carthaginian. He is said by
some authors to have founded a fourth academy.
17 Metrodorus was a minister of Mithridates the Great; and
employed by him as supreme judge in Pontus, and afterward as an
ambassador. Cicero speaks of him in other places (De Orat. ii. 88) as a
man of wonderful memory.
18 Quintus Hortensius was eight years older than Cicero; and,
till Cicero’s fame surpassed his, he was accounted the most eloquent of
all the Romans. He was Verres’s counsel in the prosecution conducted
against him by Cicero. Seneca relates that his memory was so great that
he could come out of an auction and repeat the catalogue backward. He
died 50
b.c.
19 This treatise is one which has not come down to us, but
which had been lately composed by Cicero in order to comfort himself for
the loss of his daughter.
20 The epigram is,
О•бјґПЂО±П‚ бјО»О№Оµ П‡О±бї–ПЃОµ, ОљО»ОµбЅ№ОјОІПЃОїП„ОїП‚ бЅОјОІПЃО±ОєО№бЅЅП„О·П‚
ἥλατ’ ἀφ’ ὑψηλοῦ τείχεος εἰς Ἀΐδην,
бј„ОѕО№ОїОЅ ОїбЅђОґбЅІОЅ бј°ОґбЅјОЅ ОёО±ОЅбЅ±П„ОїП… ОєО±ОєбЅёОЅ, бјЂО»О»бЅ° О О»бЅ±П„П‰ОЅОїП‚
ἓν τὸ περὶ ψύχης γράμμ’ ἀναλεξάμενος.
Which may be translated, perhaps,
Farewell, O sun, Cleombrotus exclaim’d,
Then plunged from off a height beneath the sea;
Stung by pain, of no disgrace ashamed,
But moved by Plato’s high philosophy.
21 This is alluded to by Juvenal:
Provida Pompeio dederat Campania febres
Optandas: sed multæ urbes et publica vota
Vicerunt. Igitur Fortuna ipsius et Urbis,
Servatum victo caput abstulit.—Sat. x. 283.
22 Pompey’s second wife was Julia, the daughter of Julius Cæsar,
she died the year before the death of Crassus, in Parthia. Virgil
speaks of Cæsar and Pompey as relations, using the same expression
(socer) as Cicero:
Aggeribus socer Alpinis atque arce Monœci
Descendens, gener adversis instructus Eois.—Æn. vi. 830.
23 This idea is beautifully expanded by Byron:
Yet if, as holiest men have deem’d, there be
A land of souls beyond that sable shore
To shame the doctrine of the Sadducee
And sophist, madly vain or dubious lore,
How sweet it were in concert to adore
With those who made our mortal labors light,
To hear each voice we fear’d to hear no more.
Behold each mighty shade reveal’d to sight,
The Bactrian, Samian sage, and all who taught the right!
Childe Harold, ii.
24 The epitaph in the original is:
Ὦ ξεῖν’ ἀγγεῖλον Λακεδαιμονίοις ὅτι τῇδε
ОєОµбЅ·ОјОµОёО±, П„ОїбїђП‚ ОєОµбЅ·ОЅП‰ОЅ ПЂОµО№ОёбЅ№ОјОµОЅОїО№ ОЅОїОјбЅ·ОјОїО№П‚.
25 This was expressed in the Greek verses,
бј€ПЃП‡бЅґП‚ ОјбЅІОЅ ОјбЅґ П†бї¦ОЅО±О№ бјђПЂО№П‡ОёОїОЅбЅ·ОїО№ПѓО№ОЅ бј„ПЃО№ПѓП„ОїОЅ,
φύντα δ’ ὅπως ὤκιστα πύλας Ἀΐδϋο περῆσαι
which by some authors are attributed to Homer.
26 This is the first fragment of the Cresphontes.—Ed. Var.
vii., p. 594.
бјњОґОµО№ ОібЅ°ПЃ бјЎОјбѕ¶П‚ ПѓбЅ»О»О»ОїОіОїОЅ ПЂОїО№ОїП…ОјбЅіОЅОїП…П‚
Τὸν φύντα θρηνεῖν, εἰς ὅσ’ ἔρχεται κακά.
Τὸν δ’ αὖ θανόντα καὶ πόνων πεπαυμένον
П‡О±бЅ·ПЃОїОЅП„О±П‚ ОµбЅђП†О·ОјОїбї–ОЅП„О±П‚ бјђОєПЂбЅіОјОµО№ОЅ ОґбЅ№ОјП‰ОЅ
27 The Greek verses are quoted by Plutarch:
бј¬ПЂОїП… ОЅбЅµПЂО№Оµ, бј О»бЅ·ОёО№ОїО№ П†ПЃбЅіОЅОµП‚ бјЂОЅОґПЃбї¶ОЅ
О•бЅђОёбЅ»ОЅОїОїП‚ ОєОµбї–П„О±О№ ОјОїО№ПЃО№ОґбЅ·бїі ОёО±ОЅбЅ±П„бїі
ОџбЅђОє бј ОЅ ОібЅ°ПЃ О¶бЅЅОµО№ОЅ ОєО±О»бЅёОЅ О±бЅђП„бї· ОїбЅ”П„Оµ ОіОїОЅОµбї¦ПѓО№.
28 This refers to the story that when Eumolpus, the son of
Neptune, whose assistance the Eleusinians had called in against the
Athenians, had been slain by the Athenians, an oracle demanded the
sacrifice of one of the daughters of Erechtheus, the King of Athens. And
when one was drawn by lot, the others voluntarily accompanied her to
death.
29 MenЕ“ceus was son of Creon, and in the war of the Argives
against Thebes, Teresias declared that the Thebans should conquer if
MenЕ“ceus would sacrifice himself for his country; and accordingly he
killed himself outside the gates of Thebes.
30 The Greek is,
ОјбЅµОґОµ ОјОїО№ бј„ОєО»О±П…ПѓП„ОїП‚ ОёбЅ±ОЅО±П„ОїП‚ ОјбЅ№О»ОїО№, бјЂО»О»бЅ° П†бЅ·О»ОїО№ПѓО№
ПЂОїО№бЅµПѓО±О№ОјО№ ОёО±ОЅбЅјОЅ бј„О»ОіОµО± ОєО±бЅ¶ ПѓП„ОїОЅО±П‡бЅ±П‚.
32 The lines quoted by Cicero here appear to have come from
the Latin play of Prometheus by Accius; the ideas are borrowed, rather
than translated, from the Prometheus of Г†schylus.
34 Each soldier carried a stake, to help form a palisade in
front of the camp.
35 Insania—from
in, a particle of negative force in
composition, and
sanus, healthy, sound.
36 The man who first received this surname was L. Calpurnius
Piso, who was consul, 133
b.c., in the Servile War.
37 The Greek is,
Ἀλλά μοι οἰδάνεται κραδίη χόλῳ ὅπποτ’ ἐκείνου
Μνήσομαι ὅς μ’ ἀσύφηλον ἐν Ἀργείοισιν ἔρεξεν.—Il. ix. 642.
I have given Pope’s translation in the text.
38 This is from the Theseus:
бј�ОібЅј ОґбЅІ П„Оїбї¦П„Ої ПЂО±ПЃбЅ° ПѓОїП†Оїбї¦ П„О№ОЅОїП‚ ОјО±ОёбЅјОЅ
εὶς φροντίδας νοῦν συμφοράς τ’ ἐβαλλόμην
φυγάς τ’ ἐμαυτῷ προστιθεὶς πάτρας ἐμῆς.
θανάτους τ’ ἀώρους, καὶ κακῶν ἄλλας ὁδοὺς
ὡς, εἴ τι πάσχοιμ’ ὠν ἐδόξαζόν ποτε
ОњбЅµ ОјОїО№ ОЅбЅіОїПЃП„ОїОЅ ПЂПЃОїПѓПЂОµПѓбЅёОЅ Ојбѕ¶О»О»ОїОЅ ОґбЅ±ОєОїО№.
39 Ter. Phorm. II. i. 11.
40 This refers to the speech of Agamemnon in Euripides, in
the Iphigenia in Aulis,
О–О·О»бї¶ ПѓОµ, ОібЅіПЃОїОЅ,
ζηλῶ δ’ ἀνδρῶν ὃς ἀκίνδυνον
βίον ἐξεπέρασ’, ἀγνὼς, ἀκλεής.—v. 15.
41 This is a fragment from the Hypsipyle:
О•П†П… ОјбЅІОЅ ОїбЅђОґОµбЅ¶П‚ бЅ…ПѓП„О№П‚ ОїбЅђ ПЂОїОЅОµбї– ОІПЃОїП„бї¶ОЅ
θάπτει τε τέκνα χἄτερ’ αὖ κτᾶται νεὰ,
αὐτός τε θνήσκει. καὶ τάδ’ ἄχθονται βροτοὶ
εἰς γῆν φέροντες γῆν ἀναγκαίως δ’ ἔχει
ОІбЅ·ОїОЅ ОёОµПЃбЅ·О¶ОµО№ОЅ бЅҐПѓП„Оµ ОєбЅ±ПЃПЂО№ОјОїОЅ ПѓП„бЅ±П‡П…ОЅ.
42
Πολλὰς ἐκ κεφαλῆς προθελύμνους ἕλκετο χαίτας.—Il. x. 15.
43
бј¬П„ОїО№ бЅЃ ОєО±ПЂПЂбЅіОґО№ОїОЅ П„бЅё бј€О»О·ОђОїОЅ Оїбј¶ОїП‚ бјЂО»бѕ¶П„Ої
ὅν θυμὸν κατεδὼν, πάτον ἀνθρώπων ἀλεείνων.—Il. vi. 201.
44 This is a translation from Euripides:
бЅПѓОёвЂ™ бјµОјОµПЃОїП‚ μ’ бЅ‘ПЂбї†О»ОёОµ Оібї‡ П„Оµ κ’ ОїбЅђПЃО±ОЅбї·
λέξαι μολούσῃ δεῦρο Μηδείας τύχας.—Med. 57.
45
О›бЅ·О·ОЅ ОібЅ°ПЃ ПЂОїО»О»ОїбЅ¶ ОєО±бЅ¶ бјђПЂбЅµП„ПЃО№ОјОїО№ бј¤ОјО±П„О± ПЂбЅ±ОЅП„О±
ПЂбЅ·ПЂП„ОїП…ПѓО№ОЅ, ПЂбЅ№П„Оµ ОєбЅіОЅ П„О№П‚ бјЂОЅО±ПЂОЅОµбЅ»ПѓОµО№Оµ ПЂбЅ№ОЅОїО№Ої;
бјЂО»О»бЅ° П‡ПЃбЅґ П„бЅёОЅ ОјбЅІОЅ ОєО±П„О±ОёО±ПЂП„бЅіОјОµОЅ, бЅ…П‚ ОєОµ ОёбЅ±ОЅО·ПѓО№,
νηλέα θυμὸν ἔχοντας, ἔπ’ ἤματι δακρυσάντας.—
Hom. Il. xix. 226.
46 This is one of the fragments of Euripides which we are
unable to assign to any play in particular; it occurs Var. Ed. Tr. Inc.
167.
Εἰ μεν τόδ’ ἦμαρ πρῶτον ἦν κακουμένῳ
ОєО±бЅ¶ ОјбЅґ ОјО±ОєПЃбЅ°ОЅ ОґбЅґ ОґО№бЅ° ПЂбЅ№ОЅП‰ОЅ бјђОЅО±П…ПѓП„бЅ№О»ОїП…ОЅ
Оµбј°ОєбЅёП‚ ПѓП†О±ОґбЅ±О¶ОµО№ОЅ бј¦ОЅ бј‚ОЅ, бЅЎП‚ ОЅОµбЅ№О¶П…ОіО±
ПЂбї¶О»ОїОЅ, П‡бЅ±О»О№ОЅОїОЅ бјЂПЃП„бЅ·П‰П‚ ОґОµОґОµОіОјбЅіОЅОїОЅ
νῦν δ’ ἀμβλύς εἰμι, καὶ κατηρτυκὼς κακῶν.
47 This is only a fragment, preserved by Stobæus:
Τοὺς δ’ ἂν μεγίστους καὶ σοφωτάτους φρενὶ
τοιούσδ’ ἴδοις ἂν, οἶός ἐστι νῦν ὅδε,
ОєО±О»бї¶П‚ ОєО±Оєбї¶П‚ ПЂПЃбЅ±ПѓПѓОїОЅП„О№ ПѓП…ОјПЂО±ПЃО±О№ОЅбЅіПѓО±О№
бЅ…П„О±ОЅ ОґбЅІ ОґО±бЅ·ОјП‰ОЅ бјЂОЅОґПЃбЅёП‚ ОµбЅђП„П…П‡Оїбї¦П‚ П„бЅё ПЂПЃбЅ¶ОЅ
μάστιγ’ ἐπίσῃ τοῦ βίου παλίντροπον,
П„бЅ° ПЂОїО»О»бЅ° П†ПЃОїбї¦ОґО± ОєО±бЅ¶ ОєО±Оєбї¶П‚ Оµбј°ПЃО·ОјбЅіОЅО±.
48
О©Оє. ОџбЅђОєОїбї¦ОЅ О ПЃОїОјО·ОёОµбї¦ П„Оїбї¦П„Ої ОіО№ОіОЅбЅЅПѓОєОµО№П‚ бЅ…П„О№
бЅЂПЃОібї†П‚ ОЅОїПѓОїбЅ»ПѓО·П‚ Оµбј°ПѓбЅ¶ОЅ бј°О±П„ПЃОїбЅ¶ О»бЅ№ОіОїО№.
О ПЃ. бјђбЅ±ОЅ П„О№П‚ бјђОЅ ОєО±О№ПЃбї· ОіОµ ОјО±О»ОёбЅ±ПѓПѓбїѓ ОєОµбЅ±ПЃ
καὶ μὴ σφριγῶντα θυμὸν ἰσχναίνη βιᾳ.—
Г†sch. Prom. v. 378.
49 Cicero alludes here to Il. vii. 211, which is thus
translated by Pope:
His massy javelin quivering in his hand,
He stood the bulwark of the Grecian band;
Through every Argive heart new transport ran,
All Troy stood trembling at the mighty man:
E’en Hector paused, and with new doubt oppress’d,
Felt his great heart suspended in his breast;
’Twas vain to seek retreat, and vain to fear,
Himself had challenged, and the foe drew near.
But Melmoth (Note on the Familiar Letters of Cicero, book ii. Let. 23)
rightly accuses Cicero of having misunderstood Homer, who “by no means
represents Hector as being thus totally dismayed at the approach of his
adversary; and, indeed, it would have been inconsistent with the general
character of that hero to have described him under such circumstances of
terror.”
Τὸν δὲ καὶ Ἀργεῖοι μέγ’ ἐγήθεον εἰσορόωντες,
О¤ПЃП‰бЅ°П‚ ОґбЅІ П„ПЃбЅ№ОјОїП‚ О±бј¶ОЅОїП‚ бЅ‘ПЂбЅµО»П…ОёОµ ОіП…бї–О± бј•ОєО±ПѓП„ОїОЅ,
Ἕκτορι δ’ αὐτῷ θυμὸς ἐνὶ στήθεσσι πάτασσεν.
But there is a great difference, as Dr. Clarke remarks, between
ОёП…ОјбЅёП‚ бјђОЅбЅ¶ ПѓП„бЅµОёОµПѓПѓО№ ПЂбЅ±П„О±ПѓПѓОµОЅ and
ОєО±ПЃОґбЅіО· бј”ОѕП‰ ПѓП„О·ОёбЅіП‰ОЅ бј”ОёПЃП‰ПѓОєОµОЅ, or
П„ПЃбЅ№ОјОїП‚ О±бј¶ОЅОїП‚
ὑπήλυθε γυῖα.—
The Trojans, says Homer,
trembled at the sight of
Ajax, and even Hector himself felt some emotion in his breast.
50 Cicero means Scipio Nasica, who, in the riots consequent
on the reelection of Tiberius Gracchus to the tribunate, 133
b.c.,
having called in vain on the consul, Mucius Scævola, to save the
republic, attacked Gracchus himself, who was slain in the tumult.
51 Morosus is evidently derived from
mores—“
Morosus,
mos, stubbornness, self-will, etc.”—Riddle and Arnold, Lat. Dict.
52 In the original they run thus:
Οὔκ ἐστιν οὐδὲν δεινὸν ὧδ’ εἰπεῖν ἔπος,
ОџбЅђОґбЅІ ПЂбЅ±ОёОїП‚, ОїбЅђОґбЅІ ОѕП…ОјП†ОїПЃбЅ° ОёОµбЅµО»О±П„ОїП‚
ἧς οὐκ ἂν ἀροιτ’ ἄχθος ἀνθρώπον φύσις.
53 This passage is from the Eunuch of Terence, act i., sc. 1,
14.
54 These verses are from the Atreus of Accius.
55 This was Marcus Atilius Regulus, the story of whose
treatment by the Carthaginians in the first Punic War is well known to
everybody.
56 This was Quintus Servilius Cæpio, who, 105
b.c., was
destroyed, with his army, by the Cimbri, it was believed as a judgment
for the covetousness which he had displayed in the plunder of Tolosa.
57 This was Marcus Aquilius, who, in the year 88
b.c., was
sent against Mithridates as one of the consular legates; and, being
defeated, was delivered up to the king by the inhabitants of Mitylene.
Mithridates put him to death by pouring molten gold down his throat.
58 This was the elder brother of the triumvir Marcus Crassus,
87
b.c. He was put to death by Fimbria, who was in command of some of
the troops of Marius.
59 Lucius Cæsar and Caius Cæsar were relations (it is
uncertain in what degree) of the great Cæsar, and were killed by Fimbria
on the same occasion as Octavius.
60 M. Antonius was the grandfather of the triumvir; he was
murdered the same year, 87
b.c., by Annius, when Marius and Cinna took
Rome.
61 This story is alluded to by Horace:
Districtus ensis cui super impiГў
Cervice pendet non Siculæ dapes
Dulcem elaborabunt saporem,
Non avium citharæve cantus
Somnum reducent.—iii. 1. 17.
62 Hieronymus was a Rhodian, and a pupil of Aristotle,
flourishing about 300
b.c. He is frequently mentioned by Cicero.
63 We know very little of Dinomachus. Some MSS. have
Clitomachus.
64 Callipho was in all probability a pupil of Epicurus, but
we have no certain information about him.
65 Diodorus was a Syrian, and succeeded Critolaus as the head
of the Peripatetic School at Athens.
66 Aristo was a native of Ceos, and a pupil of Lycon, who
succeeded Straton as the head of the Peripatetic School, 270
b.c. He
afterward himself succeeded Lycon.
67 Pyrrho was a native of Elis, and the originator of the
sceptical theories of some of the ancient philosophers. He was a
contemporary of Alexander.
68 Herillus was a disciple of Zeno of Cittium, and therefore
a Stoic. He did not, however, follow all the opinions of his master: he
held that knowledge was the chief good. Some of the treatises of
Cleanthes were written expressly to confute him.
69 Anacharsis was (Herod., iv., 76) son of Gnurus and brother
of Saulius, King of Thrace. He came to Athens while Solon was occupied
in framing laws for his people; and by the simplicity of his way of
living, and his acute observations on the manners of the Greeks, he
excited such general admiration that he was reckoned by some writers
among the Seven Wise Men of Greece.
70 This was Appius Claudius Cæcus, who was censor 310
b.c.,
and who, according to Livy, was afflicted with blindness by the Gods for
persuading the Potitii to instruct the public servants in the way of
sacrificing to Hercules. He it was who made the Via Appia.
71 The fact of Homer’s blindness rests on a passage in the
Hymn to Apollo, quoted by Thucydides as a genuine work of Homer, and
which is thus spoken of by one of the most accomplished scholars that
this country or this age has ever produced: “They are indeed beautiful
verses; and if none worse had ever been attributed to Homer, the Prince
of Poets would have had little reason to complain.
“He has been describing the Delian festival in honor of Apollo and
Diana, and concludes this part of the poem with an address to the women
of that island, to whom it is to be supposed that he had become
familiarly known by his frequent recitations:
Χαίρετε δ’ ὑμεῖς πᾶσαι, ἐμεῖο δὲ καὶ μετόπισθε
μνήσασθ’, ὅπποτέ κέν τις ἐπιχθονίων ἀνθρώπων
ἐνθάδ’ ἀνείρηται ξεῖνος ταλαπείριος ἐλθὼν
ὦ κοῦραι, τίς δ’ ὕμμιν ἀνὴρ ἥδιστος ἀοιδῶν
бјђОЅОёбЅ±ОґОµ ПЂП‰О»Оµбї–П„О±О№ ОєО±бЅ¶ П„бЅібїі П„бЅіПЃПЂОµПѓОёОµ ОјбЅ±О»О№ПѓП„О±;
ὑμεῖς δ’ εὖ μάλα πᾶσαι ὑποκρίνασθε ἀφ’ ἡμῶν,
О¤П…П†О»бЅёП‚ бјЂОЅбЅґПЃ, Оїбј°ОєОµбї– ОґбЅІ О§бЅ·бїі бјђОЅбЅ¶ ПЂО±О№ПЂО±О»ОїбЅіПѓПѓбїѓ,
П„Оїбї¦ ПЂбѕ¶ПѓО±О№ ОјОµП„бЅ№ПЂО№ПѓОёОµОЅ бјЂПЃО№ПѓП„ОµбЅ»ОїП…ПѓО№ОЅ бјЂОїО№ОґО±бЅ·.
Virgins, farewell—and oh! remember me
Hereafter, when some stranger from the sea,
A hapless wanderer, may your isle explore,
And ask you, �Maids, of all the bards you boast,
Who sings the sweetest, and delights you most?’
Oh! answer all, �A blind old man, and poor,
Sweetest he sings, and dwells on Chios’ rocky shore.’”
Coleridge’s Introduction to the Study of the Greek Classic Poets.
72 Some read
scientiam and some
inscientiam; the latter
of which is preferred by some of the best editors and commentators.
73 For a short account of these ancient Greek philosophers,
see the sketch prefixed to the Academics (
Classical Library).
74 Cicero wrote his philosophical works in the last three
years of his life. When he wrote this piece, he was in the sixty-third
year of his age, in the year of Rome 709.
76 Diodorus and Posidonius were Stoics; Philo and Antiochus
were Academics; but the latter afterward inclined to the doctrine of the
Stoics.
78 Cicero was one of the College of Augurs.
79 The Latinæ Feriæ was originally a festival of the Latins,
altered by Tarquinius Superbus into a Roman one. It was held in the
Alban Mount, in honor of Jupiter Latiaris. This holiday lasted six days:
it was not held at any fixed time; but the consul was never allowed to
take the field till he had held them.—
Vide Smith, Dict. Gr. and Rom.
Ant., p. 414.
80 Exhedra, the word used by Cicero, means a study, or
place where disputes were held.
81 M. Piso was a Peripatetic. The four great sects were the
Stoics, the Peripatetics, the Academics, and the Epicureans.
82 It was a prevailing tenet of the Academics that there is
no certain knowledge.
83 The five forms of Plato are these:
ОїбЅђПѓбЅ·О±, П„О±бЅђП„бЅёОЅ, бј•П„ОµПЃОїОЅ,
ПѓП„бЅ±ПѓО№П‚, ОєбЅ·ОЅО·ПѓО№П‚.
84 The four natures here to be understood are the four
elements—fire, water, air, and earth; which are mentioned as the four
principles of Empedocles by Diogenes Laertius.
85 These five moving stars are Saturn, Jupiter, Mars,
Mercury, and Venus. Their revolutions are considered in the next book.
86 Or, Generation of the Gods.
87 The
ПЂПЃбЅ№О»О·П€О№П‚ of Epicurus, before mentioned, is what he
here means.
88 ОЈП„ОµПЃбЅіОјОЅО№О± is the word which Epicurus used to distinguish
between those objects which are perceptible to sense, and those which
are imperceptible; as the essence of the Divine Being, and the various
operations of the divine power.
89 Zeno here mentioned is not the same that Cotta spoke of
before. This was the founder of the Stoics. The other was an Epicurean
philosopher whom he had heard at Athens.
90 That is, there would be the same uncertainty in heaven as
is among the Academics.
91 Those nations which were neither Greek nor Roman.
92 Sigilla numerantes is the common reading; but P.
Manucius proposes
venerantes, which I choose as the better of the two,
and in which sense I have translated it.
93 Fundamental doctrines.
95 The moon, as well as the sun, is indeed in the zodiac, but
she does not measure the same course in a month. She moves in another
line of the zodiac nearer the earth.
96 According to the doctrines of Epicurus, none of these
bodies themselves are clearly seen, but
simulacra ex corporibus
effluentia.
97 Epicurus taught his disciples in a garden.
98 By the word
Deus, as often used by our author, we are to
understand all the Gods in that theology then treated of, and not a
single personal Deity.
99 The best commentators on this passage agree that Cicero
does not mean that Aristotle affirmed that there was no such person as
Orpheus, but that there was no such poet, and that the verse called
Orphic was said to be the invention of another. The passage of Aristotle
to which Cicero here alludes has, as Dr. Davis observes, been long
lost.
100 A just proportion between the different sorts of beings.
101 Some give
quos non pudeat earum Epicuri vocum; but the
best copies have not
non; nor would it be consistent with Cotta to say
quos non pudeat, for he throughout represents Velleius as a perfect
Epicurean in every article.
102 His country was Abdera, the natives of which were
remarkable for their stupidity.
103 This passage will not admit of a translation answerable
to the sense of the original. Cicero says the word
amicitia
(friendship) is derived from
amor (love or affection).
104 This manner of speaking of Jupiter frequently occurs in
Homer,
——πατὴρ ἀνδρῶν τε θεῶν τε,
and has been used by Virgil and other poets since Ennius.
105 Perses, or Perseus, the last king of Macedonia, was taken
by Cnæus Octavius, the prætor, and brought as prisoner to Paullus
Г†milius, 167
b.c.
106 An exemption from serving in the wars, and from paying
public taxes.
107 Mopsus. There were two soothsayers of this name: the
first was one of the Lapithæ, son of Ampycus and Chloris, called also
the son of Apollo and Hienantis; the other a son of Apollo and Manto,
who is said to have founded Mallus, in Asia Minor, where his oracle
existed as late as the time of Strabo.
108 Tiresias was the great Theban prophet at the time of the
war of the Seven against Thebes.
109 Amphiaraus was King of Argos (he had been one of the
Argonauts also). He was killed after the war of the Seven against
Thebes, which he was compelled to join in by the treachery of his wife
Eriphyle, by the earth opening and swallowing him up as he was fleeing
from Periclymenus.
110 Calchas was the prophet of the Grecian army at the siege
of Troy.
111 Helenus was a son of Priam and Hecuba. He is represented
as a prophet in the Philoctetes of Sophocles. And in the Г†neid he is
also represented as king of part of Epirus, and as predicting to Г†neas
the dangers and fortunes which awaited him.
112 This short passage would be very obscure to the reader
without an explanation from another of Cicero’s treatises. The
expression here,
ad investigandum suem regiones vineæ terminavit,
which is a metaphor too bold, if it was not a sort of augural language,
seems to me to have been the effect of carelessness in our great author;
for Navius did not divide the regions, as he calls them, of the vine to
find his sow, but to find a grape.
113 The Peremnia were a sort of auspices performed just
before the passing a river.
114 The Acumina were a military auspices, and were partly
performed on the point of a spear, from which they were called Acumina.
115 Those were called
testamenta in procinctu, which were
made by soldiers just before an engagement, in the presence of men
called as witnesses.
116 This especially refers to the Decii, one of whom devoted
himself for his country in the war with the Latins, 340
b.c., and his
son imitated the action in the war with the Samnites, 295
b.c. Cicero
(Tusc. i. 37) says that his son did the same thing in the war with
Pyrrhus at the battle of Asculum, though in other places (De Off. iii.
4) he speaks of only two Decii as having signalized themselves in this
manner.
117 The Rogator, who collected the votes, and pronounced who
was the person chosen. There were two sorts of Rogators; one was the
officer here mentioned, and the other was the Rogator, or speaker of the
whole assembly.
118 Which was Sardinia, as appears from one of Cicero’s
epistles to his brother Quintus.
119 Their sacred books of ceremonies.
120 The war between Octavius and Cinna, the consuls.
121 This, in the original, is a fragment of an old Latin
verse,
——Terram fumare calentem.
122 The Latin word is
principatus, which exactly
corresponds with the Greek word here used by Cicero; by which is to be
understood the superior, the most prevailing excellence in every kind
and species of things through the universe.
123 The passage of Aristotle to which Cicero here refers is
lost.
124 He means the Epicureans.
125 Here the Stoic speaks too plain to be misunderstood. His
world, his
mundus, is the universe, and that universe is his great
Deity,
in quo sit totius naturæ principatus, in which the superior
excellence of universal nature consists.
126 Athens, the seat of learning and politeness, of which
Balbus will not allow Epicurus to be worthy.
127 This is Pythagoras’s doctrine, as appears in Diogenes
Laertius.
128 He here alludes to mathematical and geometrical
instruments.
129 Balbus here speaks of the fixed stars, and of the motions
of the orbs of the planets. He here alludes, says M. Bonhier, to the
different and diurnal motions of these stars; one sort from east to
west, the other from one tropic to the other: and this is the
construction which our learned and great geometrician and astronomer,
Dr. Halley, made of this passage.
130 This mensuration of the year into three hundred and
sixty-five days and near six hours (by the odd hours and minutes of
which, in every fifth year, the
dies intercalaris, or leap-year, is
made) could not but be known, Dr. Halley states, by Hipparchus, as
appears from the remains of that great astronomer of the ancients. We
are inclined to think that Julius Cæsar had divided the year, according
to what we call the Julian year, before Cicero wrote this book; for we
see, in the beginning of it, how pathetically he speaks of Cæsar’s
usurpation.
131 The words of Censorinus, on this occasion, are to the
same effect. The opinions of philosophers concerning this great year are
very different; but the institution of it is ascribed to Democritus.
133 Though Mars is said to hold his orbit in the zodiac with
the rest, and to finish his revolution through the same orbit (that is,
the zodiac) with the other two, yet Balbus means in a different line of
the zodiac.
134 According to late observations, it never goes but a sign
and a half from the sun.
135 These, Dr. Davis says, are “aërial fires;” concerning
which he refers to the second book of Pliny.
136 In the Eunuch of Terence.
139 The books of Ceremonies.
140 This Libera is taken for Proserpine, who, with her
brother Liber, was consecrated by the Romans; all which are parts of
nature in prosopopЕ“ias. Cicero, therefore, makes Balbus distinguish
between the person Liber, or Bacchus, and the Liber which is a part of
nature in prosopopЕ“ia.
141 These allegorical fables are largely related by Hesiod in
his Theogony.
Horace says exactly the same thing:
HГўc arte Pollux et vagus Hercules
Enisus arces attigit igneas:
Quos inter Augustus recumbens
Purpureo bibit ore nectar.
Hâc te merentem, Bacche pater, tuæ
Vexere tigres indocili jugum
Collo ferentes: hГўc Quirinus
Martis equis Acheronta fugit.—Hor. iii. 3. 9.
142 Cicero means by
conversis casibus, varying the cases
from the common rule of declension; that is, by departing from the true
grammatical rules of speech; for if we would keep to it, we should
decline the word
Jupiter,
Jupiteris in the second case, etc.
143 Pater divГ»mque hominumque.
144 The common reading is,
planiusque alio loco idem;
which, as Dr. Davis observes, is absurd; therefore, in his note, he
prefers
planius quam alia loco idem, from two copies, in which sense I
have translated it.
145 From the verb
gero, to bear.
146 That is, “mother earth.”
147 Janus is said to be the first who erected temples in
Italy, and instituted religious rites, and from whom the first month in
the Roman calendar is derived.
149 Noctu quasi diem efficeret. Ben Jonson says the same
thing:
Thou that mak’st a day of night,
Goddess excellently bright.—Ode to the Moon.
150 Olympias was the mother of Alexander.
151 Venus is here said to be one of the names of Diana,
because
ad res omnes veniret; but she is not supposed to be the same
as the mother of Cupid.
152 Here is a mistake, as Fulvius Ursinus observes; for the
discourse seems to be continued in one day, as appears from the
beginning of this book. This may be an inadvertency of Cicero.
153 The senate of Athens was so called from the words
бјЊПЃОµО№ОїП‚ О бЅ±ОіОїП‚, the Village, some say the Hill, of Mars.
156 By
nulla cohærendi natura—if it is the right, as it is
the common reading—Cicero must mean the same as by
nulla crescendi
natura, or
coalescendi, either of which Lambinus proposes; for, as the
same learned critic well observes, is there not a cohesion of parts in a
clod, or in a piece of stone? Our learned Walker proposes
sola
cohærendi natura, which mends the sense very much; and I wish he had
the authority of any copy for it.
157 Nasica Scipio, the censor, is said to have been the first
who made a water-clock in Rome.
159 An old Latin poet, commended by Quintilian for the
gravity of his sense and his loftiness of style.
160 The shepherd is here supposed to take the stem or beak of
the ship for the mouth, from which the roaring voices of the sailors
came.
Rostrum is here a lucky word to put in the mouth of one who
never saw a ship before, as it is used for the beak of a bird, the snout
of a beast or fish, and for the stem of a ship.
162 Greek,
бјЂбЅґПЃ; Latin,
aer.
163 The treatise of Aristotle, from whence this is taken, is
lost.
164 To the universe the Stoics certainly annexed the idea of
a limited space, otherwise they could not have talked of a middle; for
there can be no middle but of a limited space: infinite space can have
no middle, there being infinite extension from every part.
165 These two contrary reversions are from the tropics of
Cancer and Capricorn. They are the extreme bounds of the sun’s course.
The reader must observe that the astronomical parts of this book are
introduced by the Stoic as proofs of design and reason in the universe;
and, notwithstanding the errors in his planetary system, his intent is
well answered, because all he means is that the regular motions of the
heavenly bodies, and their dependencies, are demonstrations of a divine
mind. The inference proposed to be drawn from his astronomical
observations is as just as if his system was in every part
unexceptionably right: the same may be said of his anatomical
observations.
168 These verses of Cicero are a translation from a Greek
poem of Aratus, called the Phænomena.
170 The arctic and antarctic poles.
171 The two Arctoi are northern constellations. Cynosura is
what we call the Lesser Bear; Helice, the Greater Bear; in Latin,
Ursa
Minor and
Ursa Major.
172 These stars in the Greater Bear are vulgarly called the
“Seven Stars,” or the “Northern Wain;” by the Latins, “Septentriones.”
175 Exactly agreeable to this and the following description
of the Dragon is the same northern constellation described in the map by
Flamsteed in his Atlas CЕ“lestis; and all the figures here described by
Aratus nearly agree with the maps of the same constellations in the
Atlas CЕ“lestis, though they are not all placed precisely alike.
176 The tail of the Greater Bear.
177 That is, in Macedon, where Aratus lived.
178 The true interpretation of this passage is as follows:
Here in Macedon, says Aratus, the head of the Dragon does not entirely
immerge itself in the ocean, but only touches the superficies of it. By
ortus and
obitus I doubt not but Cicero meant, agreeable to Aratus,
those parts which arise to view, and those which are removed from
sight.
179 These are two northern constellations. Engonasis, in some
catalogues called Hercules, because he is figured kneeling
бјђОЅ ОібЅ№ОЅО±ПѓО№ОЅ
(on his knees).
�νγόνασιν καλέουσ’, as Aratus says, they call
Engonasis.
180 The crown is placed under the feet of Hercules in the
Atlas CЕ“lestis; but Ophiuchus (
бЅ€П†О№Оїбї¦П‡ОїП‚), the Snake-holder, is placed in
the map by Flamsteed as described here by Aratus; and their heads almost
meet.
181 The Scorpion. Ophiuchus, though a northern constellation,
is not far from that part of the zodiac where the Scorpion is, which is
one of the six southern signs.
182 The Wain of seven stars.
183 The Wain-driver. This northern constellation is, in our
present maps, figured with a club in his right hand behind the Greater
Bear.
184 In some modern maps Arcturus, a star of the first
magnitude, is placed in the belt that is round the waist of Boötes.
Cicero says
subter præcordia, which is about the waist; and Aratus
says
бЅ‘ПЂбЅё О¶бЅЅОЅбїѓ, under the belt.
185 Sub caput Arcti, under the head of the Greater Bear.
186 The Crab is, by the ancients and moderns, placed in the
zodiac, as here, between the Twins and the Lion; and they are all three
northern signs.
187 The Twins are placed in the zodiac with the side of one
to the northern hemisphere, and the side of the other to the southern
hemisphere. Auriga, the Charioteer, is placed in the northern hemisphere
near the zodiac, by the Twins; and at the head of the Charioteer is
Helice, the Greater Bear, placed; and the Goat is a bright star of the
first magnitude placed on the left shoulder of this northern
constellation, and called
Capra, the Goat.
HЕ“di, the Kids, are two
more stars of the same constellation.
188 A constellation; one of the northern signs in the zodiac,
in which the Hyades are placed.
189 One of the feet of Cepheus, a northern constellation, is
under the tail of the Lesser Bear.
190 Grotius, and after him Dr. Davis, and other learned men,
read
Cassiepea, after the Greek
ОљО±ПѓПѓбЅ·ОµПЂОµО№О±, and reject the common
reading,
Cassiopea.
191 These northern constellations here mentioned have been
always placed together as one family with Cepheus and Perseus, as they
are in our modern maps.
192 This alludes to the fable of Perseus and Andromeda.
193 Pegasus, who is one of Perseus and Andromeda’s family.
195 Aries, the Ram, is the first northern sign in the
zodiac;
Pisces, the Fishes, the last southern sign; therefore they
must be near one another, as they are in a circle or belt. In
Flamsteed’s Atlas Cœlestis one of the Fishes is near the head of the
Ram, and the other near the Urn of Aquarius.
196 These are called Virgiliæ by Cicero; by Aratus, the
Pleiades,
О О»О·ПЉбЅ±ОґОµП‚; and they are placed at the neck of the Bull; and one
of Perseus’s feet touches the Bull in the Atlas Cœlestis.
197 This northern constellation is called Fides by Cicero;
but it must be the same with Lyra; because Lyra is placed in our maps as
Fides is here.
198 This is called Ales Avis by Cicero; and I doubt not but
the northern constellation Cygnus is here to be understood, for the
description and place of the Swan in the Atlas CЕ“lestis are the same
which Ales Avis has here.
200 The Water-bearer, one of the six southern signs in the
zodiac: he is described in our maps pouring water out of an urn, and
leaning with one hand on the tail of Capricorn, another southern sign.
201 When the sun is in Capricorn, the days are at the
shortest; and when in Cancer, at the longest.
202 One of the six southern signs.
203 Sagittarius, another southern sign.
204 A northern constellation.
205 A northern constellation.
206 A southern constellation.
207 This is Canis Major, a southern constellation. Orion and
the Dog are named together by Hesiod, who flourished many hundred years
before Cicero or Aratus.
208 A southern constellation, placed as here in the Atlas
CЕ“lestis.
209 A southern constellation, so called from the ship Argo,
in which Jason and the rest of the Argonauts sailed on their expedition
to Colchos.
210 The Ram is the first of the northern signs in the zodiac;
and the last southern sign is the Fishes; which two signs, meeting in
the zodiac, cover the constellation called Argo.
211 The river Eridanus, a southern constellation.
212 A southern constellation.
213 This is called the Scorpion in the original of Aratus.
214 A southern constellation.
215 A southern constellation.
216 The Serpent is not mentioned in Cicero’s translation; but
it is in the original of Aratus.
217 A southern constellation.
218 The Goblet, or Cup, a southern constellation.
219 A southern constellation.
220 Antecanis, a southern constellation, is the Little Dog,
and called
Antecanis in Latin, and
О ПЃОїОєбЅ»П‰ОЅ in Greek, because he rises
before the other Dog.
221 Pansætius, a Stoic philosopher.
223 The proboscis of the elephant is frequently called a
hand, because it is as useful to him as one. “They breathe, drink, and
smell, with what may not be improperly called a hand,” says Pliny, bk.
viii. c. 10.—
Davis.
224 The passage of Aristotle’s works to which Cicero here
alludes is entirely lost; but Plutarch gives a similar account.
225 Balbus does not tell us the remedy which the panther
makes use of; but Pliny is not quite so delicate: he says,
excrementis
hominis sibi medetur.
226 Aristotle says they purge themselves with this herb after
they fawn. Pliny says both before and after.
227 The cuttle-fish has a bag at its neck, the black blood of
which the Romans used for ink. It was called
atramentum.
228 The Euphrates is said to carry into Mesopotamia a large
quantity of citrons, with which it covers the fields.
229 Q. Curtius, and some other authors, say the Ganges is the
largest river in India; but Ammianus Marcellinus concurs with Cicero in
calling the river Indus the largest of all rivers.
230 These Etesian winds return periodically once a year, and
blow at certain seasons, and for a certain time.
231 Some read
mollitur, and some
molitur; the latter of
which P. Manucius justly prefers, from the verb
molo,
molis; from
whence, says he,
molares dentes, the grinders.
232 The weasand, or windpipe.
233 The epiglottis, which is a cartilaginous flap in the
shape of a tongue, and therefore called so.
234 Cicero is here giving the opinion of the ancients
concerning the passage of the chyle till it is converted to blood.
235 What Cicero here calls the ventricles of the heart are
likewise called auricles, of which there is the right and left.
236 The Stoics and Peripatetics said that the nerves, veins,
and arteries come directly from the heart. According to the anatomy of
the moderns, they come from the brain.
237 The author means all musical instruments, whether string
or wind instruments, which are hollow and tortuous.
238 The Latin version of Cicero is a translation from the
Greek of Aratus.
239 Chrysippus’s meaning is, that the swine is so inactive
and slothful a beast that life seems to be of no use to it but to keep
it from putrefaction, as salt keeps dead flesh.
240 Ales, in the general signification, is any large bird;
and
oscinis is any singing bird. But they here mean those birds which
are used in augury:
alites are the birds whose flight was observed by
the augurs, and
oscines the birds from whose voices they augured.
241 As the Academics doubted everything, it was indifferent
to them which side of a question they took.
242 The keepers and interpreters of the Sibylline oracles
were the Quindecimviri.
243 The popular name of Jupiter in Rome, being looked upon as
defender of the Capitol (in which he was placed), and stayer of the
State.
244 Some passages of the original are here wanting. Cotta
continues speaking against the doctrine of the Stoics.
245 The word
sortes is often used for the answers of the
oracles, or, rather, for the rolls in which the answers were written.
246 Three of this eminent family sacrificed themselves for
their country; the father in the Latin war, the son in the Tuscan war,
and the grandson in the war with Pyrrhus.
247 The Straits of Gibraltar.
248 The common reading is,
ex quo anima dicitur; but Dr.
Davis and M. Bouhier prefer
animal, though they keep
anima in the
text, because our author says elsewhere,
animum ex anima dictum, Tusc.
I. 1. Cicero is not here to be accused of contradictions, for we are to
consider that he speaks in the characters of other persons; but there
appears to be nothing in these two passages irreconcilable, and probably
anima is the right word here.
249 He is said to have led a colony from Greece into Caria,
in Asia, and to have built a town, and called it after his own name, for
which his countrymen paid him divine honors after his death.
250 Our great author is under a mistake here. Homer does not
say he met Hercules himself, but his
Εἴδωλον, his “visionary likeness;”
and adds that he himself
μετ’ ἀθανάτοισι θεοῖσι
П„бЅіПЃПЂОµП„О±О№ бјђОЅ ОёО±О»бЅ·бїѓП‚, ОєО±бЅ¶ бј”П‡ОµО№ ОєО±О»О»бЅ·ПѓП†П…ПЃОїП… бјОІО·ОЅ,
ПЂО±бї–ОґО± О”О№бЅёП‚ ОјОµОібЅ±О»ОїО№Ої ОєО±бЅ¶ бјПЃО·П‚ П‡ПЃП…ПѓОїПЂОµОґбЅ·О»ОїП….
which Pope translates—
A shadowy form, for high in heaven’s abodes
Himself resides, a God among the Gods;
There, in the bright assemblies of the skies,
He nectar quaffs, and Hebe crowns his joys.
251 They are said to have been the first workers in iron.
They were called Idæi, because they inhabited about Mount Ida in Crete,
and Dactyli, from
ОґбЅ±ОєП„П…О»ОїО№ (the fingers), their number being five.
252 From whom, some say, the city of that name was called.
253 Capedunculæ seem to have been bowls or cups, with handles
on each side, set apart for the use of the altar.—
Davis.
254 See Cicero de Divinatione, and Ovid. Fast.
255 In the consulship of Piso and Gabinius sacrifices to
Serapis and Isis were prohibited in Rome; but the Roman people afterward
placed them again in the number of their gods. See Tertullian’s Apol.
and his first book Ad Nationes, and Arnobius, lib. 2.—
Davis.
256 In some copies Circe, Pasiphae, and Г†a are mentioned
together; but Г†a is rejected by the most judicious editors.
257 They were three, and are said to have averted a plague by
offering themselves a sacrifice.
258 So called from the Greek word
ОёО±П…ОјбЅ±О¶П‰, to wonder.
259 She was first called Geres, from
gero, to bear.
260 The word is
precatione, which means the books or forms
of prayers used by the augurs.
261 Cotta’s intent here, as well as in other places, is to
show how unphilosophical their civil theology was, and with what
confusions it was embarrassed; which design of the Academic the reader
should carefully keep in view, or he will lose the chain of argument.
262 Anactes,
бјЊОЅО±ОєП„ОµП‚, was a general name for all kings, as we
find in the oldest Greek writers, and particularly in Homer.
263 The common reading is Aleo; but we follow Lambinus and
Davis, who had the authority of the best manuscript copies.
264 Some prefer Phthas to Opas (see Dr. Davis’s edition); but
Opas is the generally received reading.
269 So called from the Greek word
ОЅбЅ№ОјОїП‚,
lex, a law.
270 He is called
бЅ®ПЂО№П‚ in some old Greek fragments, and
ОџбЅ–ПЂО№П‚ by Callimachus in his hymn on Diana.
271 ОЈО±ОІбЅ±О¶бЅ·ОїП‚, Sabazius, is one of the names used for
Bacchus.
272 Here is a wide chasm in the original. What is lost
probably may have contained great part of Cotta’s arguments against the
providence of the Stoics.
273 Here is one expression in the quotation from Cæcilius
that is not commonly met with, which is
præstigias præstrinxit;
Lambinus gives
præstinxit, for the sake, I suppose, of playing on
words, because it might then be translated, “He has deluded my
delusions, or stratagems;” but
præstrinxit is certainly the right
reading.
274 The ancient Romans had a judicial as well as a military
prætor; and he sat, with inferior judges attending him, like one of our
chief-justices.
Sessum it prætor, which I doubt not is the right
reading, Lambinus restored from an old copy. The common reading was
sessum ite precor.
275 Picenum was a region of Italy.
276 The
sex primi were general receivers of all taxes and
tributes; and they were obliged to make good, out of their own fortunes,
whatever deficiencies were in the public treasury.
277 The Lætorian Law was a security for those under age
against extortioners, etc. By this law all debts contracted under
twenty-five years of age were void.
278 This is from Ennius—
Utinam ne in nemore Pelio securibus
Cæsa cecidisset abiegna ad terram trabes.
Translated from the beginning of the Medea of Euripides—
Μήδ’ ἐν νάπαισι Πηλίον πεσεῖν ποτε
П„ОјО·ОёОµбї–ПѓО± ПЂОµбЅ»ОєО·.
279 Q. Fabius Maximus, surnamed Cunctator.
280 Diogenes Laertius says he was pounded to death in a stone
mortar by command of Nicocreon, tyrant of Cyprus.
281 Elea, a city of Lucania, in Italy. The manner in which
Zeno was put to death is, according to Diogenes Laertius, uncertain.
282 This great and good man was accused of destroying the
divinity of the Gods of his country. He was condemned, and died by
drinking a glass of poison.
284 The common reading is,
in tympanidis rogum inlatus est.
This passage has been the occasion of as many different opinions
concerning both the reading and the sense as any passage in the whole
treatise.
Tympanum is used for a timbrel or drum,
tympanidia a
diminutive of it. Lambinus says
tympana “were sticks with which the
tyrant used to beat the condemned.” P. Victorius substitutes
tyrannidis for
tympanidis.
285 The original is
de amissa salute; which means the
sentence of banishment among the Romans, in which was contained the loss
of goods and estate, and the privileges of a Roman; and in this sense
L’Abbé d’Olivet translates it.
286 The forty-seventh proposition of the first book of Euclid
is unanimously ascribed to him by the ancients. Dr. Wotton, in his
Reflections upon Ancient and Modern Learning, says, “It is indeed a very
noble proposition, the foundation of trigonometry, of universal and
various use in those curious speculations about incommensurable
numbers.”
287 These votive tables, or pictures, were hung up in the
temples.
288 This passage is a fragment from a tragedy of Attius.
289 Hipponax was a poet at Ephesus, and so deformed that
Bupalus drew a picture of him to provoke laughter; for which Hipponax is
said to have written such keen iambics on the painter that he hanged
himself.
Lycambes had promised Archilochus the poet to marry his daughter to him,
but afterward retracted his promise, and refused her; upon which
Archilochus is said to have published a satire in iambic verse that
provoked him to hang himself.
290 Cicero refers here to an oracle approving of his laws,
and promising Sparta prosperity as long as they were obeyed, which
Lycurgus procured from Delphi.
291 Pro aris et focis is a proverbial expression. The
Romans, when they would say their all was at stake, could not express it
stronger than by saying they contended
pro aris et focis, for religion
and their firesides, or, as we express it, for religion and property.
292 Cicero, who was an Academic, gives his opinion according
to the manner of the Academics, who looked upon probability, and a
resemblance of truth, as the utmost they could arrive at.
295 It is unnecessary to give an account of the other names
here mentioned; but that of Lænas is probably less known. He was Publius
Popillius Lænas, consul 132
b.c., the year after the death of Tiberius
Gracchus, and it became his duty to prosecute the accomplices of
Gracchus, for which he was afterward attacked by Caius Gracchus with
such animosity that he withdrew into voluntary exile. Cicero pays a
tribute to the energy of Opimius in the first Oration against Catiline,
c. iii.
296 This phenomenon of the parhelion, or mock sun, which so
puzzled Cicero’s interlocutors, has been very satisfactorily explained
by modern science. The parhelia are formed by the reflection of the
sunbeams on a cloud properly situated. They usually accompany the
coronæ, or luminous circles, and are placed in the same circumference,
and at the same height. Their colors resemble that of the rainbow; the
red and yellow are towards the side of the sun, and the blue and violet
on the other. There are, however, coronæ sometimes seen without
parhelia, and
vice versГў. Parhelia are double, triple, etc., and in
1629, a parhelion of five suns was seen at Rome, and another of six suns
at Arles, 1666.
297 There is a little uncertainty as to what this age was,
but it was probably about twenty-five.
298 Cicero here gives a very exact and correct account of the
planetarium of Archimedes, which is so often noticed by the ancient
astronomers. It no doubt corresponded in a great measure to our modern
planetarium, or orrery, invented by the earl of that name. This
elaborate machine, whose manufacture requires the most exact and
critical science, is of the greatest service to those who study the
revolutions of the stars, for astronomic, astrologic, or meteorologic
purposes.
299 The end of the fourteenth chapter and the first words of
the fifteenth are lost; but it is plain that in the fifteenth it is
Scipio who is speaking.
300 There is evidently some error in the text here, for
Ennius was born 515
a.u.c., was a personal friend of the elder
Africanus, and died about 575
a.u.c., so that it is plain that we ought
to read in the text 550, not 350.
301 Two pages are lost here. Afterward it is again Scipio who
is speaking.
302 Two pages are lost here.
303 Both Ennius and Nævius wrote tragedies called
“Iphigenia.” Mai thinks the text here corrupt, and expresses some doubt
whether there is a quotation here at all.
304 He means Scipio himself.
305 There is again a hiatus. What follows is spoken by
Lælius.
306 Again two pages are lost.
307 Again two pages are lost. It is evident that Scipio is
speaking again in cap. xxxi.
308 Again two pages are lost.
309 Again two pages are lost.
310 Here four pages are lost.
311 Here four pages are lost.
312 Two pages are missing here.
314 About seven lines are lost here, and there is a great
deal of corruption and imperfection in the next few sentences.
315 Two pages are lost here.
316 The
Lex Curiata de Imperio, so often mentioned here,
was the same as the
Auctoritas Patrum, and was necessary in order to
confer upon the dictator, consuls, and other magistrates the
imperium,
or military command: without this they had only a
potestas, or civil
authority, and could not meddle with military affairs.
317 Two pages are missing here.
318 Here two pages are missing.
319 I have translated this very corrupt passage according to
Niebuhr’s emendation.
320 Assiduus, ab Г¦re dando.
322 Here four pages are missing.
323 Two pages are missing here.
324 Two pages are missing here.
325 Here twelve pages are missing.
326 Sixteen pages are missing here.
327 Here eight pages are missing.
328 A great many pages are missing here.
329 Several pages are lost here; the passage in brackets is
found in Nonius under the word “exulto.”
330 This and other chapters printed in smaller type are
generally presumed to be of doubtful authenticity.
331 The beginning of this book is lost. The two first
paragraphs come, the one from St. Augustine, the other from Lactantius.
332 Eight or nine pages are lost here.
333 Here six pages are lost.
334 Here twelve pages are missing.
335 We have been obliged to insert two or three of these
sentences between brackets, which are not found in the original, for the
sake of showing the drift of the arguments of Philus. He himself was
fully convinced that justice and morality were of eternal and immutable
obligation, and that the best interests of all beings lie in their
perpetual development and application. This eternity of Justice is
beautifully illustrated by Montesquieu. “Long,” says he, “before
positive laws were instituted, the moral relations of justice were
absolute and universal. To say that there were no justice or injustice
but that which depends on the injunctions or prohibitions of positive
laws, is to say that the radii which spring from a centre are not equal
till we have formed a circle to illustrate the proposition. We must,
therefore, acknowledge that the relations of equity were antecedent to
the positive laws which corroborated them.” But though Philus was fully
convinced of this, in order to give his friends Scipio and Lælius an
opportunity of proving it, he frankly brings forward every argument for
injustice that sophistry had ever cast in the teeth of reason.—
By the
original Translator.
336 Here four pages are missing. The following sentence is
preserved in Nonius.
337 Two pages are missing here.
338 Several pages are missing here.
339 He means Alexander the Great.
340 Six or eight pages are lost here.
341 A great many pages are missing here.
342 Six or eight pages are missing here.
343 Several pages are lost here.
344 This and the following chapters are not the actual words
of Cicero, but quotations by Lactantius and Augustine of what they
affirm that he said.
345 Twelve pages are missing here.
346 Eight pages are missing here.
347 Six or eight pages are missing here.
348 Catadupa, from
ОєО±П„бЅ° and
ОґОїбї–ПЂОїП‚, noise.
End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of Cicero's Tusculan Disputations
by Marcus Tullius Cicero
*** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK CICERO'S TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS ***
***** This file should be named 14988-h.htm or 14988-h.zip *****
This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
http://www.gutenberg.net/1/4/9/8/14988/
Produced by Ted Garvin, Hagen von Eitzen and the PG Online Distributed
Proofreading Team.
Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions
will be renamed.
Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no
one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation
(and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without
permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules,
set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to
copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to
protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark. Project
Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you
charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If you
do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the
rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose
such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and
research. They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do
practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is
subject to the trademark license, especially commercial
redistribution.
*** START: FULL LICENSE ***
THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
(or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project
Gutenberg-tm License (available with this file or online at
http://gutenberg.net/license).
Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy
all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession.
If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the
terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or
entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.
1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be
used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement
and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation"
or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the
collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an
individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are
located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from
copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative
works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg
are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project
Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by
freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with
the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by
keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project
Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others.
1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in
a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check
the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement
before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or
creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project
Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning
the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United
States.
1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate
access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently
whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the
phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project
Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed,
copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net
1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived
from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is
posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied
and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees
or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work
with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the
work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1
through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the
Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or
1.E.9.
1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional
terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked
to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the
permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work.
1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.
1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg-tm License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any
word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or
distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than
"Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version
posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.net),
you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a
copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other
form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided
that
- You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is
owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he
has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments
must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you
prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax
returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and
sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the
address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation."
- You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License. You must require such a user to return or
destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium
and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of
Project Gutenberg-tm works.
- You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any
money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days
of receipt of the work.
- You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael
Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark. Contact the
Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.
1.F.
1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm
collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain
"Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or
corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a
computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by
your equipment.
1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH F3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
DAMAGE.
1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with
your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with
the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a
refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity
providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to
receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy
is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further
opportunities to fix the problem.
1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS' WITH NO OTHER
WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by
the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance
with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production,
promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works,
harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees,
that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm
work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any
Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause.
Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm
Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers
including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists
because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from
people in all walks of life.
Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
assistance they need, is critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations.
To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4
and the Foundation web page at http://www.pglaf.org.
Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Its 501(c)(3) letter is posted at
http://pglaf.org/fundraising. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.
The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S.
Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered
throughout numerous locations. Its business office is located at
809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887, email
[email protected]. Email contact links and up to date contact
information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official
page at http://pglaf.org
For additional contact information:
Dr. Gregory B. Newby
Chief Executive and Director
[email protected]
Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation
Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
status with the IRS.
The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To
SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any
particular state visit http://pglaf.org
While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
approach us with offers to donate.
International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
ways including including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: http://pglaf.org/donate
Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works.
Professor Michael S. Hart is the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm
concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared
with anyone. For thirty years, he produced and distributed Project
Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support.
Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S.
unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily
keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition.
Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:
http://www.gutenberg.net
This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.
Cicero’s Tusculan Disputations, On the Nature of the Gods, On the Commonwealth
Project Gutenberg's Cicero's Tusculan Disputations, by Marcus Tullius Cicero
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net
Title: Cicero's Tusculan Disputations
Also, Treatises On The Nature Of The Gods, And On The Commonwealth
Author: Marcus Tullius Cicero
Release Date: February 9, 2005 [EBook #14988]
Language: English and Latin
Character set encoding: ISO-8859-1
*** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK CICERO'S TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS ***
Produced by Ted Garvin, Hagen von Eitzen and the PG Online Distributed
Proofreading Team.
CICERO’S
TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS;
В
ALSO, TREATISES ON
THE NATURE OF THE GODS,
AND ON
THE COMMONWEALTH.
В
LITERALLY TRANSLATED, CHIEFLY BY
C. D. YONGE.
NEW YORK:
HARPER & BROTHERS, PUBLISHERS,
FRANKLIN SQUARE.
1877.
2HARPER’S
NEW CLASSICAL LIBRARY.
COMPRISING LITERAL TRANSLATIONS OF
CÆSAR.
VIRGIL.
SALLUST.
HORACE.
CICERO’S ORATIONS.
CICERO’S OFFICES &c.
CICERO ON ORATORY AND ORATORS.
CICERO’S TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS, the Republic, and the Nature of the Gods.
TERENCE.
TACITUS.
LIVY. 2 Vols.
JUVENAL.
XENOPHON.
HOMER’S ILIAD.
HOMER’S ODYSSEY.
HERODOTUS.
DEMOSTHENES. 2 Vols.
THUCIDIDES.
Г†SCHYLUS.
SOPHOCLES.
EURIPIDES. 2 Vols.
PLATO. [Select Dialogues.]
12mo, Cloth, $1.50 per Volume.
Harper & Brothers will send either of the above works by mail, postage
prepaid, to any part of the United States, on receipt of the price.
3NOTE.
The greater portion of the Republic was previously translated by Francis
Barham, Esq., and published in 1841. Although ably performed, it was not
sufficiently close for the purpose of the “
Classical Library,” and was
therefore placed in the hands of the present editor for revision, as
well as for collation with recent texts. This has occasioned material
alterations and additions.
The treatise “On the Nature of the Gods” is a revision of that usually
ascribed to the celebrated Benjamin Franklin.
5CONTENTS.
Tusculan Disputations
On the Nature of the Gods
On the Commonwealth
7THE TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS.
INTRODUCTION.
In the year
a.u.c. 708, and the sixty-second year of Cicero’s age, his
daughter, Tullia, died in childbed; and her loss afflicted Cicero to
such a degree that he abandoned all public business, and, leaving the
city, retired to Asterra, which was a country house that he had near
Antium; where, after a while, he devoted himself to philosophical
studies, and, besides other works, he published his Treatise de Finibus,
and also this treatise called the Tusculan Disputations, of which
Middleton gives this concise description:
“The first book teaches us how to contemn the terrors of death, and to
look upon it as a blessing rather than an evil;
“The second, to support pain and affliction with a manly fortitude;
“The third, to appease all our complaints and uneasinesses under the
accidents of life;
“The fourth, to moderate all our other passions;
“And the fifth explains the sufficiency of virtue to make men happy.”
It was his custom in the opportunities of his leisure to take some
friends with him into the country, where, instead of amusing themselves
with idle sports or feasts, their diversions were wholly speculative,
tending to improve the mind and enlarge the understanding. In this
manner he now spent five days at his Tusculan villa in discussing with
his friends the several questions just mentioned. For, after employing
the mornings in declaiming and rhetorical exercises, they used to retire
in the afternoon
8into a gallery, called the Academy, which he had built
for the purpose of philosophical conferences, where, after the manner of
the Greeks, he held a school, as they called it, and invited the company
to call for any subject that they desired to hear explained, which being
proposed accordingly by some of the audience became immediately the
argument of that day’s debate. These five conferences, or dialogues, he
collected afterward into writing in the very words and manner in which
they really passed; and published them under the title of his Tusculan
Disputations, from the name of the villa in which they were held.
BOOK I.
ON THE CONTEMPT OF DEATH.
I.
At a time when I had entirely, or to a great degree, released myself
from my labors as an advocate, and from my duties as a senator, I had
recourse again, Brutus, principally by your advice, to those studies
which never had been out of my mind, although neglected at times, and
which after a long interval I resumed; and now, since the principles and
rules of all arts which relate to living well depend on the study of
wisdom, which is called philosophy, I have thought it an employment
worthy of me to illustrate them in the Latin tongue, not because
philosophy could not be understood in the Greek language, or by the
teaching of Greek masters; but it has always been my opinion that our
countrymen have, in some instances, made wiser discoveries than the
Greeks, with reference to those subjects which they have considered
worthy of devoting their attention to, and in others have improved upon
their discoveries, so that in one way or other we surpass them on every
point; for, with regard to the manners and habits of private life, and
family and domestic affairs, we certainly manage them with more
elegance, and better than they did; and as to our republic, that our
ancestors have, beyond all dispute, formed on better customs and laws.
What shall I say of our military affairs; in which our ancestors have
been most eminent in valor, and still more so
9in discipline? As to
those things which are attained not by study, but nature, neither
Greece, nor any nation, is comparable to us; for what people has
displayed such gravity, such steadiness, such greatness of soul,
probity, faith—such distinguished virtue of every kind, as to be equal
to our ancestors. In learning, indeed, and all kinds of literature,
Greece did excel us, and it was easy to do so where there was no
competition; for while among the Greeks the poets were the most ancient
species of learned men—since Homer and Hesiod lived before the
foundation of Rome, and Archilochus
1 was a contemporary of Romulus—we
received poetry much later. For it was about five hundred and ten years
after the building of Rome before Livius
2 published a play in the
consulship of C. Claudius, the son of Cæcus, and M. Tuditanus, a year
before the birth of Ennius, who was older than Plautus and Nævius.
II. It was, therefore, late before poets were either known or received
among us; though we find in Cato de Originibus that the guests used, at
their entertainments, to sing the praises of famous men to the sound of
the flute; but a speech of Cato’s shows this kind of poetry to have been
in no great esteem, as he censures Marcus Nobilior for carrying poets
with him into his province; for that consul, as we know, carried Ennius
with him into Г†tolia. Therefore the less esteem poets were in, the less
were
10those studies pursued; though even then those who did display the
greatest abilities that way were not very inferior to the Greeks. Do we
imagine that if it had been considered commendable in Fabius,
3 a man
of the highest rank, to paint, we should not have had many Polycleti and
Parrhasii? Honor nourishes art, and glory is the spur with all to
studies; while those studies are always neglected in every nation which
are looked upon disparagingly. The Greeks held skill in vocal and
instrumental music as a very important accomplishment, and therefore it
is recorded of Epaminondas, who, in my opinion, was the greatest man
among the Greeks, that he played excellently on the flute; and
Themistocles, some years before, was deemed ignorant because at an
entertainment he declined the lyre when it was offered to him. For this
reason musicians flourished in Greece; music was a general study; and
whoever was unacquainted with it was not considered as fully instructed
in learning. Geometry was in high esteem with them, therefore none were
more honorable than mathematicians. But we have confined this art to
bare measuring and calculating.
III. But, on the contrary, we early entertained an esteem for the
orator; though he was not at first a man of learning, but only quick at
speaking: in subsequent times he became learned; for it is reported that
Galba, Africanus, and Lælius were men of learning; and that even Cato,
who preceded them in point of time, was a studious man: then succeeded
the Lepidi, Carbo, and Gracchi, and so many great orators after them,
down to our own times, that we were very little, if at all, inferior to
the Greeks. Philosophy has been at a low ebb even to this present time,
and has had no assistance from our own language, and so now I have
undertaken to raise and illustrate it, in order that, as I have been of
service to my countrymen, when employed on public affairs, I may, if
possible, be so likewise in my retirement; and in this I must take the
more pains, because there are already many books in the
11Latin language
which are said to be written inaccurately, having been composed by
excellent men, only not of sufficient learning; for, indeed, it is
possible that a man may think well, and yet not be able to express his
thoughts elegantly; but for any one to publish thoughts which he can
neither arrange skilfully nor illustrate so as to entertain his reader,
is an unpardonable abuse of letters and retirement: they, therefore,
read their books to one another, and no one ever takes them up but those
who wish to have the same license for careless writing allowed to
themselves. Wherefore, if oratory has acquired any reputation from my
industry, I shall take the more pains to open the fountains of
philosophy, from which all my eloquence has taken its rise.
IV. But, as Aristotle,
4 a man of the greatest genius, and of the most
various knowledge, being excited by the glory of the rhetorician
Isocrates,
5 commenced teaching young men to speak, and joined
philosophy with eloquence: so it is my design not to lay aside my former
study of oratory, and yet to employ myself at the same time in this
greater and more fruitful art; for I have always thought that to be able
to speak copiously and elegantly on the most important questions was the
most perfect philosophy. And I have so diligently applied myself to this
pursuit, that I have already ventured to have a school like the Greeks.
And lately when you left us, having many of my friends about me, I
attempted at my Tusculan villa what I could do in that way; for as I
formerly used to practise declaiming, which nobody continued longer than
myself, so this is now to be the declamation of my old age. I desired
any one to propose a question which he wished to have discussed, and
then I argued that point either sitting or walking; and so I have
compiled the scholæ, as the Greeks call them, of five days, in as many
books. We proceeded in this manner: when he who had proposed the subject
for discussion had said what he thought proper, I
12spoke against him;
for this is, you know, the old and Socratic method of arguing against
another’s opinion; for Socrates thought that thus the truth would more
easily be arrived at. But to give you a better notion of our
disputations, I will not barely send you an account of them, but
represent them to you as they were carried on; therefore let the
introduction be thus:
V.
A. To me death seems to be an evil.
M. What, to those who are already dead? or to those who must die?
A. To both.
M. It is a misery, then, because an evil?
A. Certainly.
M. Then those who have already died, and those who have still got to
die, are both miserable?
A. So it appears to me.
M. Then all are miserable?
A. Every one.
M. And, indeed, if you wish to be consistent, all that are already
born, or ever shall be, are not only miserable, but always will be so;
for should you maintain those only to be miserable, you would not except
any one living, for all must die; but there should be an end of misery
in death. But seeing that the dead are miserable, we are born to eternal
misery, for they must of consequence be miserable who died a hundred
thousand years ago; or rather, all that have ever been born.
A. So, indeed, I think.
M. Tell me, I beseech you, are you afraid of the three-headed Cerberus
in the shades below, and the roaring waves of Cocytus, and the passage
over Acheron, and Tantalus expiring with thirst, while the water touches
his chin; and Sisyphus,
Who sweats with arduous toil in vain
The steepy summit of the mount to gain?
Perhaps, too, you dread the inexorable judges, Minos and Rhadamanthus;
before whom neither L. Crassus nor M. Antonius can defend you; and
where, since the cause lies before Grecian judges, you will not even be
able to employ Demosthenes; but you must plead for yourself before a
13very great assembly. These things perhaps you dread, and therefore look
on death as an eternal evil.
VI. A. Do you take me to be so imbecile as to give credit to such
things?
M. What, do you not believe them?
A. Not in the least.
M. I am sorry to hear that.
A. Why, I beg?
M. Because I could have been very eloquent in speaking against them.
A. And who could not on such a subject? or what trouble is it to
refute these monstrous inventions of the poets and painters?6
M. And yet you have books of philosophers full of arguments against
these.
A. A great waste of time, truly! for who is so weak as to be concerned
about them?
M. If, then, there is no one miserable in the infernal regions, there
can be no one there at all.
A. I am altogether of that opinion.
M. Where, then, are those you call miserable? or what place do they
inhabit? For, if they exist at all, they must be somewhere.
A. I, indeed, am of opinion that they are nowhere.
M. Then they have no existence at all.
A. Even so, and yet they are miserable for this very reason, that they
have no existence.
M. I had rather now have you afraid of Cerberus than speak thus
inaccurately.
A. In what respect?
M. Because you admit him to exist whose existence you deny with the
same breath. Where now is your sagacity? When you say any one is
miserable, you say that he who does not exist, does exist.
A. I am not so absurd as to say that.
14M. What is it that you do say, then?
A. I say, for instance, that Marcus Crassus is miserable in being
deprived of such great riches as his by death; that Cn. Pompey is
miserable in being taken from such glory and honor; and, in short, that
all are miserable who are deprived of this light of life.
M. You have returned to the same point, for to be miserable implies an
existence; but you just now denied that the dead had any existence: if,
then, they have not, they can be nothing; and if so, they are not even
miserable.
A. Perhaps I do not express what I mean, for I look upon this very
circumstance, not to exist after having existed, to be very miserable.
M. What, more so than not to have existed at all? Therefore, those who
are not yet born are miserable because they are not; and we ourselves,
if we are to be miserable after death, were miserable before we were
born: but I do not remember that I was miserable before I was born; and
I should be glad to know, if your memory is better, what you recollect
of yourself before you were born.
VII. A. You are pleasant: as if I had said that those men are
miserable who are not born, and not that they are so who are dead.
M. You say, then, that they are so?
A. Yes; I say that because they no longer exist after having existed
they are miserable.
M. You do not perceive that you are asserting contradictions; for what
is a greater contradiction, than that that should be not only miserable,
but should have any existence at all, which does not exist? When you go
out at the Capene gate and see the tombs of the Calatini, the Scipios,
Servilii, and Metelli, do you look on them as miserable?
A. Because you press me with a word, henceforward I will not say they
are miserable absolutely, but miserable on this account, because they
have no existence.
M. You do not say, then, “M. Crassus is miserable,” but only
“Miserable M. Crassus.”
A. Exactly so.
M. As if it did not follow that whatever you speak of 15in that manner
either is or is not. Are you not acquainted with the first principles of
logic? For this is the first thing they lay down, Whatever is asserted
(for that is the best way that occurs to me, at the moment, of rendering
the Greek term бјЂОѕбЅ·П‰ОјО±; if I can think of a more accurate expression
hereafter, I will use it), is asserted as being either true or false.
When, therefore, you say, “Miserable M. Crassus,” you either say this,
“M. Crassus is miserable,” so that some judgment may be made whether it
is true or false, or you say nothing at all.
A. Well, then, I now own that the dead are not miserable, since you
have drawn from me a concession that they who do not exist at all can
not be miserable. What then? We that are alive, are we not wretched,
seeing we must die? for what is there agreeable in life, when we must
night and day reflect that, at some time or other, we must die?
VIII. M. Do you not, then, perceive how great is the evil from which
you have delivered human nature?
A. By what means?
M. Because, if to die were miserable to the dead, to live would be a
kind of infinite and eternal misery. Now, however, I see a goal, and
when I have reached it, there is nothing more to be feared; but you seem
to me to follow the opinion of Epicharmus,7 a man of some discernment,
and sharp enough for a Sicilian.
A. What opinion? for I do not recollect it.
M. I will tell you if I can in Latin; for you know I am no more used
to bring in Latin sentences in a Greek discourse than Greek in a Latin
one.
A. And that is right enough. But what is that opinion of Epicharmus?
M.
I would not die, but yet
Am not concerned that I shall be dead.
A. I now recollect the Greek; but since you have
16obliged me to grant
that the dead are not miserable, proceed to convince me that it is not
miserable to be under a necessity of dying.
M. That is easy enough; but I have greater things in hand.
A. How comes that to be so easy? And what are those things of more
consequence?
M. Thus: because, if there is no evil after death, then even death
itself can be none; for that which immediately succeeds that is a state
where you grant that there is no evil: so that even to be obliged to die
can be no evil, for that is only the being obliged to arrive at a place
where we allow that no evil is.
A. I beg you will be more explicit on this point, for these subtle
arguments force me sooner to admissions than to conviction. But what are
those more important things about which you say that you are occupied?
M. To teach you, if I can, that death is not only no evil, but a good.
A. I do not insist on that, but should be glad to hear you argue it,
for even though you should not prove your point, yet you will prove that
death is no evil. But I will not interrupt you; I would rather hear a
continued discourse.
M. What, if I should ask you a question, would you not answer?
A. That would look like pride; but I would rather you should not ask
but where necessity requires.
IX.
M. I will comply with your wishes, and explain as well as I can
what you require; but not with any idea that, like the Pythian Apollo,
what I say must needs be certain and indisputable, but as a mere man,
endeavoring to arrive at probabilities by conjecture, for I have no
ground to proceed further on than probability. Those men may call their
statements indisputable who assert that what they say can be perceived
by the senses, and who proclaim themselves philosophers by profession.
A. Do as you please: We are ready to hear you.
M. The first thing, then, is to inquire what death, which seems to be
so well understood, really is; for some imagine death to be the
departure of the soul from the body;
17others think that there is no such
departure, but that soul and body perish together, and that the soul is
extinguished with the body. Of those who think that the soul does depart
from the body, some believe in its immediate dissolution; others fancy
that it continues to exist for a time; and others believe that it lasts
forever. There is great dispute even what the soul is, where it is, and
whence it is derived: with some, the heart itself (
cor) seems to be
the soul, hence the expressions,
excordes,
vecordes,
concordes; and that
prudent Nasica, who was twice consul, was called Corculus,
i.e.,
wise-heart; and Г†lius Sextus is described as
Egregie cordatus
homo,
catus Æliu’ Sextus—that great
wise-hearted man, sage Г†lius.
Empedocles imagines the blood, which is suffused over the heart, to be
the soul; to others, a certain part of the brain seems to be the throne
of the soul; others neither allow the heart itself, nor any portion of
the brain, to be the soul, but think either that the heart is the seat
and abode of the soul, or else that the brain is so. Some would have the
soul, or spirit, to be the
anima, as our schools generally agree; and
indeed the name signifies as much, for we use the expressions
animam
agere, to live;
animam efflare, to expire;
animosi, men of spirit;
bene animati, men of right feeling;
exanimi sententia, according to
our real opinion; and the very word
animus is derived from
anima.
Again, the soul seems to Zeno the Stoic to be fire.
X. But what I have said as to the heart, the blood, the brain, air, or
fire being the soul, are common opinions: the others are only
entertained by individuals; and, indeed, there were many among the
ancients who held singular opinions on this subject, of whom the latest
was Aristoxenus, a man who was both a musician and a philosopher. He
maintained a certain straining of the body, like what is called harmony
in music, to be the soul, and believed that, from the figure and nature
of the whole body, various motions are excited, as sounds are from an
instrument. He adhered steadily to his system, and yet he said
something, the nature of which, whatever it was, had been detailed and
explained a great while before by Plato. Xenocrates denied that the soul
had any figure, or anything like a body; but said it was a number, the
power of which, as
18Pythagoras had fancied, some ages before, was the
greatest in nature: his master, Plato, imagined a threefold soul, a
dominant portion of which—that is to say, reason—he had lodged in the
head, as in a tower; and the other two parts—namely, anger and
desire—he made subservient to this one, and allotted them distinct
abodes, placing anger in the breast, and desire under the præcordia. But
Dicæarchus, in that discourse of some learned disputants, held at
Corinth, which he details to us in three books—in the first book
introduces many speakers; and in the other two he introduces a certain
Pherecrates, an old man of Phthia, who, as he said, was descended from
Deucalion; asserting, that there is in fact no such thing at all as a
soul, but that it is a name without a meaning; and that it is idle to
use the expression “animals,” or “animated beings;” that neither men nor
beasts have minds or souls, but that all that power by which we act or
perceive is equally infused into every living creature, and is
inseparable from the body, for if it were not, it would be nothing; nor
is there anything whatever really existing except body, which is a
single and simple thing, so fashioned as to live and have its sensations
in consequence of the regulations of nature. Aristotle, a man superior
to all others, both in genius and industry (I always except Plato),
after having embraced these four known sorts of principles, from which
all things deduce their origin, imagines that there is a certain fifth
nature, from whence comes the soul; for to think, to foresee, to learn,
to teach, to invent anything, and many other attributes of the same
kind, such as to remember, to love, to hate, to desire, to fear, to be
pleased or displeased—these, and others like them, exist, he thinks, in
none of those first four kinds: on such account he adds a fifth kind,
which has no name, and so by a new name he calls the soul
бјђОЅОґОµО»бЅіП‡ОµО№О±, as
if it were a certain continued and perpetual motion.
XI. If I have not forgotten anything unintentionally, these are the
principal opinions concerning the soul. I have omitted Democritus, a
very great man indeed, but one who deduces the soul from the fortuitous
concourse of small, light, and round substances; for, if you believe men
of his school, there is nothing which a crowd of atoms
19cannot effect.
Which of these opinions is true, some God must determine. It is an
important question for us, Which has the most appearance of truth? Shall
we, then, prefer determining between them, or shall we return to our
subject?
A. I could wish both, if possible; but it is difficult to mix them:
therefore, if without a discussion of them we can get rid of the fears
of death, let us proceed to do so; but if this is not to be done without
explaining the question about souls, let us have that now, and the other
at another time.
M. I take that plan to be the best, which I perceive you are inclined
to; for reason will demonstrate that, whichever of the opinions which I
have stated is true, it must follow, then, that death cannot be an evil;
or that it must rather be something desirable; for if either the heart,
or the blood, or the brain, is the soul, then certainly the soul, being
corporeal, must perish with the rest of the body; if it is air, it will
perhaps be dissolved; if it is fire, it will be extinguished; if it is
Aristoxenus’s harmony, it will be put out of tune. What shall I say of
Dicæarchus, who denies that there is any soul? In all these opinions,
there is nothing to affect any one after death; for all feeling is lost
with life, and where there is no sensation, nothing can interfere to
affect us. The opinions of others do indeed bring us hope; if it is any
pleasure to you to think that souls, after they leave the body, may go
to heaven as to a permanent home.
A. I have great pleasure in that thought, and it is what I most
desire; and even if it should not be so, I should still be very willing
to believe it.
M. What occasion have you, then, for my assistance? Am I superior to
Plato in eloquence? Turn over carefully his book that treats of the
soul; you will have there all that you can want.
A. I have, indeed, done that, and often; but, I know not how it comes
to pass, I agree with it while I am reading it; but when I have laid
down the book, and begin to reflect with myself on the immortality of
the soul, all that agreement vanishes.
M. How comes that? Do you admit this—that souls
20either exist after
death, or else that they also perish at the moment of death?
A. I agree to that. And if they do exist, I admit that they are happy;
but if they perish, I cannot suppose them to be unhappy, because, in
fact, they have no existence at all. You drove me to that concession but
just now.
M. How, then, can you, or why do you, assert that you think that death
is an evil, when it either makes us happy, in the case of the soul
continuing to exist, or, at all events, not unhappy, in the case of our
becoming destitute of all sensation?
XII.
A. Explain, therefore, if it is not troublesome to you, first, if
you can, that souls do exist after death; secondly, should you fail in
that (and it is a very difficult thing to establish), that death is free
from all evil; for I am not without my fears that this itself is an
evil: I do not mean the immediate deprivation of sense, but the fact
that we shall hereafter suffer deprivation.
M. I have the best authority in support of the opinion you desire to
have established, which ought, and generally has, great weight in all
cases. And, first, I have all antiquity on that side, which the more
near it is to its origin and divine descent, the more clearly, perhaps,
on that account, did it discern the truth in these matters. This very
doctrine, then, was adopted by all those ancients whom Ennius calls in
the Sabine tongue Casci; namely, that in death there was a sensation,
and that, when men departed this life, they were not so entirely
destroyed as to perish absolutely. And this may appear from many other
circumstances, and especially from the pontifical rites and funeral
obsequies, which men of the greatest genius would not have been so
solicitous about, and would not have guarded from any injury by such
severe laws, but from a firm persuasion that death was not so entire a
destruction as wholly to abolish and destroy everything, but rather a
kind of transmigration, as it were, and change of life, which was, in
the case of illustrious men and women, usually a guide to heaven, while
in that of others it was still confined to the earth, but in such a
manner as still to exist. From this, and the sentiments of the Romans,
In heaven Romulus with Gods now lives,
21as Ennius saith, agreeing with the common belief; hence, too, Hercules
is considered so great and propitious a God among the Greeks, and from
them he was introduced among us, and his worship has extended even to
the very ocean itself. This is how it was that Bacchus was deified, the
offspring of Semele; and from the same illustrious fame we receive
Castor and Pollux as Gods, who are reported not only to have helped the
Romans to victory in their battles, but to have been the messengers of
their success. What shall we say of Ino, the daughter of Cadmus? Is she
not called Leucothea by the Greeks, and Matuta by us? Nay, more; is not
the whole of heaven (not to dwell on particulars) almost filled with the
offspring of men?
Should I attempt to search into antiquity, and produce from thence what
the Greek writers have asserted, it would appear that even those who are
called their principal Gods were taken from among men up into heaven.
XIII. Examine the sepulchres of those which are shown in Greece;
recollect, for you have been initiated, what lessons are taught in the
mysteries; then will you perceive how extensive this doctrine is. But
they who were not acquainted with natural philosophy (for it did not
begin to be in vogue till many years later) had no higher belief than
what natural reason could give them; they were not acquainted with the
principles and causes of things; they were often induced by certain
visions, and those generally in the night, to think that those men who
had departed from this life were still alive. And this may further be
brought as an irrefragable argument for us to believe that there are
Gods—that there never was any nation so barbarous, nor any people in
the world so savage, as to be without some notion of Gods. Many have
wrong notions of the Gods, for that is the nature and ordinary
consequence of bad customs, yet all allow that there is a certain divine
nature and energy. Nor does this proceed from the conversation of men,
or the agreement of philosophers; it is not an opinion established by
institutions or by laws; but, no doubt, in every case the consent of all
nations is to be looked on as a law of nature. Who is there, then, that
does not lament the loss of his friends, principally from 22imagining
them deprived of the conveniences of life? Take away this opinion, and
you remove with it all grief; for no one is afflicted merely on account
of a loss sustained by himself. Perhaps we may be sorry, and grieve a
little; but that bitter lamentation and those mournful tears have their
origin in our apprehensions that he whom we loved is deprived of all the
advantages of life, and is sensible of his loss. And we are led to this
opinion by nature, without any arguments or any instruction.
XIV. But the greatest proof of all is, that nature herself gives a
silent judgment in favor of the immortality of the soul, inasmuch as all
are anxious, and that to a great degree, about the things which concern
futurity:
One plants what future ages shall enjoy,
as Statius saith in his Synephebi. What is his object in doing so,
except that he is interested in posterity? Shall the industrious
husbandman, then, plant trees the fruit of which he shall never see? And
shall not the great man found laws, institutions, and a republic? What
does the procreation of children imply, and our care to continue our
names, and our adoptions, and our scrupulous exactness in drawing up
wills, and the inscriptions on monuments, and panegyrics, but that our
thoughts run on futurity? There is no doubt but a judgment may be formed
of nature in general, from looking at each nature in its most perfect
specimens; and what is a more perfect specimen of a man than those are
who look on themselves as born for the assistance, the protection, and
the preservation of others? Hercules has gone to heaven; he never would
have gone thither had he not, while among men, made that road for
himself. These things are of old date, and have, besides, the sanction
of universal religion.
XV. What will you say? What do you imagine that so many and such great
men of our republic, who have sacrificed their lives for its good,
expected? Do you believe that they thought that their names should not
continue beyond their lives? None ever encountered death for their
country but under a firm persuasion of immortality! Themistocles might
have lived at his ease; so might Epaminondas; and, not to look abroad
and among the ancients 23for instances, so might I myself. But, somehow
or other there clings to our minds a certain presage of future ages; and
this both exists most firmly, and appears most clearly, in men of the
loftiest genius and greatest souls. Take away this, and who would be so
mad as to spend his life amidst toils and dangers? I speak of those in
power. What are the poet’s views but to be ennobled after death? What
else is the object of these lines,
Behold old Ennius here, who erst
Thy fathers’ great exploits rehearsed?
He is challenging the reward of glory from those men whose ancestors he
himself had ennobled by his poetry. And in the same spirit he says, in
another passage,
Let none with tears my funeral grace, for I
Claim from my works an immortality.
Why do I mention poets? The very mechanics are desirous of fame after
death. Why did Phidias include a likeness of himself in the shield of
Minerva, when he was not allowed to inscribe his name on it? What do our
philosophers think on the subject? Do not they put their names to those
very books which they write on the contempt of glory? If, then,
universal consent is the voice of nature, and if it is the general
opinion everywhere that those who have quitted this life are still
interested in something, we also must subscribe to that opinion. And if
we think that men of the greatest abilities and virtues see most clearly
into the power of nature, because they themselves are her most perfect
work, it is very probable that, as every great man is especially anxious
to benefit posterity, there is something of which he himself will be
sensible after death.
XVI. But as we are led by nature to think there are Gods, and as we
discover, by reason, of what description they are, so, by the consent of
all nations, we are induced to believe that our souls survive; but where
their habitation is, and of what character they eventually are, must be
learned from reason. The want of any certain reason on which to argue
has given rise to the idea of the shades below, and to those fears which
you seem, not without 24reason, to despise; for as our bodies fall to the
ground, and are covered with earth (humus), from whence we derive the
expression to be interred (humari), that has occasioned men to imagine
that the dead continue, during the remainder of their existence, under
ground; which opinion has drawn after it many errors, which the poets
have increased; for the theatre, being frequented by a large crowd,
among which are women and children, is wont to be greatly affected on
hearing such pompous verses as these,
Lo! here I am, who scarce could gain this place,
Through stony mountains and a dreary waste;
Through cliffs, whose sharpen’d stones tremendous hung,
Where dreadful darkness spread itself around.
And the error prevailed so much, though indeed at present it seems to me
to be removed, that although men knew that the bodies of the dead had
been burned, yet they conceived such things to be done in the infernal
regions as could not be executed or imagined without a body; for they
could not conceive how disembodied souls could exist; and, therefore,
they looked out for some shape or figure. This was the origin of all
that account of the dead in Homer. This was the idea that caused my
friend Appius to frame his Necromancy; and this is how there got about
that idea of the lake of Avernus, in my neighborhood,
From whence the souls of undistinguish’d shape,
Clad in thick shade, rush from the open gate
Of Acheron, vain phantoms of the dead.
And they must needs have these appearances speak, which is not possible
without a tongue, and a palate, and jaws, and without the help of lungs
and sides, and without some shape or figure; for they could see nothing
by their mind alone—they referred all to their eyes. To withdraw the
mind from sensual objects, and abstract our thoughts from what we are
accustomed to, is an attribute of great genius. I am persuaded, indeed,
that there were many such men in former ages; but Pherecydes8 the
Syrian is the 25first on record who said that the souls of men were
immortal, and he was a philosopher of great antiquity, in the reign of
my namesake Tullius. His disciple Pythagoras greatly confirmed this
opinion, who came into Italy in the reign of Tarquin the Proud; and all
that country which is called Great Greece was occupied by his school,
and he himself was held in high honor, and had the greatest authority;
and the Pythagorean sect was for many ages after in such great credit,
that all learning was believed to be confined to that name.
XVII. But I return to the ancients. They scarcely ever gave any reason
for their opinion but what could be explained by numbers or definitions.
It is reported of Plato that he came into Italy to make himself
acquainted with the Pythagoreans; and that when there, among others, he
made an acquaintance with Archytas9 and Timæus,10 and learned from
them all the tenets of the Pythagoreans; and that he not only was of the
same opinion with Pythagoras concerning the immortality of the soul, but
that he also brought reasons in support of it; which, if you have
nothing to say against it, I will pass over, and say no more at present
about all this hope of immortality.
A. What, will you leave me when you have raised my expectations so
high? I had rather, so help me Hercules! be mistaken with Plato, whom I
know how much you esteem, and whom I admire myself, from what you say of
him, than be in the right with those others.
26M. I commend you; for, indeed, I could myself willingly be mistaken
in his company. Do we, then, doubt, as we do in other cases (though I
think here is very little room for doubt in this case, for the
mathematicians prove the facts to us), that the earth is placed in the
midst of the world, being, as it were, a sort of point, which they call
a ОєбЅіОЅП„ПЃОїОЅ, surrounded by the whole heavens; and that such is the nature
of the four principles which are the generating causes of all things,
that they have equally divided among them the constituents of all
bodies; moreover, that earthy and humid bodies are carried at equal
angles by their own weight and ponderosity into the earth and sea; that
the other two parts consist, one of fire, and the other of air? As the
two former are carried by their gravity and weight into the middle
region of the world, so these, on the other hand, ascend by right lines
into the celestial regions, either because, owing to their intrinsic
nature, they are always endeavoring to reach the highest place, or else
because lighter bodies are naturally repelled by heavier; and as this is
notoriously the case, it must evidently follow that souls, when once
they have departed from the body, whether they are animal (by which term
I mean capable of breathing) or of the nature of fire, must mount
upward. But if the soul is some number, as some people assert, speaking
with more subtlety than clearness, or if it is that fifth nature, for
which it would be more correct to say that we have not given a name to
than that we do not correctly understand it—still it is too pure and
perfect not to go to a great distance from the earth. Something of this
sort, then, we must believe the soul to be, that we may not commit the
folly of thinking that so active a principle lies immerged in the heart
or brain; or, as Empedocles would have it, in the blood.
XVIII. We will pass over Dicæarchus,11 with his contemporary and
fellow-disciple Aristoxenus,12 both indeed 27men of learning. One of
them seems never even to have been affected with grief, as he could not
perceive that he had a soul; while the other is so pleased with his
musical compositions that he endeavors to show an analogy betwixt them
and souls. Now, we may understand harmony to arise from the intervals of
sounds, whose various compositions occasion many harmonies; but I do not
see how a disposition of members, and the figure of a body without a
soul, can occasion harmony. He had better, learned as he is, leave these
speculations to his master Aristotle, and follow his own trade as a
musician. Good advice is given him in that Greek proverb,
Apply your talents where you best are skill’d.
I will have nothing at all to do with that fortuitous concourse of
individual light and round bodies, notwithstanding Democritus insists on
their being warm and having breath, that is to say, life. But this soul,
which is compounded of either of the four principles from which we
assert that all things are derived, is of inflamed air, as seems
particularly to have been the opinion of Panætius, and must necessarily
mount upward; for air and fire have no tendency downward, but always
ascend; so should they be dissipated that must be at some distance from
the earth; but should they remain, and preserve their original state, it
is clearer still that they must be carried heavenward, and this gross
and concrete air, which is nearest the earth, must be divided and broken
by them; for the soul is warmer, or rather hotter, than that air, which
I just now called gross and concrete: and this may be made evident from
this consideration—that our bodies, being compounded of the earthy
class of principles, grow warm by the heat of the soul.
XIX. We may add, that the soul can the more easily escape from this air,
which I have often named, and break 28through it, because nothing is
swifter than the soul; no swiftness is comparable to the swiftness of
the soul, which, should it remain uncorrupt and without alteration, must
necessarily be carried on with such velocity as to penetrate and divide
all this atmosphere, where clouds, and rain, and winds are formed,
which, in consequence of the exhalations from the earth, is moist and
dark: but, when the soul has once got above this region, and falls in
with, and recognizes, a nature like its own, it then rests upon fires
composed of a combination of thin air and a moderate solar heat, and
does not aim at any higher flight; for then, after it has attained a
lightness and heat resembling its own, it moves no more, but remains
steady, being balanced, as it were, between two equal weights. That,
then, is its natural seat where it has penetrated to something like
itself, and where, wanting nothing further, it may be supported and
maintained by the same aliment which nourishes and maintains the stars.
Now, as we are usually incited to all sorts of desires by the stimulus
of the body, and the more so as we endeavor to rival those who are in
possession of what we long for, we shall certainly be happy when, being
emancipated from that body, we at the same time get rid of these desires
and this rivalry. And that which we do at present, when, dismissing all
other cares, we curiously examine and look into anything, we shall then
do with greater freedom; and we shall employ ourselves entirely in the
contemplation and examination of things; because there is naturally in
our minds a certain insatiable desire to know the truth, and the very
region itself where we shall arrive, as it gives us a more intuitive and
easy knowledge of celestial things, will raise our desires after
knowledge. For it was this beauty of the heavens, as seen even here upon
earth, which gave birth to that national and hereditary philosophy (as
Theophrastus calls it), which was thus excited to a desire of knowledge.
But those persons will in a most especial degree enjoy this philosophy,
who, while they were only inhabitants of this world and enveloped in
darkness, were still desirous of looking into these things with the eye
of their mind.
XX. For if those men now think that they have attained 29something who
have seen the mouth of the Pontus, and those straits which were passed
by the ship called Argo, because,
From Argos she did chosen men convey,
Bound to fetch back the Golden Fleece, their prey;
or those who have seen the straits of the ocean,
Where the swift waves divide the neighboring shores
Of Europe, and of Afric;
what kind of sight do you imagine that will be when the whole earth is
laid open to our view? and that, too, not only in its position, form,
and boundaries, nor those parts of it only which are habitable, but
those also that lie uncultivated, through the extremities of heat and
cold to which they are exposed; for not even now is it with our eyes
that we view what we see, for the body itself has no senses; but (as the
naturalists, ay, and even the physicians assure us, who have opened our
bodies, and examined them) there are certain perforated channels from
the seat of the soul to the eyes, ears, and nose; so that frequently,
when either prevented by meditation, or the force of some bodily
disorder, we neither hear nor see, though our eyes and ears are open and
in good condition; so that we may easily apprehend that it is the soul
itself which sees and hears, and not those parts which are, as it were,
but windows to the soul, by means of which, however, she can perceive
nothing, unless she is on the spot, and exerts herself. How shall we
account for the fact that by the same power of thinking we comprehend
the most different things—as color, taste, heat, smell, and
sound—which the soul could never know by her five messengers, unless
every thing were referred to her, and she were the sole judge of all?
And we shall certainly discover these things in a more clear and perfect
degree when the soul is disengaged from the body, and has arrived at
that goal to which nature leads her; for at present, notwithstanding
nature has contrived, with the greatest skill, those channels which lead
from the body to the soul, yet are they, in some way or other, stopped
up with earthy and concrete bodies; but when we shall be nothing but
soul, then nothing will interfere 30to prevent our seeing everything in
its real substance and in its true character.
XXI. It is true, I might expatiate, did the subject require it, on the
many and various objects with which the soul will be entertained in
those heavenly regions; when I reflect on which, I am apt to wonder at
the boldness of some philosophers, who are so struck with admiration at
the knowledge of nature as to thank, in an exulting manner, the first
inventor and teacher of natural philosophy, and to reverence him as a
God; for they declare that they have been delivered by his means from
the greatest tyrants, a perpetual terror, and a fear that molested them
by night and day. What is this dread—this fear? What old woman is there
so weak as to fear these things, which you, forsooth, had you not been
acquainted with natural philosophy, would stand in awe of?
The hallow’d roofs of Acheron, the dread
Of Orcus, the pale regions of the dead.
And does it become a philosopher to boast that he is not afraid of these
things, and that he has discovered them to be false? And from this we
may perceive how acute these men were by nature, who, if they had been
left without any instruction, would have believed in these things. But
now they have certainly made a very fine acquisition in learning that
when the day of their death arrives, they will perish entirely. And if
that really is the case—for I say nothing either way—what is there
agreeable or glorious in it? Not that I see any reason why the opinion
of Pythagoras and Plato may not be true; but even although Plato were to
have assigned no reason for his opinion (observe how much I esteem the
man), the weight of his authority would have borne me down; but he has
brought so many reasons, that he appears to me to have endeavored to
convince others, and certainly to have convinced himself.
XXII. But there are many who labor on the other side of the question,
and condemn souls to death, as if they were criminals capitally
convicted; nor have they any other reason to allege why the immortality
of the soul appears to them to be incredible, except that they are not
31able to conceive what sort of thing the soul can be when disentangled
from the body; just as if they could really form a correct idea as to
what sort of thing it is, even when it is in the body; what its form,
and size, and abode are; so that were they able to have a full view of
all that is now hidden from them in a living body, they have no idea
whether the soul would be discernible by them, or whether it is of so
fine a texture that it would escape their sight. Let those consider
this, who say that they are unable to form any idea of the soul without
the body, and then they will see whether they can form any adequate idea
of what it is when it is in the body. For my own part, when I reflect on
the nature of the soul, it appears to me a far more perplexing and
obscure question to determine what is its character while it is in the
body—a place which, as it were, does not belong to it—than to imagine
what it is when it leaves it, and has arrived at the free Г¦ther, which
is, if I may so say, its proper, its own habitation. For unless we are
to say that we cannot apprehend the character or nature of anything
which we have never seen, we certainly may be able to form some notion
of God, and of the divine soul when released from the body. Dicæarchus,
indeed, and Aristoxenus, because it was hard to understand the existence
and substance and nature of the soul, asserted that there was no such
thing as a soul at all. It is, indeed, the most difficult thing
imaginable to discern the soul by the soul. And this, doubtless, is the
meaning of the precept of Apollo, which advises every one to know
himself. For I do not apprehend the meaning of the God to have been that
we should understand our members, our stature, and form; for we are not
merely bodies; nor, when I say these things to you, am I addressing
myself to your body: when, therefore, he says, “Know yourself,” he says
this, “Inform yourself of the nature of your soul;” for the body is but
a kind of vessel, or receptacle of the soul, and whatever your soul does
is your own act. To know the soul, then, unless it had been divine,
would not have been a precept of such excellent wisdom as to be
attributed to a God; but even though the soul should not know of what
nature itself is, will you say that it does not even perceive that 32it
exists at all, or that it has motion? On which is founded that reason
of Plato’s, which is explained by Socrates in the Phædrus, and inserted
by me, in my sixth book of the Republic.
XXIII. “That which is always moved is eternal; but that which gives
motion to something else, and is moved itself by some external cause,
when that motion ceases, must necessarily cease to exist. That,
therefore, alone, which is self-moved, because it is never forsaken by
itself, can never cease to be moved. Besides, it is the beginning and
principle of motion to everything else; but whatever is a principle has
no beginning, for all things arise from that principle, and it cannot
itself owe its rise to anything else; for then it would not be a
principle did it proceed from anything else. But if it has no beginning,
it never will have any end; for a principle which is once extinguished
cannot itself be restored by anything else, nor can it produce anything
else from itself; inasmuch as all things must necessarily arise from
some first cause. And thus it comes about that the first principle of
motion must arise from that thing which is itself moved by itself; and
that can neither have a beginning nor an end of its existence, for
otherwise the whole heaven and earth would be overset, and all nature
would stand still, and not be able to acquire any force by the impulse
of which it might be first set in motion. Seeing, then, that it is clear
that whatever moves itself is eternal, can there be any doubt that the
soul is so? For everything is inanimate which is moved by an external
force; but everything which is animate is moved by an interior force,
which also belongs to itself. For this is the peculiar nature and power
of the soul; and if the soul be the only thing in the whole world which
has the power of self-motion, then certainly it never had a beginning,
and therefore it is eternal.”
Now, should all the lower order of philosophers (for so I think they may
be called who dissent from Plato and Socrates and that school) unite
their force, they never would be able to explain anything so elegantly
as this, nor even to understand how ingeniously this conclusion is
drawn. The soul, then, perceives itself to have motion, 33and at the same
time that it gets that perception, it is sensible that it derives that
motion from its own power, and not from the agency of another; and it is
impossible that it should ever forsake itself. And these premises compel
you to allow its eternity, unless you have something to say against
them.
A. I should myself be very well pleased not to have even a thought
arise in my mind against them, so much am I inclined to that opinion.
XXIV. M. Well, then, I appeal to you, if the arguments which prove
that there is something divine in the souls of men are not equally
strong? But if I could account for the origin of these divine
properties, then I might also be able to explain how they might cease to
exist; for I think I can account for the manner in which the blood, and
bile, and phlegm, and bones, and nerves, and veins, and all the limbs,
and the shape of the whole body, were put together and made; ay, and
even as to the soul itself, were there nothing more in it than a
principle of life, then the life of a man might be put upon the same
footing as that of a vine or any other tree, and accounted for as caused
by nature; for these things, as we say, live. Besides, if desires and
aversions were all that belonged to the soul, it would have them only in
common with the beasts; but it has, in the first place, memory, and
that, too, so infinite as to recollect an absolute countless number of
circumstances, which Plato will have to be a recollection of a former
life; for in that book which is inscribed Menon, Socrates asks a child
some questions in geometry, with reference to measuring a square; his
answers are such as a child would make, and yet the questions are so
easy, that while answering them, one by one, he comes to the same point
as if he had learned geometry. From whence Socrates would infer that
learning is nothing more than recollection; and this topic he explains
more accurately in the discourse which he held the very day he died; for
he there asserts that, any one, who seeming to be entirely illiterate,
is yet able to answer a question well that is proposed to him, does in
so doing manifestly show that he is not learning it then, but
recollecting it by his memory. Nor is it to be accounted for in any
other way, how children 34come to have notions of so many and such
important things as are implanted, and, as it were, sealed up, in their
minds (which the Greeks call бј”ОЅОЅОїО№О±О№), unless the soul, before it
entered the body, had been well stored with knowledge. And as it had no
existence at all (for this is the invariable doctrine of Plato, who will
not admit anything to have a real existence which has a beginning and an
end, and who thinks that that alone does really exist which is of such a
character as what he calls ОµбјґОґОµО±, and we species), therefore, being shut
up in the body, it could not while in the body discover what it knows;
but it knew it before, and brought the knowledge with it, so that we are
no longer surprised at its extensive and multifarious knowledge. Nor
does the soul clearly discover its ideas at its first resort to this
abode to which it is so unaccustomed, and which is in so disturbed a
state; but after having refreshed and recollected itself, it then by its
memory recovers them; and, therefore, to learn implies nothing more than
to recollect. But I am in a particular manner surprised at memory. For
what is that faculty by which we remember? what is its force? what its
nature? I am not inquiring how great a memory Simonides13 may be said
to have had, or Theodectes,14 or that Cineas15 who was sent to Rome
as ambassador from Pyrrhus; or, in more modern times, Charmadas;16 or,
very lately, Metrodorus17 35the Scepsian, or our own contemporary
Hortensius18: I am speaking of ordinary memory, and especially of
those men who are employed in any important study or art, the great
capacity of whose minds it is hard to estimate, such numbers of things
do they remember.
XXV. Should you ask what this leads to, I think we may understand what
that power is, and whence we have it. It certainly proceeds neither from
the heart, nor from the blood, nor from the brain, nor from atoms;
whether it be air or fire, I know not, nor am I, as those men are,
ashamed, in cases where I am ignorant, to own that I am so. If in any
other obscure matter I were able to assert anything positively, then I
would swear that the soul, be it air or fire, is divine. Just think, I
beseech you: can you imagine this wonderful power of memory to be sown
in or to be a part of the composition of the earth, or of this dark and
gloomy atmosphere? Though you cannot apprehend what it is, yet you see
what kind of thing it is, or if you do not quite see that, yet you
certainly see how great it is. What, then? Shall we imagine that there
is a kind of measure in the soul, into which, as into a vessel, all that
we remember is poured? That indeed is absurd; for how shall we form any
idea of the bottom, or of the shape or fashion of such a soul as that?
And, again, how are we to conceive how much it is able to contain? Shall
we imagine the soul to receive impressions like wax, and memory to be
marks of the impressions made on the soul? What are the characters of
the words, what of the facts themselves? and what, again, is that
prodigious greatness which can give rise to impressions of so many
things? What, lastly, is that power which investigates secret things,
and is called invention and contrivance? Does that man seem to be
compounded of this earthly, mortal, and perishing nature who first
invented names for everything; 36which, if you will believe Pythagoras,
is the highest pitch of wisdom? or he who collected the dispersed
inhabitants of the world, and united them in the bonds of social life?
or he who confined the sounds of the voice, which used to seem infinite,
to the marks of a few letters? or he who first observed the courses of
the planets, their progressive motions, their laws? These were all great
men. But they were greater still who invented food, and raiment, and
houses; who introduced civilization among us, and armed us against the
wild beasts; by whom we were made sociable and polished, and so
proceeded from the necessaries of life to its embellishments. For we
have provided great entertainments for the ears by inventing and
modulating the variety and nature of sounds; we have learned to survey
the stars, not only those that are fixed, but also those which are
improperly called wandering; and the man who has acquainted himself with
all their revolutions and motions is fairly considered to have a soul
resembling the soul of that Being who has created those stars in the
heavens: for when Archimedes described in a sphere the motions of the
moon, sun, and five planets, he did the very same thing as Plato’s God,
in his Timæus, who made the world, causing one revolution to adjust
motions differing as much as possible in their slowness and velocity.
Now, allowing that what we see in the world could not be effected
without a God, Archimedes could not have imitated the same motions in
his sphere without a divine soul.
XXVI. To me, indeed, it appears that even those studies which are more
common and in greater esteem are not without some divine energy: so that
I do not consider that a poet can produce a serious and sublime poem
without some divine impulse working on his mind; nor do I think that
eloquence, abounding with sonorous words and fruitful sentences, can
flow thus without something beyond mere human power. But as to
philosophy, that is the parent of all the arts: what can we call that
but, as Plato says, a gift, or, as I express it, an invention, of the
Gods? This it was which first taught us the worship of the Gods; and
then led us on to justice, which arises from the human race being formed
into society; and after that 37it imbued us with modesty and elevation of
soul. This it was which dispersed darkness from our souls, as it is
dispelled from our eyes, enabling us to see all things that are above or
below, the beginning, end, and middle of everything. I am convinced
entirely that that which could effect so many and such great things must
be a divine power. For what is memory of words and circumstances? What,
too, is invention? Surely they are things than which nothing greater can
be conceived in a God! For I do not imagine the Gods to be delighted
with nectar and ambrosia, or with Juventas presenting them with a cup;
nor do I put any faith in Homer, who says that Ganymede was carried away
by the Gods on account of his beauty, in order to give Jupiter his wine.
Too weak reasons for doing Laomedon such injury! These were mere
inventions of Homer, who gave his Gods the imperfections of men. I would
rather that he had given men the perfections of the Gods! those
perfections, I mean, of uninterrupted health, wisdom, invention, memory.
Therefore the soul (which is, as I say, divine) is, as Euripides more
boldly expresses it, a God. And thus, if the divinity be air or fire,
the soul of man is the same; for as that celestial nature has nothing
earthly or humid about it, in like manner the soul of man is also free
from both these qualities: but if it is of that fifth kind of nature,
first introduced by Aristotle, then both Gods and souls are of the same.
XXVII. As this is my opinion, I have explained it in these very words,
in my book on Consolation.19 The origin of the soul of man is not to
be found upon earth, for there is nothing in the soul of a mixed or
concrete nature, or that has any appearance of being formed or made out
of the earth; nothing even humid, or airy, or fiery. For what is there
in natures of that kind which has the power of memory, understanding, or
thought? which can recollect the past, foresee the future, and
comprehend the present? for these capabilities are confined to divine
beings; nor can we discover any source from which men could derive them,
but from God. There is therefore a peculiar 38nature and power in the
soul, distinct from those natures which are more known and familiar to
us. Whatever, then, that is which thinks, and which has understanding,
and volition, and a principle of life, is heavenly and divine, and on
that account must necessarily be eternal; nor can God himself, who is
known to us, be conceived to be anything else except a soul free and
unembarrassed, distinct from all mortal concretion, acquainted with
everything, and giving motion to everything, and itself endued with
perpetual motion.
XXVIII. Of this kind and nature is the intellect of man. Where, then, is
this intellect seated, and of what character is it? where is your own,
and what is its character? Are you able to tell? If I have not faculties
for knowing all that I could desire to know, will you not even allow me
to make use of those which I have? The soul has not sufficient capacity
to comprehend itself; yet, the soul, like the eye, though it has no
distinct view of itself, sees other things: it does not see (which is of
least consequence) its own shape; perhaps not, though it possibly may;
but we will pass that by: but it certainly sees that it has vigor,
sagacity, memory, motion, and velocity; these are all great, divine,
eternal properties. What its appearance is, or where it dwells, it is
not necessary even to inquire. As when we behold, first of all, the
beauty and brilliant appearance of the heavens; secondly, the vast
velocity of its revolutions, beyond power of our imagination to
conceive; then the vicissitudes of nights and days, the fourfold
division of the seasons, so well adapted to the ripening of the fruits
of the earth, and the temperature of our bodies: and after that we look
up to the sun, the moderator and governor of all these things; and view
the moon, by the increase and decrease of its light, marking, as it
were, and appointing our holy days; and see the five planets, borne on
in the same circle, divided into twelve parts, preserving the same
course with the greatest regularity, but with utterly dissimilar motions
among themselves; and the nightly appearance of the heaven, adorned on
all sides with stars; then, the globe of the earth, raised above the
sea, and placed in the centre of the universe, inhabited and cultivated
in its two opposite extremities, one of which, the 39place of our
habitation, is situated towards the north pole, under the seven stars:
Where the cold northern blasts, with horrid sound,
Harden to ice the snowy cover’d ground;
the other, towards the south pole, is unknown to us, but is called by
the Greeks бјЂОЅП„бЅ·П‡ОёОїОЅО±: the other parts are uncultivated, because they are
either frozen with cold, or burned up with heat; but where we dwell, it
never fails, in its season,
To yield a placid sky, to bid the trees
Assume the lively verdure of their leaves:
The vine to bud, and, joyful, in its shoots,
Foretell the approaching vintage of its fruits:
The ripen’d corn to sing, while all around
Full riv’lets glide; and flowers deck the ground:
then the multitude of cattle, fit part for food, part for tilling the
ground, others for carrying us, or for clothing us; and man himself,
made, as it were, on purpose to contemplate the heavens and the Gods,
and to pay adoration to them: lastly, the whole earth, and wide
extending seas, given to man’s use. When we view these and numberless
other things, can we doubt that they have some being who presides over
them, or has made them (if, indeed, they have been made, as is the
opinion of Plato, or if, as Aristotle thinks, they are eternal), or who
at all events is the regulator of so immense a fabric and so great a
blessing to men? Thus, though you see not the soul of man, as you see
not the Deity, yet, as by the contemplation of his works you are led to
acknowledge a God, so you must own the divine power of the soul, from
its remembering things, from its invention, from the quickness of its
motion, and from all the beauty of virtue. Where, then, is it seated,
you will say?
XXIX. In my opinion, it is seated in the head, and I can bring you
reasons for my adopting that opinion. At present, let the soul reside
where it will, you certainly have one in you. Should you ask what its
nature is? It has one peculiarly its own; but admitting it to consist of
fire, or air, it does not affect the present question. Only observe
this, that as you are convinced there is a God, though 40you are ignorant
where he resides, and what shape he is of; in like manner you ought to
feel assured that you have a soul, though you cannot satisfy yourself of
the place of its residence, nor its form. In our knowledge of the soul,
unless we are grossly ignorant of natural philosophy, we cannot but be
satisfied that it has nothing but what is simple, unmixed, uncompounded,
and single; and if this is admitted, then it cannot be separated, nor
divided, nor dispersed, nor parted, and therefore it cannot perish; for
to perish implies a parting-asunder, a division, a disunion, of those
parts which, while it subsisted, were held together by some band. And it
was because he was influenced by these and similar reasons that Socrates
neither looked out for anybody to plead for him when he was accused, nor
begged any favor from his judges, but maintained a manly freedom, which
was the effect not of pride, but of the true greatness of his soul; and
on the last day of his life he held a long discourse on this subject;
and a few days before, when he might have been easily freed from his
confinement, he refused to be so; and when he had almost actually hold
of that deadly cup, he spoke with the air of a man not forced to die,
but ascending into heaven.
XXX. For so indeed he thought himself, and thus he spoke: “That there
were two ways, and that the souls of men, at their departure from the
body, took different roads; for those which were polluted with vices
that are common to men, and which had given themselves up entirely to
unclean desires, and had become so blinded by them as to have habituated
themselves to all manner of debauchery and profligacy, or to have laid
detestable schemes for the ruin of their country, took a road wide of
that which led to the assembly of the Gods; but they who had preserved
themselves upright and chaste, and free from the slightest contagion of
the body, and had always kept themselves as far as possible at a
distance from it, and while on earth had proposed to themselves as a
model the life of the Gods, found the return to those beings from whom
they had come an easy one.” Therefore, he argues, that all good and wise
men should take example from the swans, who are considered sacred to
Apollo, not without reason, but particularly because they seem to have
received 41the gift of divination from him, by which, foreseeing how
happy it is to die, they leave this world with singing and joy. Nor can
any one doubt of this, unless it happens to us who think with care and
anxiety about the soul (as is often the case with those who look
earnestly at the setting sun), to lose the sight of it entirely; and so
the mind’s eye, viewing itself, sometimes grows dull, and for that
reason we become remiss in our contemplation. Thus our reasoning is
borne about, harassed with doubts and anxieties, not knowing how to
proceed, but measuring back again those dangerous tracts which it has
passed, like a boat tossed about on the boundless ocean. But these
reflections are of long standing, and borrowed from the Greeks. But Cato
left this world in such a manner as if he were delighted that he had
found an opportunity of dying; for that God who presides in us forbids
our departure hence without his leave. But when God himself has given us
a just cause, as formerly he did to Socrates, and lately to Cato, and
often to many others—in such a case, certainly every man of sense would
gladly exchange this darkness for that light: not that he would forcibly
break from the chains that held him, for that would be against the law;
but, like a man released from prison by a magistrate or some lawful
authority, so he too would walk away, being released and discharged by
God. For the whole life of a philosopher is, as the same philosopher
says, a meditation on death.
XXXI. For what else is it that we do, when we call off our minds from
pleasure, that is to say, from our attention to the body, from the
managing our domestic estate, which is a sort of handmaid and servant of
the body, or from duties of a public nature, or from all other serious
business whatever? What else is it, I say, that we do, but invite the
soul to reflect on itself? oblige it to converse with itself, and, as
far as possible, break off its acquaintance with the body? Now, to
separate the soul from the body, is to learn to die, and nothing else
whatever. Wherefore take my advice; and let us meditate on this, and
separate ourselves as far as possible from the body, that is to say, let
us accustom ourselves to die. This will be enjoying a life like that of
heaven even while we remain on earth; and 42when we are carried thither
and released from these bonds, our souls will make their progress with
more rapidity; for the spirit which has always been fettered by the
bonds of the body, even when it is disengaged, advances more slowly,
just as those do who have worn actual fetters for many years: but when
we have arrived at this emancipation from the bonds of the body, then
indeed we shall begin to live, for this present life is really death,
which I could say a good deal in lamentation for if I chose.
A. You have lamented it sufficiently in your book on Consolation; and
when I read that, there is nothing which I desire more than to leave
these things; but that desire is increased a great deal by what I have
just heard.
M. The time will come, and that soon, and with equal certainty,
whether you hang back or press forward; for time flies. But death is so
far from being an evil, as it lately appeared to you, that I am inclined
to suspect, not that there is no other thing which is an evil to man,
but rather that there is nothing else which is a real good to him; if,
at least, it is true that we become thereby either Gods ourselves, or
companions of the Gods. However, this is not of so much consequence, as
there are some of us here who will not allow this. But I will not leave
off discussing this point till I have convinced you that death can, upon
no consideration whatever, be an evil.
A. How can it, after what I now know?
M. Do you ask how it can? There are crowds of arguers who contradict
this; and those not only Epicureans, whom I regard very little, but,
somehow or other, almost every man of letters; and, above all, my
favorite Dicæarchus is very strenuous in opposing the immortality of the
soul: for he has written three books, which are entitled Lesbiacs,
because the discourse was held at Mitylene, in which he seeks to prove
that souls are mortal. The Stoics, on the other hand, allow us as long a
time for enjoyment as the life of a raven; they allow the soul to exist
a great while, but are against its eternity.
XXXII. Are you willing to hear then why, even allowing this, death
cannot be an evil.
A. As you please; but no one shall drive me from my belief in
mortality.
43M. I commend you, indeed, for that; though we should not be too
confident in our belief of anything; for we are frequently disturbed by
some subtle conclusion. We give way and change our opinions even in
things that are more evident than this; for in this there certainly is
some obscurity. Therefore, should anything of this kind happen, it is
well to be on our guard.
A. You are right in that; but I will provide against any accident.
M. Have you any objection to our dismissing our friends the
Stoics—those, I mean, who allow that the souls exist after they have
left the body, but yet deny that they exist forever?
A. We certainly may dismiss the consideration of those men who admit
that which is the most difficult point in the whole question, namely,
that a soul can exist independently of the body, and yet refuse to grant
that which is not only very easy to believe, but which is even the
natural consequence of the concession which they have made—that if they
can exist for a length of time; they most likely do so forever.
M. You take it right; that is the very thing. Shall we give,
therefore, any credit to Pauæstius, when he dissents from his master,
Plato? whom he everywhere calls divine, the wisest, the holiest of men,
the Homer of philosophers, and whom he opposes in nothing except this
single opinion of the soul’s immortality: for he maintains what nobody
denies, that everything which has been generated will perish, and that
even souls are generated, which he thinks appears from their resemblance
to those of the men who begot them; for that likeness is as apparent in
the turn of their minds as in their bodies. But he brings another
reason—that there is nothing which is sensible of pain which is not
also liable to disease; but whatever is liable to disease must be liable
to death. The soul is sensible of pain, therefore it is liable to
perish.
XXXIII. These arguments may be refuted; for they proceed from his not
knowing that, while discussing the subject of the immortality of the
soul, he is speaking of the intellect, which is free from all turbid
motion; but not of those parts of the mind in which those disorders,
44anger and lust, have their seat, and which he whom he is opposing, when
he argues thus, imagines to be distinct and separate from the mind. Now
this resemblance is more remarkable in beasts, whose souls are void of
reason. But the likeness in men consists more in the configuration of
the bodies: and it is of no little consequence in what bodies the soul
is lodged; for there are many things which depend on the body that give
an edge to the soul, many which blunt it. Aristotle, indeed, says that
all men of great genius are melancholy; so that I should not have been
displeased to have been somewhat duller than I am. He instances many,
and, as if it were matter of fact, brings his reasons for it. But if the
power of those things that proceed from the body be so great as to
influence the mind (for they are the things, whatever they are, that
occasion this likeness), still that does not necessarily prove why a
similitude of souls should be generated. I say nothing about cases of
unlikeness. I wish Panætius could be here: he lived with Africanus. I
would inquire of him which of his family the nephew of Africanus’s
brother was like? Possibly he may in person have resembled his father;
but in his manners he was so like every profligate, abandoned man, that
it was impossible to be more so. Whom did the grandson of P. Crassus,
that wise and eloquent and most distinguished man, resemble? Or the
relations and sons of many other excellent men, whose names there is no
occasion to mention? But what are we doing? Have we forgotten that our
purpose was, when we had sufficiently spoken on the subject of the
immortality of the soul, to prove that, even if the soul did perish,
there would be, even then, no evil in death?
A. I remembered it very well; but I had no dislike to your digressing
a little from your original design, while you were talking of the soul’s
immortality.
M. I perceive you have sublime thoughts, and are eager to mount up to
heaven.
XXXIV. I am not without hopes myself that such may be our fate. But
admit what they assert—that the soul does not continue to exist after
death.
A. Should it be so, I see that we are then deprived of the hopes of a
happier life.
45M. But what is there of evil in that opinion? For let the soul perish
as the body: is there any pain, or indeed any feeling at all, in the
body after death? No one, indeed asserts that; though Epicurus charges
Democritus with saying so; but the disciples of Democritus deny it. No
sense, therefore, remains in the soul; for the soul is nowhere. Where,
then, is the evil? for there is nothing but these two things. Is it
because the mere separation of the soul and body cannot be effected
without pain? But even should that be granted, how small a pain must
that be! Yet I think that it is false, and that it is very often
unaccompanied by any sensation at all, and sometimes even attended with
pleasure; but certainly the whole must be very trifling, whatever it is,
for it is instantaneous. What makes us uneasy, or rather gives us pain,
is the leaving all the good things of life. But just consider if I might
not more properly say, leaving the evils of life; only there is no
reason for my now occupying myself in bewailing the life of man, and yet
I might, with very good reason. But what occasion is there, when what I
am laboring to prove is that no one is miserable after death, to make
life more miserable by lamenting over it? I have done that in the book
which I wrote, in order to comfort myself as well as I could. If, then,
our inquiry is after truth, death withdraws us from evil, not from good.
This subject is indeed so copiously handled by Hegesias, the Cyrenaic
philosopher, that he is said to have been forbidden by Ptolemy from
delivering his lectures in the schools, because some who heard him made
away with themselves. There is, too, an epigram of Callimachus20 on
Cleombrotus of Ambracia, who, without any misfortune having befallen
him, as he says, threw himself from a wall into the sea, after he had
read a book of Plato’s. The book I mentioned of that Hegesias is called
Ἀποκαρτερτερῶν, or “A Man who
46starves himself,” in which a man is represented as killing
himself by starvation, till he is prevented by his friends,
in reply to whom he reckons up all the miseries of human
life. I might do the same, though not so fully as he, who
thinks it not worth any man’s while to live. I pass over
others. Was it even worth my while to live, for, had I
died before I was deprived of the comforts of my own
family, and of the honors which I received for my public
services, would not death have taken me from the evils of
life rather than from its blessings?
XXXV. Mention, therefore, some one, who never knew
distress; who never received any blow from fortune.
The great Metellus had four distinguished sons; but
Priam had fifty, seventeen of whom were born to him by
his lawful wife. Fortune had the same power over both,
though she exercised it but on one; for Metellus was laid
on his funeral pile by a great company of sons and daughters,
grandsons, and granddaughters; but Priam fell by
the hand of an enemy, after having fled to the altar, and
having seen himself deprived of all his numerous progeny.
Had he died before the death of his sons and the ruin of
his kingdom,
With all his mighty wealth elate,
Under rich canopies of state;
would he then have been taken from good or from evil?
It would indeed, at that time, have appeared that he was
being taken away from good; yet surely it would have
turned out advantageous for him; nor should we have
had these mournful verses,
Lo! these all perish’d in one flaming pile;
The foe old Priam did of life beguile,
And with his blood, thy altar, Jove, defile.
As if anything better could have happened to him at that
time than to lose his life in that manner; but yet, if it had
befallen him sooner, it would have prevented all those consequences;
but even as it was, it released him from any
further sense of them. The case of our friend Pompey21
47was something better: once, when he had been very ill
at Naples, the Neapolitans, on his recovery, put crowns
on their heads, as did those of Puteoli; the people flocked
from the country to congratulate him—it is a Grecian
custom, and a foolish one; still it is a sign of good fortune.
But the question is, had he died, would he have
been taken from good, or from evil? Certainly from
evil. He would not have been engaged in a war with his
father-in-law;22 he would not have taken up arms before
he was prepared; he would not have left his own house,
nor fled from Italy; he would not, after the loss of his
army, have fallen unarmed into the hands of slaves, and
been put to death by them; his children would not have
been destroyed; nor would his whole fortune have come
into the possession of the conquerors. Did not he, then,
who, if he had died at that time, would have died in all
his glory, owe all the great and terrible misfortunes into
which he subsequently fell to the prolongation of his life
at that time?
XXXVI. These calamities are avoided by death, for
even though they should never happen, there is a possibility
that they may; but it never occurs to a man that such
a disaster may befall him himself. Every one hopes to
be as happy as Metellus: as if the number of the happy
exceeded that of the miserable; or as if there were any
certainty in human affairs; or, again, as if there were
more rational foundation for hope than fear. But should
we grant them even this, that men are by death deprived
of good things; would it follow that the dead are therefore
in need of the good things of life, and are miserable
on that account? Certainly they must necessarily say so.
Can he who does not exist be in need of anything? To
be in need of has a melancholy sound, because it in effect
amounts to this—he had, but he has not; he regrets, he
looks back upon, he wants. Such are, I suppose, the distresses
48of one who is in need of. Is he deprived
of eyes? to be blind is misery. Is he destitute of children? not to have
them is misery. These considerations apply to the living, but the dead
are neither in need of the blessings of life, nor of life itself. But
when I am speaking of the dead, I am speaking of those who have no
existence. But would any one say of us, who do exist, that we want horns
or wings? Certainly not. Should it be asked, why not? the answer would
be, that not to have what neither custom nor nature has fitted you for
would not imply a want of them, even though you were sensible that you
had them not. This argument should be pressed over and over again, after
that point has once been established, which, if souls are mortal, there
can be no dispute about—I mean, that the destruction of them by death
is so entire as to remove even the least suspicion of any sense
remaining. When, therefore, this point is once well grounded and
established, we must correctly define what the term to want means; that
there may be no mistake in the word. To want, then, signifies this: to
be without that which you would be glad to have; for inclination for a
thing is implied in the word want, excepting when we use the word in an
entirely different sense, as we do when we say that a fever is wanting
to any one. For it admits of a different interpretation, when you are
without a certain thing, and are sensible that you are without it, but
yet can easily dispense with having it. “To want,” then, is an
expression which you cannot apply to the dead; nor is the mere fact of
wanting something necessarily lamentable. The proper expression ought to
be, “that they want a good,” and that is an evil.
But a living man does not want a good, unless he is distressed without
it; and yet, we can easily understand how any man alive can be without a
kingdom. But this cannot be predicated of you with any accuracy: it
might have been asserted of Tarquin, when he was driven from his
kingdom. But when such an expression is used respecting the dead, it is
absolutely unintelligible. For to want implies to be sensible; but the
dead are insensible: therefore, the dead can be in no want.
XXXVII. But what occasion is there to philosophize 49here in a matter
with which we see that philosophy is but little concerned? How often
have not only our generals but whole armies, rushed on certain death!
But if it had been a thing to be feared, L. Brutus would never have
fallen in fight, to prevent the return of that tyrant whom he had
expelled; nor would Decius the father have been slain in fighting with
the Latins; nor would his son, when engaged with the Etruscans, nor his
grandson with Pyrrhus have exposed themselves to the enemy’s darts.
Spain would never have seen, in one campaign, the Scipios fall fighting
for their country; nor would the plains of Cannæ have witnessed the
death of Paulus and Geminus, or Venusia that of Marcellus; nor would the
Latins have beheld the death of Albinus, nor the Leucanians that of
Gracchus. But are any of these miserable now? Nay, they were not so even
at the first moment after they had breathed their last; nor can any one
be miserable after he has lost all sensation. Oh, but the mere
circumstance of being without sensation is miserable. It might be so if
being without sensation were the same thing as wanting it; but as it is
evident there can be nothing of any kind in that which has no existence,
what can there be afflicting to that which can neither feel want nor be
sensible of anything? We might be said to have repeated this over too
often, only that here lies all that the soul shudders at from the fear
of death. For whoever can clearly apprehend that which is as manifest as
the light—that when both soul and body are consumed, and there is a
total destruction, then that which was an animal becomes nothing—will
clearly see that there is no difference between a Hippocentaur, which
never had existence, and King Agamemnon, and that M. Camillus is no more
concerned about this present civil war than I was at the sacking of
Rome, when he was living.
XXXVIII. Why, then, should Camillus be affected with the thoughts of
these things happening three hundred and fifty years after his time? And
why should I be uneasy it I were to expect that some nation might
possess itself of this city ten thousand years hence? Because so great
is our regard for our country, as not to be measured by our own feeling,
but by its own actual safety.
50Death, then, which threatens us daily from a thousand accidents, and
which, by reason of the shortness of life, can never be far off, does
not deter a wise man from making such provision for his country and his
family as he hopes may last forever; and from regarding posterity, of
which he can never have any real perception, as belonging to himself.
Wherefore a man may act for eternity, even though he be persuaded that
his soul is mortal; not, indeed, from a desire of glory, which he will
be insensible of, but from a principle of virtue, which glory will
inevitably attend, though that is not his object. The process, indeed,
of nature is this: that just in the same manner as our birth was the
beginning of things with us, so death will be the end; and as we were
noways concerned with anything before we were born, so neither shall we
be after we are dead. And in this state of things where can the evil be,
since death has no connection with either the living or the dead? The
one have no existence at all, the other are not yet affected by it. They
who make the least of death consider it as having a great resemblance to
sleep; as if any one would choose to live ninety years on condition
that, at the expiration of sixty, he should sleep out the remainder. The
very swine would not accept of life on those terms, much less I.
Endymion, indeed, if you listen to fables, slept once on a time on
Latmus, a mountain of Caria, and for such a length of time that I
imagine he is not as yet awake. Do you think that he is concerned at the
Moon’s being in difficulties, though it was by her that he was thrown
into that sleep, in order that she might kiss him while sleeping. For
what should he be concerned for who has not even any sensation? You look
on sleep as an image of death, and you take that on you daily; and have
you, then, any doubt that there is no sensation in death, when you see
there is none in sleep, which is its near resemblance?
XXXIX. Away, then, with those follies, which are little better than the
old women’s dreams, such as that it is miserable to die before our time.
What time do you mean? That of nature? But she has only lent you life,
as she might lend you money, without fixing any certain time for its
repayment. Have you any grounds of complaint, 51then, that she recalls it
at her pleasure? for you received it on these terms. They that complain
thus allow that if a young child dies, the survivors ought to bear his
loss with equanimity; that if an infant in the cradle dies, they ought
not even to utter a complaint; and yet nature has been more severe with
them in demanding back what she gave. They answer by saying that such
have not tasted the sweets of life; while the other had begun to
conceive hopes of great happiness, and, indeed, had begun to realize
them. Men judge better in other things, and allow a part to be
preferable to none. Why do they not admit the same estimate in life?
Though Callimachus does not speak amiss in saying that more tears had
flowed from Priam than his son; yet they are thought happier who die
after they have reached old age. It would be hard to say why; for I do
not apprehend that any one, if a longer life were granted to him, would
find it happier. There is nothing more agreeable to a man than prudence,
which old age most certainly bestows on a man, though it may strip him
of everything else. But what age is long, or what is there at all long
to a man? Does not
Old age, though unregarded, still attend
On childhood’s pastimes, as the cares of men?
But because there is nothing beyond old age, we call that long: all
these things are said to be long or short, according to the proportion
of time they were given us for. Artistotle saith there is a kind of
insect near the river Hypanis, which runs from a certain part of Europe
into the Pontus, whose life consists but of one day; those that die at
the eighth hour die in full age; those who die when the sun sets are
very old, especially when the days are at the longest. Compare our
longest life with eternity, and we shall be found almost as short-lived
as those little animals.
XL. Let us, then, despise all these follies—for what softer name can I
give to such levities?—and let us lay the foundation of our happiness
in the strength and greatness of our minds, in a contempt and disregard
of all earthly things, and in the practice of every virtue. For at
present we are enervated by the softness of our imaginations, 52so that,
should we leave this world before the promises of our fortune-tellers
are made good to us, we should think ourselves deprived of some great
advantages, and seem disappointed and forlorn. But if, through life, we
are in continual suspense, still expecting, still desiring, and are in
continual pain and torture, good Gods! how pleasant must that journey be
which ends in security and ease! How pleased am I with Theramenes! Of
how exalted a soul does he appear! For, although we never read of him
without tears, yet that illustrious man is not to be lamented in his
death, who, when he had been imprisoned by the command of the thirty
tyrants, drank off, at one draught, as if he had been thirsty, the
poisoned cup, and threw the remainder out of it with such force that it
sounded as it fell; and then, on hearing the sound of the drops, he
said, with a smile, “I drink this to the most excellent Critias,” who
had been his most bitter enemy; for it is customary among the Greeks, at
their banquets, to name the person to whom they intend to deliver the
cup. This celebrated man was pleasant to the last, even when he had
received the poison into his bowels, and truly foretold the death of
that man whom he named when he drank the poison, and that death soon
followed. Who that thinks death an evil could approve of the evenness of
temper in this great man at the instant of dying? Socrates came, a few
years after, to the same prison and the same cup by as great iniquity on
the part of his judges as the tyrants displayed when they executed
Theramenes. What a speech is that which Plato makes him deliver before
his judges, after they had condemned him to death!
XLI. “I am not without hopes, O judges, that it is a favorable
circumstance for me that I am condemned to die; for one of these two
things must necessarily happen—either that death will deprive me
entirely of all sense, or else that, by dying, I shall go from hence
into some other place; wherefore, if all sense is utterly extinguished,
and if death is like that sleep which sometimes is so undisturbed as to
be even without the visions of dreams—in that case, O ye good Gods!
what gain is it to die? or what length of days can be imagined which
would be preferable to such a night? And if the constant course of
future time 53is to resemble that night, who is happier than I am? But if
on the other hand, what is said be true, namely, that death is but a
removal to those regions where the souls of the departed dwell, then
that state must be more happy still to have escaped from those who call
themselves judges, and to appear before such as are truly so—Minos,
Rhadamanthus, Æacus, Triptolemus—and to meet with those who have lived
with justice and probity!23 Can this change of abode appear otherwise
than great to you? What bounds can you set to the value of conversing
with Orpheus, and Musæus, and Homer, and Hesiod? I would even, were it
possible, willingly die often, in order to prove the certainty of what I
speak of. What delight must it be to meet with Palamedes, and Ajax, and
others, who have been betrayed by the iniquity of their judges! Then,
also, should I experience the wisdom of even that king of kings, who led
his vast troops to Troy, and the prudence of Ulysses and Sisyphus: nor
should I then be condemned for prosecuting my inquiries on such subjects
in the same way in which I have done here on earth. And even you, my
judges, you, I mean, who have voted for my acquittal, do not you fear
death, for nothing bad can befall a good man, whether he be alive or
dead; nor are his concerns ever overlooked by the Gods; nor in my case
either has this befallen me by chance; and I have nothing to charge
those men with who accused or condemned me but the fact that they
believed that they were doing me harm.” In this manner he proceeded.
There is no part of his speech which I admire more than his last words:
“But it is time,” says he, “for me now to go hence, that I may die; and
for you, that you may continue to live. Which condition of the two is
the best, the immortal Gods know; but I do not believe that any mortal
man does.”
54XLII. Surely I would rather have had this man’s soul than all the
fortunes of those who sat in judgment on him; although that very thing
which he says no one except the Gods know, namely, whether life or death
is most preferable, he knows himself, for he had previously stated his
opinion on it; but he maintained to the last that favorite maxim of his,
of affirming nothing. And let us, too, adhere to this rule of not
thinking anything an evil which is a general provision of nature; and
let us assure ourselves, that if death is an evil, it is an eternal
evil, for death seems to be the end of a miserable life; but if death is
a misery, there can be no end of that. But why do I mention Socrates, or
Theramenes, men distinguished by the glory of virtue and wisdom? when a
certain Lacedæmomian, whose name is not so much as known, held death in
such contempt, that, when led to it by the ephori, he bore a cheerful
and pleasant countenance; and, when he was asked by one of his enemies
whether he despised the laws of Lycurgus, “On the contrary,” answered
he, “I am greatly obliged to him, for he has amerced me in a fine which
I can pay without borrowing, or taking up money at interest.” This was a
man worthy of Sparta. And I am almost persuaded of his innocence because
of the greatness of his soul. Our own city has produced many such. But
why should I name generals, and other men of high rank, when Cato could
write that legions have marched with alacrity to that place from whence
they never expected to return? With no less greatness of soul fell the
Lacedæmonians at Thermopylæ, on whom Simonides wrote the following
epitaph:
Go, stranger, tell the Spartans, here we lie,
Who to support their laws durst boldly die.
24
What was it that Leonidas, their general, said to them? “March on with
courage, my Lacedæmonians. To-night, perhaps, we shall sup in the
regions below.” This was a brave nation while the laws of Lycurgus were
in force. One of them, when a Persian had said to him in conversation,
55“We shall hide the sun from your sight by the number of our arrows and
darts,” replied, “We shall fight, then in the shade.” Do I talk of their
men? How great was that Lacedæmonian woman, who had sent her son to
battle, and when she heard that he was slain, said, “I bore him for that
purpose, that you might have a man who durst die for his country!”
However, it is a matter of notoriety that the Spartans were bold and
hardy, for the discipline of a republic has great influence.
XLIII. What, then, have we not reason to admire Theodorus the Cyrenean,
a philosopher of no small distinction, who, when Lysimachus threatened
to crucify him, bade him keep those menaces for his courtiers? “To
Theodorus it makes no difference whether he rot in the air or
underground.” By which saying of the philosopher I am reminded to say
something of the custom of funerals and sepulture, and of funeral
ceremonies, which is, indeed, not a difficult subject, especially if we
recollect what has been before said about insensibility. The opinion of
Socrates respecting this matter is clearly stated in the book which
treats of his death, of which we have already said so much; for when he
had discussed the immortality of the soul, and when the time of his
dying was approaching rapidly, being asked by Criton how he would be
buried, “I have taken a great deal of pains,” saith he, “my friends, to
no purpose, for I have not convinced our Criton that I shall fly from
hence, and leave no part of me behind. Notwithstanding, Criton, if you
can overtake me, wheresoever you get hold of me, bury me as you please:
but believe me, none of you will be able to catch me when I have flown
away from hence.” That was excellently said, inasmuch as he allows his
friend to do as he pleased, and yet shows his indifference about
anything of this kind. Diogenes was rougher, though of the same opinion;
but in his character of a Cynic he expressed himself in a somewhat
harsher manner; he ordered himself to be thrown anywhere without being
buried. And when his friends replied, “What! to the birds and beasts?”
“By no means,” saith he; “place my staff near me, that I may drive them
away.” “How can you do that,” they answer, “for you will not perceive
them?” “How am I then 56injured by being torn by those animals, if I have
no sensation?” Anaxagoras, when he was at the point of death at
Lampsacus, and was asked by his friends, whether, if anything should
happen to him, he would not choose to be carried to Clazomenæ, his
country, made this excellent answer, “There is,” says he, “no occasion
for that, for all places are at an equal distance from the infernal
regions.” There is one thing to be observed with respect to the whole
subject of burial, that it relates to the body, whether the soul live or
die. Now, with regard to the body, it is clear that, whether the soul
live or die, that has no sensation.
XLIV. But all things are full of errors. Achilles drags Hector, tied to
his chariot; he thinks, I suppose, he tears his flesh, and that Hector
feels the pain of it; therefore, he avenges himself on him, as he
imagines. But Hecuba bewails this as a sore misfortune:
I saw (a dreadful sight) great Hector slain,
Dragg’d at Achilles’ car along the plain.
What Hector? or how long will he be Hector? Accius is better in this,
and Achilles, too, is sometimes reasonable:
I Hector’s body to his sire convey’d,
Hector I sent to the infernal shade.
It was not Hector that you dragged along, but a body that had been
Hector’s. Here another starts from underground, and will not suffer his
mother to sleep:
To thee I call, my once-loved parent, hear,
Nor longer with thy sleep relieve thy care;
Thine eye which pities not is closed—arise;
Ling’ring I wait the unpaid obsequies.
When these verses are sung with a slow and melancholy tune, so as to
affect the whole theatre with sadness, one can scarce help thinking
those unhappy that are unburied:
Ere the devouring dogs and hungry vultures...
He is afraid he shall not have the use of his limbs so well if they are
torn to pieces, but is under no such apprehensions if they are burned:
57
Nor leave my naked bones, my poor remains,
To shameful violence and bloody stains.
I do not understand what he could fear who could pour forth such
excellent verses to the sound of the flute. We must, therefore, adhere
to this, that nothing is to be regarded after we are dead, though many
people revenge themselves on their dead enemies. Thyestes pours forth
several curses in some good lines of Ennius, praying, first of all, that
Atreus may perish by a shipwreck, which is certainly a very terrible
thing, for such a death is not free from very grievous sensations. Then
follow these unmeaning expressions:
May
On the sharp rock his mangled carcass lie,
His entrails torn, to hungry birds a prey!
May he convulsive writhe his bleeding side,
And with his clotted gore the stones be dyed!
The rocks themselves were not more destitute of feeling than he who was
hanging to them by his side; though Thyestes imagines he is wishing him
the greatest torture. It would be torture, indeed, if he were sensible;
but as he is not, it can be none; then how very unmeaning is this:
Let him, still hovering o’er the Stygian wave,
Ne’er reach the body’s peaceful port, the grave!
You see under what mistaken notions all this is said. He imagines the
body has its haven, and that the dead are at rest in their graves.
Pelops was greatly to blame in not having informed and taught his son
what regard was due to everything.
XLV. But what occasion is there to animadvert on the opinions of
individuals, when we may observe whole nations to fall into all sorts of
errors? The Egyptians embalm their dead, and keep them in their houses;
the Persians dress them over with wax, and then bury them, that they may
preserve their bodies as long as possible. It is customary with the Magi
to bury none of their order, unless they have been first torn by wild
beasts. In Hyrcania, the people maintain dogs for the public use; the
nobles have their own—and we know that they have a good breed of dogs;
but every one, according to his ability, 58provides himself with some, in
order to be torn by them; and they hold that to be the best kind of
interment. Chrysippus, who is curious in all kinds of historical facts,
has collected many other things of this kind; but some of them are so
offensive as not to admit of being related. All that has been said of
burying is not worth our regard with respect to ourselves, though it is
not to be neglected as to our friends, provided we are thoroughly aware
that the dead are insensible. But the living, indeed, should consider
what is due to custom and opinion; only they should at the same time
consider that the dead are noways interested in it. But death truly is
then met with the greatest tranquillity when the dying man can comfort
himself with his own praise. No one dies too soon who has finished the
course of perfect virtue. I myself have known many occasions when I have
seemed in danger of immediate death; oh! how I wish it had come to me!
for I have gained nothing by the delay. I had gone over and over again
the duties of life; nothing remained but to contend with fortune. If
reason, then, cannot sufficiently fortify us to enable us to feel a
contempt for death, at all events let our past life prove that we have
lived long enough, and even longer than was necessary; for
notwithstanding the deprivation of sense, the dead are not without that
good which peculiarly belongs to them, namely, the praise and glory
which they have acquired, even though they are not sensible of it. For
although there be nothing in glory to make it desirable, yet it follows
virtue as its shadow; and the genuine judgment of the multitude on good
men, if ever they form any, is more to their own praise than of any real
advantage to the dead. Yet I cannot say, however it may be received,
that Lycurgus and Solon have no glory from their laws, and from the
political constitution which they established in their country; or that
Themistocles and Epaminondas have not glory from their martial virtue.
XLVI. For Neptune shall sooner bury Salamis itself with his waters than
the memory of the trophies gained there; and the BЕ“otian Leuctra shall
perish sooner than the glory of that great battle. And longer still
shall fame be before it deserts Curius, and Fabricius, and Calatinus,
59and the two Scipios, and the two Africani, and Maximus, and Marcellus,
and Paulus, and Cato, and Lælius, and numberless other heroes; and
whoever has caught any resemblance of them, not estimating it by common
fame, but by the real applause of good men, may with confidence, when
the occasion requires, approach death, on which we are sure that even if
the chief good is not continued, at least no evil is. Such a man would
even wish to die while in prosperity; for all the favors that could be
heaped on him would not be so agreeable to him as the loss of them would
be painful. That speech of the Lacedæmonian seems to have the same
meaning, who, when Diagoras the Rhodian, who had himself been a
conqueror at the Olympic games, saw two of his own sons conquerors there
on the same day, approached the old man, and, congratulating him, said,
“You should die now, Diagoras, for no greater happiness can possibly
await you.” The Greeks look on these as great things; perhaps they think
too highly of them, or, rather, they did so then. And so he who said
this to Diagoras, looking on it as something very glorious, that three
men out of one family should have been conquerors there, thought it
could answer no purpose to him to continue any longer in life, where he
could only be exposed to a reverse of fortune.
I might have given you a sufficient answer, as it seems to me, on this
point, in a few words, as you had allowed the dead were not exposed to
any positive evil; but I have spoken at greater length on the subject
for this reason, because this is our greatest consolation in the losing
and bewailing of our friends. For we ought to bear with moderation any
grief which arises from ourselves, or is endured on our own account,
lest we should seem to be too much influenced by self-love. But should
we suspect our departed friends to be under those evils, which they are
generally imagined to be, and to be sensible of them, then such a
suspicion would give us intolerable pain; and accordingly I wished, for
my own sake, to pluck up this opinion by the roots, and on that account
I have been perhaps somewhat more prolix than was necessary.
XLVII. A. More prolix than was necessary? Certainty not, in my
opinion. For I was induced, by the former 60part of your speech, to wish
to die; but, by the latter, sometimes not to be unwilling, and at others
to be wholly indifferent about it. But the effect of your whole argument
is, that I am convinced that death ought not to be classed among the
evils.
M. Do you, then, expect that I am to give you a regular peroration,
like the rhetoricians, or shall I forego that art?
A. I would not have you give over an art which you have set off to
such advantage; and you were in the right to do so, for, to speak the
truth, it also has set you off. But what is that peroration? For I
should be glad to hear it, whatever it is.
M. It is customary, in the schools, to produce the opinions of the
immortal Gods on death; nor are these opinions the fruits of the
imagination alone of the lecturers, but they have the authority of
Herodotus and many others. Cleobis and Biton are the first they mention,
sons of the Argive priestess; the story is a well-known one. As it was
necessary that she should be drawn in a chariot to a certain annual
sacrifice, which was solemnized at a temple some considerable distance
from the town, and the cattle that were to draw the chariot had not
arrived, those two young men whom I have just mentioned, pulling off
their garments, and anointing their bodies with oil, harnessed
themselves to the yoke. And in this manner the priestess was conveyed to
the temple; and when the chariot had arrived at the proper place, she is
said to have entreated the Goddess to bestow on them, as a reward for
their piety, the greatest gift that a God could confer on man. And the
young men, after having feasted with their mother, fell asleep; and in
the morning they were found dead. Trophonius and Agamedes are said to
have put up the same petition, for they, having built a temple to Apollo
at Delphi, offered supplications to the God, and desired of him some
extraordinary reward for their care and labor, particularizing nothing,
but asking for whatever was best for men. Accordingly, Apollo signified
to them that he would bestow it on them in three days, and on the third
day at daybreak they were found dead. And so they say that this was a
formal decision pronounced by that God to 61whom the rest of the deities
have assigned the province of divining with an accuracy superior to that
of all the rest.
XLVIII. There is also a story told of Silenus, who, when taken prisoner
by Midas, is said to have made him this present for his ransom—namely,
that he informed him25 that never to have been born was by far the
greatest blessing that could happen to man; and that the next best thing
was to die very soon; which very opinion Euripides makes use of in his
Cresphontes, saying,
When man is born, �tis fit, with solemn show,
We speak our sense of his approaching woe;
With other gestures and a different eye,
Proclaim our pleasure when he’s bid to die.
26
There is something like this in Crantor’s Consolation; for he says that
Terinæsus of Elysia, when he was bitterly lamenting the loss of his son,
came to a place of divination to be informed why he was visited with so
great affliction, and received in his tablet these three verses:
Thou fool, to murmur at Euthynous’ death!
The blooming youth to fate resigns his breath:
The fate, whereon your happiness depends,
At once the parent and the son befriends.
27
On these and similar authorities they affirm that the question has been
determined by the Gods. Nay, more; Alcidamas, an ancient rhetorician of
the very highest reputation, wrote even in praise of death, which he
endeavored to establish by an enumeration of the evils of life; and his
Dissertation has a great deal of eloquence in it; but 62he was
unacquainted with the more refined arguments of the philosophers. By the
orators, indeed, to die for our country is always considered not only as
glorious, but even as happy: they go back as far as Erechtheus,28
whose very daughters underwent death, for the safety of their
fellow-citizens: they instance Codrus, who threw himself into the midst
of his enemies, dressed like a common man, that his royal robes might
not betray him, because the oracle had declared the Athenians
conquerors, if their king was slain. MenЕ“ceus29 is not overlooked by
them, who, in compliance with the injunctions of an oracle, freely shed
his blood for his country. Iphigenia ordered herself to be conveyed to
Aulis, to be sacrificed, that her blood might be the cause of spilling
that of her enemies.
XLIX. From hence they proceed to instances of a fresher date. Harmodius
and Aristogiton are in everybody’s mouth; the memory of Leonidas the
Lacedæmonian and Epaminondas the Theban is as fresh as ever. Those
philosophers were not acquainted with the many instances in our
country—to give a list of whom would take up too much time—who, we
see, considered death desirable as long as it was accompanied with
honor. But, notwithstanding this is the correct view of the case, we
must use much persuasion, speak as if we were endued with some higher
authority, in order to bring men to begin to wish to die, or cease to be
afraid of death. For if that last day does not occasion an entire
extinction, but a change of abode only, what can be more desirable? And
if it, on the other hand, destroys, and absolutely puts an end to us,
what can be preferable to the having a deep sleep fall on us, in the
midst of the fatigues of life, and being thus overtaken, to sleep to
eternity? And, should this really 63be the case, then Ennius’s language
is more consistent with wisdom than Solon’s; for our Ennius says,
Let none bestow upon my passing bier
One needless sigh or unavailing tear.
But the wise Solon says,
Let me not unlamented die, but o’er my bier
Burst forth the tender sigh, the friendly tear.
30
But let us, if indeed it should be our fate to know the time which is
appointed by the Gods for us to die, prepare ourselves for it with a
cheerful and grateful mind, thinking ourselves like men who are
delivered from a jail, and released from their fetters, for the purpose
of going back to our eternal habitation, which may be more emphatically
called our own; or else to be divested of all sense and trouble. If, on
the other hand, we should have no notice given us of this decree, yet
let us cultivate such a disposition as to look on that formidable hour
of death as happy for us, though shocking to our friends; and let us
never imagine anything to be an evil which is an appointment of the
immortal Gods, or of nature, the common parent of all. For it is not by
hazard or without design that we have been born and situated as we have.
On the contrary, beyond all doubt there is a certain power which
consults the happiness of human nature; and this would neither have
produced nor provided for a being which, after having gone through the
labors of life, was to fall into eternal misery by death. Let us rather
infer that we have a retreat and haven prepared for us, which I wish we
could crowd all sail and arrive at; but though the winds should not
serve, and we should be driven back, yet we shall to a certainty arrive
at that point eventually, though somewhat later. But how can that be
miserable for one which all must of necessity undergo? I have given you
a peroration, that you might not think I had overlooked or neglected
anything.
A. I am persuaded you have not; and, indeed, that peroration has
confirmed me.
64M. I am glad it has had that effect. But it is now time to consult
our health. To-morrow, and all the time we continue in this Tusculan
villa, let us consider this subject; and especially those portions of it
which may ease our pain, alleviate our fears, and lessen our desires,
which is the greatest advantage we can reap from the whole of
philosophy.
BOOK II.
ON BEARING PAIN.
I.
Neoptolemus, in Ennius, indeed, says that the study of philosophy was
expedient for him; but that it required limiting to a few subjects, for
that to give himself up entirely to it was what he did not approve of.
And for my part, Brutus, I am perfectly persuaded that it is expedient
for me to philosophize; for what can I do better, especially as I have
no regular occupation? But I am not for limiting my philosophy to a few
subjects, as he does; for philosophy is a matter in which it is
difficult to acquire a little knowledge without acquainting yourself
with many, or all its branches, nor can you well take a few subjects
without selecting them out of a great number; nor can any one, who has
acquired the knowledge of a few points, avoid endeavoring with the same
eagerness to understand more. But still, in a busy life, and in one
mainly occupied with military matters, such as that of Neoptolemus was
at that time, even that limited degree of acquaintance with philosophy
may be of great use, and may yield fruit, not perhaps so plentiful as a
thorough knowledge of the whole of philosophy, but yet such as in some
degree may at times deliver us from the dominion of our desires, our
sorrows, and our fears; just as the effect of that discussion which we
lately maintained in my Tusculan villa seemed to be that a great
contempt of death was engendered, which contempt is of no small efficacy
towards delivering the mind from fear; for whoever dreads what cannot be
avoided can by no means live with a quiet and tranquil mind. But he who
is under no
65fear of death, not only because it is a thing absolutely
inevitable but also because he is persuaded that death itself hath
nothing terrible in it, provides himself with a very great resource
towards a happy life. However, I am not tolerant that many will argue
strenuously against us; and, indeed, that is a thing which can never be
avoided, except by abstaining from writing at all. For if my Orations,
which were addressed to the judgment and approbation of the people (for
that is a popular art, and the object of oratory is popular applause),
have been criticised by some people who are inclined to withhold their
praise from everything but what they are persuaded they can attain to
themselves, and who limit their ideas of good speaking by the hopes
which they conceive of what they themselves may attain to, and who
declare, when they are overwhelmed with a flow of words and sentences,
that they prefer the utmost poverty of thought and expression to that
plenty and copiousness (from which arose the Attic kind of oratory,
which they who professed it were strangers to, though they have now been
some time silenced, and laughed out of the very courts of justice), what
may I not expect, when at present I cannot have the least countenance
from the people by whom I used to be upheld before? For philosophy is
satisfied with a few judges, and of her own accord industriously avoids
the multitude, who are jealous of it, and utterly displeased with it; so
that, should any one undertake to cry down the whole of it, he would
have the people on his side; while, if he should attack that school
which I particularly profess, he would have great assistance from those
of the other philosophers.
II. But I have answered the detractors of philosophy in general, in my
Hortensius. And what I had to say in favor of the Academics, is, I
think, explained with sufficient accuracy in my four books of the
Academic Question.
But yet I am so far from desiring that no one should write against me,
that it is what I most earnestly wish; for philosophy would never have
been in such esteem in Greece itself, if it had not been for the
strength which it acquired from the contentions and disputations of the
66most learned men; and therefore I recommend all men who have abilities
to follow my advice to snatch this art also from declining Greece, and
to transport it to this city; as our ancestors by their study and
industry have imported all their other arts which were worth having.
Thus the praise of oratory, raised from a low degree, is arrived at such
perfection that it must now decline, and, as is the nature of all
things, verge to its dissolution in a very short time. Let philosophy,
then, derive its birth in Latin language from this time, and let us lend
it our assistance, and bear patiently to be contradicted and refuted;
and although those men may dislike such treatment who are bound and
devoted to certain predetermined opinions, and are under such
obligations to maintain them that they are forced, for the sake of
consistency, to adhere to them even though they do not themselves wholly
approve of them; we, on the other hand, who pursue only probabilities,
and who cannot go beyond that which seems really likely, can confute
others without obstinacy, and are prepared to be confuted ourselves
without resentment. Besides, if these studies are ever brought home to
us, we shall not want even Greek libraries, in which there is an
infinite number of books, by reason of the multitude of authors among
them; for it is a common practice with many to repeat the same things
which have been written by others, which serves no purpose but to stuff
their shelves; and this will be our case, too, if many apply themselves
to this study.
III. But let us excite those, if possible, who have had a liberal
education, and are masters of an elegant style, and who philosophize
with reason and method.
For there is a certain class of them who would willingly be called
philosophers, whose books in our language are said to be numerous, and
which I do not despise; for, indeed, I never read them: but still,
because the authors themselves declare that they write without any
regularity, or method, or elegance, or ornament, I do not care to read
what must be so void of entertainment. There is no one in the least
acquainted with literature who does not know the style and sentiments of
that school; wherefore, since they are at no pains to express themselves
well, I
67do not see why they should be read by anybody except by one
another. Let them read them, if they please, who are of the same
opinions; for in the same manner as all men read Plato and the other
Socratics, with those who sprung from them, even those who do not agree
with their opinions, or are very indifferent about them; but scarcely
any one except their own disciples take Epicurus or Metrodorus into
their hands; so they alone read these Latin books who think that the
arguments contained in them are sound. But, in my opinion, whatever is
published should be recommended to the reading of every man of learning;
and though we may not succeed in this ourselves, yet nevertheless we
must be sensible that this ought to be the aim of every writer. And on
this account I have always been pleased with the custom of the
Peripatetics and Academics, of disputing on both sides of the question;
not solely from its being the only method of discovering what is
probable on every subject, but also because it affords the greatest
scope for practising eloquence; a method that Aristotle first made use
of, and afterward all the Aristotelians; and in our own memory Plilo,
whom we have often heard, appointed one time to treat of the precepts of
the rhetoricians, and another for philosophical discussion, to which
custom I was brought to conform by my friends at my Tusculum; and
accordingly our leisure time was spent in this manner. And therefore, as
yesterday before noon we applied ourselves to speaking, and in the
afternoon went down into the Academy, the discussions which were held
there I have acquainted you with, not in the manner of a narration, but
in almost the very same words which were employed in the debate.
IV. The discourse, then, was introduced in this manner while we were
walking, and it was commenced by some such an opening as this:
A. It is not to be expressed how much I was delighted, or rather
edified, by your discourse of yesterday. For although I am conscious to
myself that I have never been too fond of life, yet at times, when I
have considered that there would be an end to this life, and that I must
some time or other part with all its good things, a certain dread
68and
uneasiness used to intrude itself on my thoughts; but now, believe me, I
am so freed from that kind of uneasiness that there is nothing that I
think less worth any regard.
M. I am not at all surprised at that, for it is the effect of
philosophy, which is the medicine of our souls; it banishes all
groundless apprehensions, frees us from desires, and drives away fears:
but it has not the same influence over all men; it is of very great
influence when it falls in with a disposition well adapted to it. For
not only does Fortune, as the old proverb says, assist the bold, but
reason does so in a still greater degree; for it, by certain precepts,
as it were, strengthens even courage itself. You were born naturally
great and soaring, and with a contempt for all things which pertain to
man alone; therefore a discourse against death took easy possession of a
brave soul. But do you imagine that these same arguments have any force
with those very persons who have invented, and canvassed, and published
them, excepting indeed some very few particular persons? For how few
philosophers will you meet with whose life and manners are conformable
to the dictates of reason! who look on their profession, not as a means
of displaying their learning, but as a rule for their own practice! who
follow their own precepts, and comply with their own decrees! You may
see some of such levity and such vanity, that it would have been better
for them to have been ignorant; some covetous of money, some others
eager for glory, many slaves to their lusts; so that their discourses
and their actions are most strangely at variance; than which nothing in
my opinion can be more unbecoming: for just as if one who professed to
teach grammar should speak with impropriety, or a master of music sing
out of tune, such conduct has the worst appearance in these men, because
they blunder in the very particular with which they profess that they
are well acquainted. So a philosopher who errs in the conduct of his
life is the more infamous because he is erring in the very thing which
he pretends to teach, and, while he lays down rules to regulate life by,
is irregular in his own life.
V.
A. Should this be the case, is it not to be feared that
69you are
dressing up philosophy in false colors? For what stronger argument can
there be that it is of little use than that some very profound
philosophers live in a discreditable manner?
M. That, indeed, is no argument at all, for as all the fields which
are cultivated are not fruitful (and this sentiment of Accius is false,
and asserted without any foundation,
The ground you sow on is of small avail;
To yield a crop good seed can never fail),
it is not every mind which has been properly cultivated that produces
fruit; and, to go on with the comparison, as a field, although it may be
naturally fruitful, cannot produce a crop without dressing, so neither
can the mind without education; such is the weakness of either without
the other. Whereas philosophy is the culture of the mind: this it is
which plucks up vices by the roots; prepares the mind for the receiving
of seeds; commits them to it, or, as I may say, sows them, in the hope
that, when come to maturity, they may produce a plentiful harvest. Let
us proceed, then, as we began. Say, if you please, what shall be the
subject of our disputation.
A. I look on pain to be the greatest of all evils.
M. What, even greater than infamy?
A. I dare not indeed assert that; and I blush to think I am so soon
driven from my ground.
M. You would have had greater reason for blushing had you persevered
in it; for what is so unbecoming—what can appear worse to you, than
disgrace, wickedness, immorality? To avoid which, what pain is there
which we ought not (I will not say to avoid shirking, but even) of our
own accord to encounter, and undergo, and even to court?
A. I am entirely of that opinion; but, notwithstanding that pain is
not the greatest evil, yet surely it is an evil.
M. Do you perceive, then, how much of the terror of pain you have
given up on a small hint?
A. I see that plainly; but I should be glad to give up more of it.
M. I will endeavor to make you do so; but it is a great 70undertaking,
and I must have a disposition on your part which is not inclined to
offer any obstacles.
A. You shall have such: for as I behaved yesterday, so now I will
follow reason wherever she leads.
VI. M. First, then, I will speak of the weakness of many philosophers,
and those, too, of various sects; the head of whom, both in authority
and antiquity, was Aristippus, the pupil of Socrates, who hesitated not
to say that pain was the greatest of all evils. And after him Epicurus
easily gave in to this effeminate and enervated doctrine. After him
Hieronymus the Rhodian said, that to be without pain was the chief good,
so great an evil did pain appear to him to be. The rest, with the
exceptions of Zeno, Aristo, Pyrrho, were pretty much of the same opinion
that you were of just now—that it was indeed an evil, but that there
were many worse. When, then, nature herself, and a certain generous
feeling of virtue, at once prevents you from persisting in the assertion
that pain is the chief evil, and when you were driven from such an
opinion when disgrace was contrasted with pain, shall philosophy, the
preceptress of life, cling to this idea for so many ages? What duty of
life, what praise, what reputation, would be of such consequence that a
man should be desirous of gaining it at the expense of submitting to
bodily pain, when he has persuaded himself that pain is the greatest
evil? On the other side, what disgrace, what ignominy, would he not
submit to that he might avoid pain, when persuaded that it was the
greatest of evils? Besides, what person, if it be only true that pain is
the greatest of evils, is not miserable, not only when he actually feels
pain, but also whenever he is aware that it may befall him. And who is
there whom pain may not befall? So that it is clear that there is
absolutely no one who can possibly be happy. Metrodorus, indeed, thinks
that man perfectly happy whose body is free from all disorders, and who
has an assurance that it will always continue so; but who is there who
can be assured of that?
VII. But Epicurus, indeed, says such things that it should seem that his
design was only to make people laugh; for he affirms somewhere that if a
wise man were to be burned or put to the torture—you expect, perhaps,
71that he is going to say he would bear it, he would support himself
under it with resolution, he would not yield to it (and that by
Hercules! would be very commendable, and worthy of that very Hercules
whom I have just invoked): but even this will not satisfy Epicurus, that
robust and hardy man! No; his wise man, even if he were in Phalaris’s
bull, would say, How sweet it is! how little do I regard it! What,
sweet? Is it not sufficient, if it is not disagreeable? But those very
men who deny pain to be an evil are not in the habit of saying that it
is agreeable to any one to be tormented; they rather say that it is
cruel, or hard to bear, afflicting, unnatural, but still not an evil:
while this man who says that it is the only evil, and the very worst of
all evils, yet thinks that a wise man would pronounce it sweet. I do not
require of you to speak of pain in the same words which Epicurus uses—a
man, as you know, devoted to pleasure: he may make no difference, if he
pleases, between Phalaris’s bull and his own bed; but I cannot allow the
wise man to be so indifferent about pain. If he bears it with courage,
it is sufficient: that he should rejoice in it, I do not expect; for
pain is, beyond all question, sharp, bitter, against nature, hard to
submit to and to bear. Observe Philoctetes: We may allow him to lament,
for he saw Hercules himself groaning loudly through extremity of pain on
Mount Е’ta. The arrows with which Hercules presented him were then no
consolation to him, when
The viper’s bite, impregnating his veins
With poison, rack’d him with its bitter pains.
And therefore he cries out, desiring help, and wishing to die,
Oh that some friendly hand its aid would lend,
My body from this rock’s vast height to send
Into the briny deep! I’m all on fire,
And by this fatal wound must soon expire.
It is hard to say that the man who was obliged to cry out in this manner
was not oppressed with evil, and great evil too.
VIII. But let us observe Hercules himself, who was subdued by pain at
the very time when he was on the point 72of attaining immortality by
death. What words does Sophocles here put in his mouth, in his
Trachiniæ? who, when Deianira had put upon him a tunic dyed in the
centaur’s blood, and it stuck to his entrails, says,
What tortures I endure no words can tell,
Far greater these, than those which erst befell
From the dire terror of thy consort, Jove—
E’en stern Eurystheus’ dire command above;
This of thy daughter, Е’neus, is the fruit,
Beguiling me with her envenom’d suit,
Whose close embrace doth on my entrails prey,
Consuming life; my lungs forbid to play;
The blood forsakes my veins; my manly heart
Forgets to beat; enervated, each part
Neglects its office, while my fatal doom
Proceeds ignobly from the weaver’s loom.
The hand of foe ne’er hurt me, nor the fierce
Giant issuing from his parent earth.
Ne’er could the Centaur such a blow enforce,
No barbarous foe, nor all the Grecian force;
This arm no savage people could withstand,
Whose realms I traversed to reform the land.
Thus, though I ever bore a manly heart,
I fall a victim to a woman’s art.
IX.
Assist, my son, if thou that name dost hear,
My groans preferring to thy mother’s tear:
Convey her here, if, in thy pious heart,
Thy mother shares not an unequal part:
Proceed, be bold, thy father’s fate bemoan,
Nations will join, you will not weep alone.
Oh, what a sight is this same briny source,
Unknown before, through all my labors’ course!
That virtue, which could brave each toil but late,
With woman’s weakness now bewails its fate.
Approach, my son; behold thy father laid,
A wither’d carcass that implores thy aid;
Let all behold: and thou, imperious Jove,
On me direct thy lightning from above:
Now all its force the poison doth assume,
And my burnt entrails with its flame consume.
Crestfallen, unembraced, I now let fall
Listless, those hands that lately conquer’d all;
When the Nemæan lion own’d their force,
And he indignant fell a breathless corse;
The serpent slew, of the Lernean lake,
As did the Hydra of its force partake:
By this, too, fell the Erymanthian boar:
73E’en Cerberus did his weak strength deplore.
This sinewy arm did overcome with ease
That dragon, guardian of the Golden Fleece.
My many conquests let some others trace;
It’s mine to say, I never knew disgrace.
31
Can we then, despise pain, when we see Hercules himself giving vent to
his expressions of agony with such impatience?
X. Let us see what Г†schylus says, who was not only a poet but a
Pythagorean philosopher also, for that is the account which you have
received of him; how doth he make Prometheus bear the pain he suffered
for the Lemnian theft, when he clandestinely stole away the celestial
fire, and bestowed it on men, and was severely punished by Jupiter for
the theft. Fastened to Mount Caucasus, he speaks thus:
Thou heav’n-born race of Titans here fast bound,
Behold thy brother! As the sailors sound
With care the bottom, and their ships confine
To some safe shore, with anchor and with line;
So, by Jove’s dread decree, the God of fire
Confines me here the victim of Jove’s ire.
With baneful art his dire machine he shapes;
From such a God what mortal e’er escapes?
When each third day shall triumph o’er the night,
Then doth the vulture, with his talons light,
Seize on my entrails; which, in rav’nous guise,
He preys on! then with wing extended flies
Aloft, and brushes with his plumes the gore:
But when dire Jove my liver doth restore,
Back he returns impetuous to his prey,
Clapping his wings, he cuts th’ ethereal way.
Thus do I nourish with my blood this pest,
Confined my arms, unable to contest;
Entreating only that in pity Jove
Would take my life, and this cursed plague remove.
But endless ages past unheard my moan,
Sooner shall drops dissolve this very stone.
32
And therefore it scarcely seems possible to avoid calling a man who is
suffering, miserable; and if he is miserable, then pain is an evil.
74XI. A. Hitherto you are on my side; I will see to that by-and-by;
and, in the mean while, whence are those verses? I do not remember them.
M. I will inform you, for you are in the right to ask. Do you see that
I have much leisure?
A. What, then?
M. I imagine, when you were at Athens, you attended frequently at the
schools of the philosophers.
A. Yes, and with great pleasure.
M. You observed, then, that though none of them at that time were very
eloquent, yet they used to mix verses with their harangues.
A. Yes, and particularly Dionysius the Stoic used to employ a great
many.
M. You say right; but they were quoted without any appropriateness or
elegance. But our friend Philo used to give a few select lines and well
adapted; and in imitation of him, ever since I took a fancy to this kind
of elderly declamation, I have been very fond of quoting our poets; and
where I cannot be supplied from them, I translate from the Greek, that
the Latin language may not want any kind of ornament in this kind of
disputation.
But, do you not see how much harm is done by poets? They introduce the
bravest men lamenting over their misfortunes: they soften our minds; and
they are, besides, so entertaining, that we do not only read them, but
get them by heart. Thus the influence of the poets is added to our want
of discipline at home, and our tender and delicate manner of living, so
that between them they have deprived virtue of all its vigor and energy.
Plato, therefore, was right in banishing them from his commonwealth,
where he required the best morals, and the best form of government. But
we, who have all our learning from Greece, read and learn these works of
theirs from our childhood; and look on this as a liberal and learned
education.
XII. But why are we angry with the poets? We may find some philosophers,
those masters of virtue, who have taught that pain was the greatest of
evils. But you, young man, when you said but just now that it appeared
so to you, upon being asked by me what appeared greater than infamy,
gave up that opinion at a word. Suppose I ask 75Epicurus the same
question. He will answer that a trifling degree of pain is a greater
evil than the greatest infamy; for that there is no evil in infamy
itself, unless attended with pain. What pain, then, attends Epicurus,
when he says that very thing, that pain is the greatest evil! And yet
nothing can be a greater disgrace to a philosopher than to talk thus.
Therefore, you allowed enough when you admitted that infamy appeared to
you to be a greater evil than pain. And if you abide by this admission,
you will see how far pain should be resisted; and that our inquiry
should be not so much whether pain be an evil, as how the mind may be
fortified for resisting it. The Stoics infer from some petty quibbling
arguments that it is no evil, as if the dispute were about a word, and
not about the thing itself. Why do you impose upon me, Zeno? For when
you deny what appears very dreadful to me to be an evil, I am deceived,
and am at a loss to know why that which appears to me to be a most
miserable thing should be no evil. The answer is, that nothing is an
evil but what is base and vicious. You return to your trifling, for you
do not remove what made me uneasy. I know that pain is not vice—you
need not inform me of that: but show me that it makes no difference to
me whether I am in pain or not. It has never anything to do, say you,
with a happy life, for that depends upon virtue alone; but yet pain is
to be avoided. If I ask, why? It is disagreeable, against nature, hard
to bear, woful and afflicting.
XIII. Here are many words to express that by so many different forms
which we call by the single word evil. You are defining pain, instead of
removing it, when you say, it is disagreeable, unnatural, scarcely
possible to be endured or borne, nor are you wrong in saying so: but the
man who vaunts himself in such a manner should not give way in his
conduct, if it be true that nothing is good but what is honest, and
nothing evil but what is disgraceful. This would be wishing, not
proving. This argument is a better one, and has more truth in it—that
all things which Nature abhors are to be looked upon as evil; that those
which she approves of are to be considered as good: for when this is
admitted, and the dispute 76about words removed, that which they with
reason embrace, and which we call honest, right, becoming, and sometimes
include under the general name of virtue, appears so far superior to
everything else that all other things which are looked upon as the gifts
of fortune, or the good things of the body, seem trifling and
insignificant; and no evil whatever, nor all the collective body of
evils together, appears to be compared to the evil of infamy. Wherefore,
if, as you granted in the beginning, infamy is worse than pain, pain is
certainly nothing; for while it appears to you base and unmanly to
groan, cry out, lament, or faint under pain; while you cherish notions
of probity, dignity, honor, and, keeping your eye on them, refrain
yourself, pain will certainly yield to virtue, and, by the influence of
imagination, will lose its whole force.—For you must either admit that
there is no such thing as virtue, or you must despise every kind of
pain. Will you allow of such a virtue as prudence, without which no
virtue whatever can even be conceived? What, then? Will that suffer you
to labor and take pains to no purpose? Will temperance permit you to do
anything to excess? Will it be possible for justice to be maintained by
one who through the force of pain discovers secrets, or betrays his
confederates, or deserts many duties of life? Will you act in a manner
consistently with courage, and its attendants, greatness of soul,
resolution, patience, and contempt for all worldly things? Can you hear
yourself called a great man when you lie grovelling, dejected, and
deploring your condition with a lamentable voice; no one would call you
even a man while in such a condition. You must therefore either abandon
all pretensions to courage, or else pain must be put out of the
question.
XIV. You know very well that, even though part of your Corinthian
furniture were gone, the remainder might be safe without that; but if
you lose one virtue (though virtue in reality cannot be lost), still if,
I say, you should acknowledge that you were deficient in one, you would
be stripped of all. Can you, then, call yourself a brave man, of a great
soul, endued with patience and steadiness above the frowns of fortune?
or Philoctetes? for I choose to instance him, rather than yourself, for
he certainly was not 77a brave man, who lay in his bed, which was watered
with his tears,
Whose groans, bewailings, and whose bitter cries,
With grief incessant rent the very skies.
I do not deny pain to be pain—for were that the case, in what would
courage consist?—but I say it should be assuaged by patience, if there
be such a thing as patience: if there be no such thing, why do we speak
so in praise of philosophy? or why do we glory in its name? Does pain
annoy us? Let it sting us to the heart: if you are without defensive
armor, bare your throat to it; but if you are secured by Vulcanian
armor, that is to say by resolution, resist it. Should you fail to do
so, that guardian of your honor, your courage, will forsake and leave
you.—By the laws of Lycurgus, and by those which were given to the
Cretans by Jupiter, or which Minos established under the direction of
Jupiter, as the poets say, the youths of the State are trained by the
practice of hunting, running, enduring hunger and thirst, cold and heat.
The boys at Sparta are scourged so at the altars that blood follows the
lash in abundance; nay, sometimes, as I used to hear when I was there,
they are whipped even to death; and yet not one of them was ever heard
to cry out, or so much as groan. What, then? Shall men not be able to
bear what boys do? and shall custom have such great force, and reason
none at all?
XV. There is some difference between labor and pain; they border upon
one another, but still there is a certain difference between them. Labor
is a certain exercise of the mind or body, in some employment or
undertaking of serious trouble and importance; but pain is a sharp
motion in the body, disagreeable to our senses.—Both these feelings,
the Greeks, whose language is more copious than ours, express by the
common name of О бЅ№ОЅОїП‚: therefore they call industrious men painstaking,
or, rather, fond of labor; we, more conveniently, call them laborious;
for laboring is one thing, and enduring pain another. You see, O Greece!
your barrenness of words, sometimes, though you think you are always so
rich in them. I say, then, that there is a difference between laboring
and being in 78pain. When Caius Marius had an operation performed for a
swelling in his thigh, he felt pain; when he headed his troops in a very
hot season, he labored. Yet these two feelings bear some resemblance to
one another; for the accustoming ourselves to labor makes the endurance
of pain more easy to us. And it was because they were influenced by this
reason that the founders of the Grecian form of government provided that
the bodies of their youth should be strengthened by labor, which custom
the Spartans transferred even to their women, who in other cities lived
more delicately, keeping within the walls of their houses; but it was
otherwise with the Spartans.
The Spartan women, with a manly air,
Fatigues and dangers with their husbands share;
They in fantastic sports have no delight,
Partners with them in exercise and fight.
And in these laborious exercises pain interferes sometimes. They are
thrown down, receive blows, have bad falls, and are bruised, and the
labor itself produces a sort of callousness to pain.
XVI. As to military service (I speak of our own, not of that of the
Spartans, for they used to march slowly to the sound of the flute, and
scarce a word of command was given without an anapæst), you may see, in
the first place, whence the very name of an army (exercitus33) is
derived; and, secondly, how great the labor is of an army on its march:
then consider that they carry more than a fortnight’s provision, and
whatever else they may want; that they carry the burden of the
stakes,34 for as to shield, sword, or helmet, they look on them as no
more encumbrance than their own limbs, for they say that arms are the
limbs of a soldier, and those, indeed, they carry so commodiously that,
when there is occasion, they throw down their burdens, and use their
arms as readily as their limbs. Why need I mention the exercises of the
legions? And how great the labor is which is undergone in the running,
encounters, shouts! Hence it is that their minds are worked 79up to make
so light of wounds in action. Take a soldier of equal bravery, but
undisciplined, and he will seem a woman. Why is it that there is this
sensible difference between a raw recruit and a veteran soldier? The age
of the young soldiers is for the most part in their favor; but it is
practice only that enables men to bear labor and despise wounds.
Moreover, we often see, when the wounded are carried off the field, the
raw, untried soldier, though but slightly wounded, cries out most
shamefully; but the more brave, experienced veteran only inquires for
some one to dress his wounds, and says,
Patroclus, to thy aid I must appeal
Ere worse ensue, my bleeding wounds to heal;
The sons of Æsculapius are employ’d,
No room for me, so many are annoy’d.
XVII. This is certainly Eurypylus himself. What an experienced
man!—While his friend is continually enlarging on his misfortunes, you
may observe that he is so far from weeping that he even assigns a reason
why he should bear his wounds with patience.
Who at his enemy a stroke directs,
His sword to light upon himself expects.
Patroclus, I suppose, will lead him off to his chamber to bind up his
wounds, at least if he be a man: but not a word of that; he only
inquires how the battle went:
Say how the Argives bear themselves in fight?
And yet no words can show the truth as well as those, your deeds and
visible sufferings.
Peace! and my wounds bind up;
but though Eurypylus could bear these afflictions, Г†sopus could not,
Where Hector’s fortune press’d our yielding troops;
and he explains the rest, though in pain. So unbounded is military glory
in a brave man! Shall, then, a veteran soldier be able to behave in this
manner, and shall a wise and learned man not be able? Surely the latter
might be 80able to bear pain better, and in no small degree either. At
present, however, I am confining myself to what is engendered by
practice and discipline. I am not yet come to speak of reason and
philosophy. You may often hear of old women living without victuals for
three or four days; but take away a wrestler’s provisions but for one
day, and he will implore the aid of Jupiter Olympius, the very God for
whom he exercises himself: he will cry out that he cannot endure it.
Great is the force of custom! Sportsmen will continue whole nights in
the snow; they will bear being almost frozen upon the mountains. From
practice boxers will not so much as utter a groan, however bruised by
the cestus. But what do you think of those to whom a victory in the
Olympic games seemed almost on a par with the ancient consulships of the
Roman people? What wounds will the gladiators bear, who are either
barbarians, or the very dregs of mankind! How do they, who are trained
to it, prefer being wounded to basely avoiding it! How often do they
prove that they consider nothing but the giving satisfaction to their
masters or to the people! for when covered with wounds, they send to
their masters to learn their pleasure: if it is their will, they are
ready to lie down and die. What gladiator, of even moderate reputation,
ever gave a sigh? who ever turned pale? who ever disgraced himself
either in the actual combat, or even when about to die? who that had
been defeated ever drew in his neck to avoid the stroke of death? So
great is the force of practice, deliberation, and custom! Shall this,
then, be done by
A Samnite rascal, worthy of his trade;
and shall a man born to glory have so soft a part in his soul as not to
be able to fortify it by reason and reflection? The sight of the
gladiators’ combats is by some looked on as cruel and inhuman, and I do
not know, as it is at present managed, but it may be so; but when the
guilty fought, we might receive by our ears perhaps (but certainly by
our eyes we could not) better training to harden us against pain and
death.
XVIII. I have now said enough about the effects of exercise, custom, and
careful meditation. Proceed we now 81to consider the force of reason,
unless you have something to reply to what has been said.
A. That I should interrupt you! By no means; for your discourse has
brought me over to your opinion. Let the Stoics, then, think it their
business to determine whether pain be an evil or not, while they
endeavor to show by some strained and trifling conclusions, which are
nothing to the purpose, that pain is no evil. My opinion is, that
whatever it is, it is not so great as it appears; and I say, that men
are influenced to a great extent by some false representations and
appearance of it, and that all which is really felt is capable of being
endured. Where shall I begin, then? Shall I superficially go over what I
said before, that my discourse may have a greater scope?
This, then, is agreed upon by all, and not only by learned men, but also
by the unlearned, that it becomes the brave and magnanimous—those that
have patience and a spirit above this world—not to give way to pain.
Nor has there ever been any one who did not commend a man who bore it in
this manner. That, then, which is expected from a brave man, and is
commended when it is seen, it must surely be base in any one to be
afraid of at its approach, or not to bear when it comes. But I would
have you consider whether, as all the right affections of the soul are
classed under the name of virtues, the truth is that this is not
properly the name of them all, but that they all have their name from
that leading virtue which is superior to all the rest: for the name
“virtue” comes from vir, a man, and courage is the peculiar
distinction of a man: and this virtue has two principal duties, to
despise death and pain. We must, then, exert these, if we would be men
of virtue, or, rather, if we would be men, because virtue (virtus) takes
its very name from vir, man.
XIX. You may inquire, perhaps, how? And such an inquiry is not amiss,
for philosophy is ready with her assistance. Epicurus offers himself to
you, a man far from a bad—or, I should rather say, a very good man: he
advises no more than he knows. “Despise pain,” says he. Who is it saith
this? Is it the same man who calls pain the greatest of all evils? It is
not, indeed, very consistent in him. Let us hear what he says: “If the
pain is excessive, 82it must needs be short.” I must have that over
again, for I do not apprehend what you mean exactly by “excessive” or
“short.” That is excessive than which nothing can be greater; that is
short than which nothing is shorter. I do not regard the greatness of
any pain from which, by reason of the shortness of its continuance, I
shall be delivered almost before it reaches me. But if the pain be as
great as that of Philoctetes, it will appear great indeed to me, but yet
not the greatest that I am capable of bearing; for the pain is confined
to my foot. But my eye may pain me, I may have a pain in the head, or
sides, or lungs, or in every part of me. It is far, then, from being
excessive. Therefore, says he, pain of a long continuance has more
pleasure in it than uneasiness. Now, I cannot bring myself to say so
great a man talks nonsense; but I imagine he is laughing at us. My
opinion is that the greatest pain (I say the greatest, though it may be
ten atoms less than another) is not therefore short, because acute. I
could name to you a great many good men who have been tormented many
years with the acutest pains of the gout. But this cautious man doth not
determine the measure of that greatness or of duration, so as to enable
us to know what he calls excessive with regard to pain, or short with
respect to its continuance. Let us pass him by, then, as one who says
just nothing at all; and let us force him to acknowledge,
notwithstanding he might behave himself somewhat boldly under his colic
and his strangury, that no remedy against pain can be had from him who
looks on pain as the greatest of all evils. We must apply, then, for
relief elsewhere, and nowhere better (if we seek for what is most
consistent with itself) than to those who place the chief good in
honesty, and the greatest evil in infamy. You dare not so much as groan,
or discover the least uneasiness in their company, for virtue itself
speaks to you through them.
XX. Will you, when you may observe children at Lacedæmon, and young men
at Olympia, and barbarians in the amphitheatre, receive the severest
wounds, and bear them without once opening their mouths—will you, I
say, if any pain should by chance attack you, cry out like a woman? Will
you not rather bear it with resolution and constancy? 83and not cry, It
is intolerable; nature cannot bear it! I hear what you say: Boys bear
this because they are led thereto by glory; some bear it through shame,
many through fear, and yet are we afraid that nature cannot bear what is
borne by many, and in such different circumstances? Nature not only
bears it, but challenges it, for there is nothing with her preferable,
nothing which she desires more than credit, and reputation, and praise,
and honor, and glory. I choose here to describe this one thing under
many names, and I have used many that you may have the clearer idea of
it; for what I mean to say is, that whatever is desirable of itself,
proceeding from virtue, or placed in virtue, and commendable on its own
account (which I would rather agree to call the only good than deny it
to be the chief good) is what men should prefer above all things. And as
we declare this to be the case with respect to honesty, so we speak in
the contrary manner of infamy; nothing is so odious, so detestable,
nothing so unworthy of a man. And if you are thoroughly convinced of
this (for, at the beginning of this discourse, you allowed that there
appeared to you more evil in infamy than in pain), it follows that you
ought to have the command over yourself, though I scarcely know how this
expression may seem an accurate one, which appears to represent man as
made up of two natures, so that one should be in command and the other
be subject to it.
XXI. Yet this division does not proceed from ignorance; for the soul
admits of a twofold division, one of which partakes of reason, the other
is without it. When, therefore, we are ordered to give a law to
ourselves, the meaning is, that reason should restrain our rashness.
There is in the soul of every man something naturally soft, low,
enervated in a manner, and languid. Were there nothing besides this, men
would be the greatest of monsters; but there is present to every man
reason, which presides over and gives laws to all; which, by improving
itself, and making continual advances, becomes perfect virtue. It
behooves a man, then, to take care that reason shall have the command
over that part which is bound to practise obedience. In what manner? you
will say. Why, as a master has over his slave, a general over his 84army,
a father over his son. If that part of the soul which I have called soft
behaves disgracefully, if it gives itself up to lamentations and
womanish tears, then let it be restrained, and committed to the care of
friends and relations, for we often see those persons brought to order
by shame whom no reasons can influence. Therefore, we should confine
those feelings, like our servants, in safe custody, and almost with
chains. But those who have more resolution, and yet are not utterly
immovable, we should encourage with our exhortations, as we would good
soldiers, to recollect themselves, and maintain their honor. That wisest
man of all Greece, in the Niptræ, does not lament too much over his
wounds, or, rather, he is moderate in his grief:
Move slow, my friends; your hasty speed refrain,
Lest by your motion you increase my pain.
Pacuvius is better in this than Sophocles, for in the one Ulysses
bemoans his wounds too vehemently; for the very people who carried him
after he was wounded, though his grief was moderate, yet, considering
the dignity of the man, did not scruple to say,
And thou, Ulysses, long to war inured,
Thy wounds, though great, too feebly hast endured.
The wise poet understood that custom was no contemptible instructor how
to bear pain. But the same hero complains with more decency, though in
great pain:
Assist, support me, never leave me so;
Unbind my wounds, oh! execrable woe!
He begins to give way, but instantly checks himself:
Away! begone! but cover first the sore;
For your rude hands but make my pains the more.
Do you observe how he constrains himself? not that his bodily pains were
less, but because he checks the anguish of his mind. Therefore, in the
conclusion of the Niptræ, he blames others, even when he himself is
dying:
Complaints of fortune may become the man,
None but a woman will thus weeping stand.
85And so that soft place in his soul obeys his reason, just as an abashed
soldier does his stern commander.
XXII. The man, then, in whom absolute wisdom exists (such a man, indeed,
we have never as yet seen, but the philosophers have described in their
writings what sort of man he will be, if he should exist); such a man,
or at least that perfect and absolute reason which exists in him, will
have the same authority over the inferior part as a good parent has over
his dutiful children: he will bring it to obey his nod without any
trouble or difficulty. He will rouse himself, prepare and arm himself,
to oppose pain as he would an enemy. If you inquire what arms he will
provide himself with, they will be contention, encouragement, discourse
with himself. He will say thus to himself: Take care that you are guilty
of nothing base, languid, or unmanly. He will turn over in his mind all
the different kinds of honor. Zeno of Elea will occur to him, who
suffered everything rather than betray his confederates in the design of
putting an end to the tyranny. He will reflect on Anaxarchus, the pupil
of Democritus, who, having fallen into the hands of Nicocreon, King of
Cyprus, without the least entreaty for mercy or refusal, submitted to
every kind of torture. Calanus the Indian will occur to him, an ignorant
man and a barbarian, born at the foot of Mount Caucasus, who committed
himself to the flames by his own free, voluntary act. But we, if we have
the toothache, or a pain in the foot, or if the body be anyways
affected, cannot bear it. For our sentiments of pain as well as pleasure
are so trifling and effeminate, we are so enervated and relaxed by
luxuries, that we cannot bear the sting of a bee without crying out. But
Caius Marius, a plain countryman, but of a manly soul, when he had an
operation performed on him, as I mentioned above, at first refused to be
tied down; and he is the first instance of any one’s having had an
operation performed on him without being tied down. Why, then, did
others bear it afterward? Why, from the force of example. You see, then,
that pain exists more in opinion than in nature; and yet the same Marius
gave a proof that there is something very sharp in pain for he would not
submit to have the other thigh cut. So that he bore his pain with
resolution as a man; but, 86like a reasonable person, he was not willing
to undergo any greater pain without some necessary reason. The whole,
then, consists in this—that you should have command over yourself. I
have already told you what kind of command this is; and by considering
what is most consistent with patience, fortitude, and greatness of soul,
a man not only restrains himself, but, somehow or other, mitigates even
pain itself.
XXIII. Even as in a battle the dastardly and timorous soldier throws
away his shield on the first appearance of an enemy, and runs as fast as
he can, and on that account loses his life sometimes, though he has
never received even one wound, when he who stands his ground has nothing
of the sort happen to him, so they who cannot bear the appearance of
pain throw themselves away, and give themselves up to affliction and
dismay. But they that oppose it, often come off more than a match for
it. For the body has a certain resemblance to the soul: as burdens are
more easily borne the more the body is exerted, while they crush us if
we give way, so the soul by exerting itself resists the whole weight
that would oppress it; but if it yields, it is so pressed that it cannot
support itself. And if we consider things truly, the soul should exert
itself in every pursuit, for that is the only security for its doing its
duty. But this should be principally regarded in pain, that we must not
do anything timidly, or dastardly, or basely, or slavishly, or
effeminately, and, above all things, we must dismiss and avoid that
Philoctetean sort of outcry. A man is allowed sometimes to groan, but
yet seldom; but it is not permissible even in a woman to howl; for such
a noise as this is forbidden, by the twelve tables, to be used even at
funerals. Nor does a wise or brave man ever groan, unless when he exerts
himself to give his resolution greater force, as they who run in the
stadium make as much noise as they can. The wrestlers, too, do the same
when they are training; and the boxers, when they aim a blow with the
cestus at their adversary, give a groan, not because they are in pain,
or from a sinking of their spirits, but because their whole body is put
upon the stretch by the throwing-out of these groans, and the blow comes
the stronger.
87XXIV. What! they who would speak louder than ordinary are they
satisfied with working their jaws, sides, or tongue or stretching the
common organs of speech and utterance? The whole body and every muscle
is at full stretch if I may be allowed the expression; every nerve is
exerted to assist their voice. I have actually seen the knees of Marcus
Antonius touch the ground when he was speaking with vehemence for
himself, with relation to the Varian law. For, as the engines you throw
stones or darts with throw them out with the greater force the more they
are strained and drawn back; so it is in speaking, running, or
boxing—the more people strain themselves, the greater their force.
Since, therefore, this exertion has so much influence—if in a moment of
pain groans help to strengthen the mind, let us use them; but if they be
groans of lamentation, if they be the expression of weakness or
abjectness, or unmanly weeping, then I should scarcely call him a man
who yielded to them. For even supposing that such groaning could give
any ease, it still should be considered whether it were consistent with
a brave and resolute man. But if it does not ease our pain, why should
we debase ourselves to no purpose? For what is more unbecoming in a man
than to cry like a woman? But this precept which is laid down with
respect to pain is not confined to it. We should apply this exertion of
the soul to everything else. Is anger inflamed? is lust excited? we must
have recourse to the same citadel, and apply to the same arms. But since
it is pain which we are at present discussing, we will let the other
subjects alone. To bear pain, then, sedately and calmly, it is of great
use to consider with all our soul, as the saying is, how noble it is to
do so, for we are naturally desirous (as I said before, but it cannot be
too often repeated) and very much inclined to what is honorable, of
which, if we discover but the least glimpse, there is nothing which we
are not prepared to undergo and suffer to attain it. From this impulse
of our minds, this desire for genuine glory and honorable conduct, it is
that such dangers are supported in war, and that brave men are not
sensible of their wounds in action, or, if they are sensible of them,
prefer death to the departing but the least step 88from their honor. The
Decii saw the shining swords of their enemies when they were rushing
into the battle. But the honorable character and the glory of the death
which they were seeking made all fear of death of little weight. Do you
imagine that Epaminondas groaned when he perceived that his life was
flowing out with his blood? No; for he left his country triumphing over
the Lacedæmonians, whereas he had found it in subjection to them. These
are the comforts, these are the things that assuage the greatest pain.
XXV. You may ask, How the case is in peace? What is to be done at home?
How we are to behave in bed? You bring me back to the philosophers, who
seldom go to war. Among these, Dionysius of Heraclea, a man certainly of
no resolution, having learned fortitude of Zeno, quitted it on being in
pain; for, being tormented with a pain in his kidneys, in bewailing
himself he cried out that those things were false which he had formerly
conceived of pain. And when his fellow-disciple, Cleanthes, asked him
why he had changed his opinion, he answered, “That the case of any man
who had applied so much time to philosophy, and yet was unable to bear
pain, might be a sufficient proof that pain is an evil; that he himself
had spent many years at philosophy, and yet could not bear pain: it
followed, therefore, that pain was an evil.” It is reported that
Cleanthes on that struck his foot on the ground, and repeated a verse
out of the Epigonæ:
Amphiaraus, hear’st thou this below?
He meant Zeno: he was sorry the other had degenerated from him.
But it was not so with our friend Posidonius, whom I have often seen
myself; and I will tell you what Pompey used to say of him: that when he
came to Rhodes, after his departure from Syria, he had a great desire to
hear Posidonius, but was informed that he was very ill of a severe fit
of the gout; yet he had great inclination to pay a visit to so famous a
philosopher. Accordingly, when he had seen him, and paid his
compliments, and had spoken with great respect of him, he said he was
very sorry that he could not hear him lecture. “But indeed you may,”
89replied the other, “nor will I suffer any bodily pain to occasion so
great a man to visit me in vain.” On this Pompey relates that, as he lay
on his bed, he disputed with great dignity and fluency on this very
subject: that nothing was good but what was honest; and that in his
paroxysms he would often say, “Pain, it is to no purpose;
notwithstanding you are troublesome, I will never acknowledge you an
evil.” And in general all celebrated and notorious afflictions become
endurable by disregarding them.
XXVI. Do we not observe that where those exercises called gymnastic are
in esteem, those who enter the lists never concern themselves about
dangers? that where the praise of riding and hunting is highly esteemed,
they who practice these arts decline no pain? What shall I say of our
own ambitious pursuits or desire of honors? What fire have not
candidates run through to gain a single vote? Therefore Africanus had
always in his hands Xenophon, the pupil of Socrates, being particularly
pleased with his saying, that the same labors were not equally heavy to
the general and to the common man, because the honor itself made the
labor lighter to the general. But yet, so it happens, that even with the
illiterate vulgar an idea of honor is of great influence, though they
cannot understand what it is. They are led by report and common opinion
to look on that as honorable which has the general voice. Not that I
would have you, should the multitude be ever so fond of you, rely on
their judgment, nor approve of everything which they think right: you
must use your own judgment. If you are satisfied with yourself when you
have approved of what is right, you will not only have the mastery over
yourself (which I recommended to you just now), but over everybody, and
everything. Lay this down, then, as a rule, that a great capacity, and
lofty elevation of soul, which distinguishes itself most by despising
and looking down with contempt on pain, is the most excellent of all
things, and the more so if it does not depend on the people and does not
aim at applause, but derives its satisfaction from itself. Besides, to
me, indeed, everything seems the more commendable the less the people
are courted, and the fewer eyes there 90are to see it. Not that you
should avoid the public, for every generous action loves the public
view; yet no theatre for virtue is equal to a consciousness of it.
XXVII. And let this be principally considered: that this bearing of
pain, which I have often said is to be strengthened by an exertion of
the soul, should be the same in everything. For you meet with many who,
through a desire of victory, or for glory, or to maintain their rights,
or their liberty, have boldly received wounds, and borne themselves up
under them; and yet those very same persons, by relaxing that
intenseness of their minds, were unequal to bearing the pain of a
disease; for they did not support themselves under their former
sufferings by reason or philosophy, but by inclination and glory.
Therefore some barbarians and savage people are able to fight very
stoutly with the sword, but cannot bear sickness like men; but the
Grecians, men of no great courage, but as wise as human nature will
admit of, cannot look an enemy in the face, yet the same will bear to be
visited with sickness tolerably, and with a sufficiently manly spirit;
and the Cimbrians and Celtiberians are very alert in battle, but bemoan
themselves in sickness. For nothing can be consistent which has not
reason for its foundation. But when you see those who are led by
inclination or opinion, not retarded by pain in their pursuits, nor
hindered by it from succeeding in them, you may conclude, either that
pain is no evil, or that, notwithstanding you may choose to call an evil
whatever is disagreeable and contrary to nature, yet it is so very
trifling an evil that it may so effectually be got the better of by
virtue as quite to disappear. And I would have you think of this night
and day; for this argument will spread itself, and take up more room
some time or other, and not be confined to pain alone; for if the
motives to all our actions are to avoid disgrace and acquire honor, we
may not only despise the stings of pain, but the storms of fortune,
especially if we have recourse to that retreat which was pointed out in
our yesterday’s discussion; for, as if some God had advised a man who
was pursued by pirates to throw himself overboard, saying, “There is
something at hand to receive you; either a dolphin will take you up, as
it did Arion of 91Methymna; or those horses sent by Neptune to Pelops
(who are said to have carried chariots so rapidly as to be borne up by
the waves) will receive you, and convey you wherever you please. Cast
away all fear.” So, though your pains be ever so sharp and disagreeable,
if the case is not such that it is worth your while to endure them, you
see whither you may betake yourself. I think this will do for the
present. But perhaps you still abide by your opinion.
A. Not in the least, indeed; and I hope I am freed by these two days’
discourses from the fear of two things that I greatly dreaded.
M. To-morrow, then, for rhetoric, as we were saying. But I see we must
not drop our philosophy.
A. No, indeed; we will have the one in the forenoon, and this at the
usual time.
M. It shall be so, and I will comply with your very laudable
inclinations.
BOOK III.
ON GRIEF OF MIND.
I.
What reason shall I assign, O Brutus, why, as we consist of mind and
body, the art of curing and preserving the body should be so much sought
after, and the invention of it, as being so useful, should be ascribed
to the immortal Gods; but the medicine of the mind should not have been
so much the object of inquiry while it was unknown, nor so much attended
to and cultivated after its discovery, nor so well received or approved
of by some, and accounted actually disagreeable, and looked upon with an
envious eye by many? Is it because we, by means of the mind, judge of
the pains and disorders of the body, but do not, by means of the body,
arrive at any perception of the disorders of the mind? Hence it comes
that the mind only judges of itself when that very faculty by which it
is judged is in a bad state. Had nature given us faculties for
discerning and viewing herself, and could we go through life by keeping
our eye on her—our best guide—
92there would be no reason certainly why
any one should be in want of philosophy or learning; but, as it is, she
has furnished us only with some feeble rays of light, which we
immediately extinguish so completely by evil habits and erroneous
opinions that the light of nature is nowhere visible. The seeds of
virtues are natural to our constitutions, and, were they suffered to
come to maturity, would naturally conduct us to a happy life; but now,
as soon as we are born and received into the world, we are instantly
familiarized with all kinds of depravity and perversity of opinions; so
that we may be said almost to suck in error with our nurse’s milk. When
we return to our parents, and are put into the hands of tutors and
governors, we are imbued with so many errors that truth gives place to
falsehood, and nature herself to established opinion.
II. To these we may add the poets; who, on account of the appearance
they exhibit of learning and wisdom, are heard, read, and got by heart,
and make a deep impression on our minds. But when to these are added the
people, who are, as it were, one great body of instructors, and the
multitude, who declare unanimously for what is wrong, then are we
altogether overwhelmed with bad opinions, and revolt entirely from
nature; so that they seem to deprive us of our best guide who have
decided that there is nothing better for man, nothing more worthy of
being desired by him, nothing more excellent, than honors and commands,
and a high reputation with the people; which indeed every excellent man
aims at; but while he pursues that only true honor which nature has in
view above all other objects, he finds himself busied in arrant trifles,
and in pursuit of no conspicuous form of virtue, but only some shadowy
representation of glory. For glory is a real and express substance, not
a mere shadow. It consists in the united praise of good men, the free
voice of those who form a true judgment of pre-eminent virtue; it is, as
it were, the very echo of virtue; and being generally the attendant on
laudable actions, should not be slighted by good men. But popular fame,
which would pretend to imitate it, is hasty and inconsiderate, and
generally commends wicked and immoral actions, and throws discredit upon
the appearance and beauty of honesty by assuming
93a resemblance of it.
And it is owing to their not being able to discover the difference
between them that some men ignorant of real excellence, and in what it
consists, have been the destruction of their country and of themselves.
And thus the best men have erred, not so much in their intentions as by
a mistaken conduct. What? is no cure to be attempted to be applied to
those who are carried away by the love of money, or the lust of
pleasures, by which they are rendered little short of madmen, which is
the case of all weak people? or is it because the disorders of the mind
are less dangerous than those of the body? or because the body will
admit of a cure, while there is no medicine whatever for the mind?
III. But there are more disorders of the mind than of the body, and they
are of a more dangerous nature; for these very disorders are the more
offensive because they belong to the mind and disturb it; and the mind,
when disordered, is, as Ennius says, in a constant error: it can neither
bear nor endure anything, and is under the perpetual influence of
desires. Now, what disorders can be worse to the body than these two
distempers of the mind (for I overlook others), weakness and desire? But
how, indeed, can it be maintained that the mind cannot prescribe for
itself, when she it is who has invented the medicines for the body,
when, with regard to bodily cures, constitution and nature have a great
share, nor do all who suffer themselves to be cured find that effect
instantly; but those minds which are disposed to be cured, and submit to
the precepts of the wise, may undoubtedly recover a healthy state?
Philosophy is certainly the medicine of the soul, whose assistance we do
not seek from abroad, as in bodily disorders, but we ourselves are bound
to exert our utmost energy and power in order to effect our cure. But as
to philosophy in general, I have, I think, in my Hortensius,
sufficiently spoken of the credit and attention which it deserves: since
that, indeed, I have been continually either disputing or writing on its
most material branches; and I have laid down in these books all the
discussions which took place between myself and my particular friends at
my Tusculan villa. But as I have spoken in the two former of pain and
death, this book shall be
94devoted to the account of the third day of
our disputations.
We came down into the Academy when the day was already declining towards
afternoon, and I asked one of those who were present to propose a
subject for us to discourse on; and then the business was carried on in
this manner:
IV.
A. My opinion is, that a wise man is subject to grief.
M. What, and to the other perturbations of mind, as fears, lusts,
anger? For these are pretty much like what the Greeks call
ПЂбЅ±ОёО·. I might
call them diseases, and that would be a literal translation, but it is
not agreeable to our way of speaking. For envy, delight, and pleasure
are all called by the Greeks diseases, being affections of the mind not
in subordination to reason; but we, I think, are right in calling the
same motions of a disturbed soul perturbations, and in very seldom using
the term diseases; though, perhaps, it appears otherwise to you.
A. I am of your opinion.
M. And do you think a wise man subject to these?
A. Entirely, I think.
M. Then that boasted wisdom is but of small account, if it differs so
little from madness?
A. What? does every commotion of the mind seem to you to be madness?
M. Not to me only; but I apprehend, though I have often been surprised
at it, that it appeared so to our ancestors many ages before Socrates;
from whom is derived all that philosophy which relates to life and
morals.
A. How so?
M. Because the name madness
35 implies a sickness of the mind and
disease; that is to say, an unsoundness and an unhealthiness of mind,
which they call madness. But the philosophers call all perturbations of
the soul diseases, and their opinion is that no fool is ever free from
these; but all that are diseased are unsound; and the minds of all fools
are diseased; therefore all fools are mad. For they held that soundness
of the mind depends on a certain
95tranquillity and steadiness; and a
mind which was destitute of these qualities they called insane, because
soundness was inconsistent with a perturbed mind just as much as with a
disordered body.
V. Nor were they less ingenious in calling the state of the soul devoid
of the light of the mind, “a being out of one’s mind,” “a being beside
one’s self.” From whence we may understand that they who gave these
names to things were of the same opinion with Socrates, that all silly
people were unsound, which the Stoics have carefully preserved as being
derived from him; for whatever mind is distempered (and, as I just now
said, the philosophers call all perturbed motions of the mind
distempers) is no more sound than a body is when in a fit of sickness.
Hence it is that wisdom is the soundness of the mind, folly a sort of
unsoundness, which is insanity, or a being out of one’s mind: and these
are much better expressed by the Latin words than the Greek, which you
will find the case also in many other topics. But we will discuss that
point elsewhere: let us now attend to our present subject. The very
meaning of the word describes the whole thing about which we are
inquiring, both as to its substance and character. For we must
necessarily understand by “sound” those whose minds are under no
perturbation from any motion as if it were a disease. They who are
differently affected we must necessarily call “unsound.” So that nothing
is better than what is usual in Latin, to say that they who are run away
with by their lust or anger have quitted the command over themselves;
though anger includes lust, for anger is defined to be the lust of
revenge. They, then, who are said not to be masters of themselves, are
said to be so because they are not under the government of reason, to
which is assigned by nature the power over the whole soul. Why the
Greeks should call this mania, I do not easily apprehend; but we define
it much better than they, for we distinguish this madness (
insania),
which, being allied to folly, is more extensive, from what we call
furor, or raving. The Greeks, indeed, would do so too, but they have
no one word that will express it: what we call
furor, they call
ОјОµО»О±ОіП‡ОїО»бЅ·О±, as if the reason
96were affected only by a black bile, and
not disturbed as often by a violent rage, or fear, or grief. Thus we say
Athamas, Alcmæon, Ajax, and Orestes were raving (
furere); because a
person affected in this manner was not allowed by the Twelve Tables to
have the management of his own affairs; therefore the words are not, if
he is mad (
insanus), but if he begins to be raving (
furiosus). For
they looked upon madness to be an unsettled humor that proceeded from
not being of sound mind; yet such a person might perform his ordinary
duties, and discharge the usual and customary requirements of life: but
they considered one that was raving as afflicted with a total blindness
of the mind, which, notwithstanding it is allowed to be greater than
madness, is nevertheless of such a nature that a wise man may be subject
to raving (
furor), but cannot possibly be afflicted by insanity
(
insania). But this is another question: let us now return to our
original subject.
VI. I think you said that it was your opinion that a wise man was liable
to grief.
A. And so, indeed, I think.
M. It is natural enough to think so, for we are not the offspring of
flints; but we have by nature something soft and tender in our souls,
which may be put into a violent motion by grief, as by a storm; nor did
that Crantor, who was one of the most distinguished men that our Academy
has ever produced, say this amiss: “I am by no means of their opinion
who talk so much in praise of I know not what insensibility, which
neither can exist, nor ought to exist”. “I would choose,” says he, “never
to be ill; but should I be so, still I should choose to retain my
sensation, whether there was to be an amputation or any other separation
of anything from my body. For that insensibility cannot be but at the
expense of some unnatural ferocity of mind, or stupor of body.”But let
us consider whether to talk in this manner be not allowing that we are
weak, and yielding to our softness. Notwithstanding, let us be hardy
enough, not only to lop off every arm of our miseries, but even to pluck
up every fibre of their roots. Yet still something, perhaps, may be left
behind, so deep does folly strike its roots: but whatever may be
97left
it will be no more than is necessary. But let us be persuaded of this,
that unless the mind be in a sound state, which philosophy alone can
effect, there can be no end of our miseries. Wherefore, as we began, let
us submit ourselves to it for a cure; we shall be cured if we choose to
be. I shall advance something further. I shall not treat of grief alone,
though that indeed is the principal thing; but, as I originally
proposed, of every perturbation of the mind, as I termed it; disorder,
as the Greeks call it: and first, with your leave, I shall treat it in
the manner of the Stoics, whose method is to reduce their arguments into
a very small space; afterward I shall enlarge more in my own way.
VII. A man of courage is also full of faith. I do not use the word
confident, because, owing to an erroneous custom of speaking, that word
has come to be used in a bad sense, though it is derived from confiding,
which is commendable. But he who is full of faith is certainly under no
fear; for there is an inconsistency between faith and fear. Now, whoever
is subject to grief is subject to fear; for whatever things we grieve at
when present we dread when hanging over us and approaching. Thus it
comes about that grief is inconsistent with courage: it is very
probable, therefore, that whoever is subject to grief is also liable to
fear, and to a broken kind of spirits and sinking. Now, whenever these
befall a man, he is in a servile state, and must own that he is
overpowered; for whoever admits these feelings, must admit timidity and
cowardice. But these cannot enter into the mind of a man of courage;
neither, therefore, can grief: but the man of courage is the only wise
man; therefore grief cannot befall the wise man. It is, besides,
necessary that whoever is brave should be a man of great soul; that
whoever is a man of a great soul should be invincible; whoever is
invincible looks down with contempt on all things here, and considers
them, beneath him. But no one can despise those things on account of
which he may be affected with grief; from whence it follows that a wise
man is never affected with grief: for all wise men are brave; therefore
a wise man is not subject to grief. And as the eye, when disordered, is
not in a good condition for performing its
98office properly; and as the
other parts, and the whole body itself, when unsettled, cannot perform
their office and business; so the mind, when disordered, is but
ill-fitted to perform its duty. The office of the mind is to use its
reason well; but the mind of a wise man is always in condition to make
the best use of his reason, and therefore is never out of order. But
grief is a disorder of the mind; therefore a wise man will be always
free from it.
VIII. And from these considerations we may get at a very probable
definition of the temperate man, whom the Greeks call
ПѓбЅЅП†ПЃП‰ОЅ: and they
call that virtue
ПѓП‰П†ПЃОїПѓбЅ»ОЅО·ОЅ, which I at one time call temperance, at
another time moderation, and sometimes even modesty; but I do not know
whether that virtue may not be properly called frugality, which has a
more confined meaning with the Greeks; for they call frugal men
П‡ПЃО·ПѓбЅ·ОјОїП…П‚, which implies only that they are useful; but our name has a
more extensive meaning: for all abstinence, all innocency (which the
Greeks have no ordinary name for, though they might use the word
бјЂОІО»бЅ±ОІОµО№О±, for innocency is that disposition of mind which would offend
no one) and several other virtues are comprehended under frugality; but
if this quality were of less importance, and confined in as small a
compass as some imagine, the surname of Piso
36 would not have been in
so great esteem. But as we allow him not the name of a frugal man
(
frugi), who either quits his post through fear, which is cowardice;
or who reserves to his own use what was privately committed to his
keeping, which is injustice; or who fails in his military undertakings
through rashness, which is folly—for that reason the word frugality
takes in these three virtues of fortitude, justice, and prudence, though
it is indeed common to all virtues, for they are all connected and knit
together. Let us allow, then, frugality itself to be another and fourth
virtue; for its peculiar property seems to be, to govern and appease all
tendencies to too eager a desire after anything, to restrain lust, and
to preserve a decent steadiness in everything. The vice in contrast to
this is called prodigality (
nequitia). Frugality, I imagine, is
derived from the
99word
fruge, the best thing which the earth produces;
nequitia is derived (though this is perhaps rather more strained;
still, let us try it; we shall only be thought to have been trifling if
there is nothing in what we say) from the fact of everything being to no
purpose (
nequicquam) in such a man; from which circumstance he is
called also
Nihil, nothing. Whoever is frugal, then, or, if it is more
agreeable to you, whoever is moderate and temperate, such a one must of
course be consistent; whoever is consistent, must be quiet; the quiet
man must be free from all perturbation, therefore from grief likewise:
and these are the properties of a wise man; therefore a wise man must be
free from grief.
IX. So that Dionysius of Heraclea is right when, upon this complaint of
Achilles in Homer,
Well hast thou spoke, but at the tyrant’s name
My rage rekindles, and my soul’s in flame:
’Tis just resentment, and becomes the brave,
Disgraced, dishonor’d like the vilest slave
37—
he reasons thus: Is the hand as it should be, when it is affected with a
swelling? or is it possible for any other member of the body, when
swollen or enlarged, to be in any other than a disordered state? Must
not the mind, then, when it is puffed up, or distended, be out of order?
But the mind of a wise man is always free from every kind of disorder:
it never swells, never is puffed up; but the mind when in anger is in a
different state. A wise man, therefore, is never angry; for when he is
angry, he lusts after something; for whoever is angry naturally has a
longing desire to give all the pain he can to the person who he thinks
has injured him; and whoever has this earnest desire must necessarily be
much pleased with the accomplishment of his wishes; hence he is
delighted with his neighbor’s misery; and as a wise man is not capable
of such feelings as these, he is therefore not capable of anger. But
should a wise man be subject to grief, he may likewise 100be subject to
anger; for as he is free from anger, he must likewise be free from
grief. Again, could a wise man be subject to grief, he might also be
liable to pity, or even might be open to a disposition towards envy
(invidentia); I do not say to envy (invidia), for that can only
exist by the very act of envying: but we may fairly form the word
invidentia from invidendo, and so avoid the doubtful name invidia;
for this word is probably derived from in and video, looking too
closely into another’s fortune; as it is said in the Melanippus,
Who envies me the flower of my children?
where the Latin is invidit florem. It may appear not good Latin, but
it is very well put by Accius; for as video governs an accusative
case, so it is more correct to say invideo florem than flori. We are
debarred from saying so by common usage. The poet stood in his own
right, and expressed himself with more freedom.
X. Therefore compassion and envy are consistent in the same man; for
whoever is uneasy at any one’s adversity is also uneasy at another’s
prosperity: as Theophrastus, while he laments the death of his companion
Callisthenes, is at the same time disturbed at the success of Alexander;
and therefore he says that Callisthenes met with man of the greatest
power and good fortune, but one who did not know how to make use of his
good fortune. And as pity is an uneasiness which arises from the
misfortunes of another, so envy is an uneasiness that proceeds from the
good success of another: therefore whoever is capable of pity is capable
of envy. But a wise man is incapable of envy, and consequently incapable
of pity. But were a wise man used to grieve, to pity also would be
familiar to him; therefore to grieve is a feeling which cannot affect a
wise man. Now, though these reasonings of the Stoics, and their
conclusions, are rather strained and distorted, and ought to be
expressed in a less stringent and narrow manner, yet great stress is to
be laid on the opinions of those men who have a peculiarly bold and
manly turn of thought and sentiment. For our friends the Peripatetics,
notwithstanding all their erudition, gravity, and fluency of language,
do not satisfy me about the moderation of these disorders and diseases
101of the soul which they insist upon; for every evil, though moderate, is
in its nature great. But our object is to make out that the wise man is
free from all evil; for as the body is unsound if it is ever so slightly
affected, so the mind under any moderate disorder loses its soundness;
therefore the Romans have, with their usual accuracy of expression,
called trouble, and anguish, and vexation, on account of the analogy
between a troubled mind and a diseased body, disorders. The Greeks call
all perturbation of mind by pretty nearly the same name; for they name
every turbid motion of the soul ПЂбЅ±ОёОїП‚, that is to say, a distemper. But
we have given them a more proper name; for a disorder of the mind is
very like a disease of the body. But lust does not resemble sickness;
neither does immoderate joy, which is an elated and exulting pleasure of
the mind. Fear, too, is not very like a distemper, though it is akin to
grief of mind, but properly, as is also the case with sickness of the
body, so too sickness of mind has no name separated from pain. And
therefore I must explain the origin of this pain, that is to say, the
cause that occasions this grief in the mind, as if it were a sickness of
the body. For as physicians think they have found out the cure when they
have discovered the cause of the distemper, so we shall discover the
method of curing melancholy when the cause of it is found out.
XI. The whole cause, then, is in opinion; and this observation applies
not to this grief alone, but to every other disorder of the mind, which
are of four sorts, but consisting of many parts. For as every disorder
or perturbation is a motion of the mind, either devoid of reason, or in
despite of reason, or in disobedience to reason, and as that motion is
excited by an opinion of either good or evil; these four perturbations
are divided equally into two parts: for two of them proceed from an
opinion of good, one of which is an exulting pleasure, that is to say, a
joy elated beyond measure, arising from an opinion of some present great
good; the other is a desire which may fairly be called even a lust, and
is an immoderate inclination after some conceived great good without any
obedience to reason. Therefore these two kinds, the exulting pleasure
and the lust, have their rise from an opinion of good, as 102the other
two, fear and grief, have from an opinion of evil. For fear is an
opinion of some great evil impending over us, and grief is an opinion of
some great evil present; and, indeed, it is a freshly conceived opinion
of an evil so great that to grieve at it seems right: it is of that kind
that he who is uneasy at it thinks he has good reason to be so. Now we
should exert, our utmost efforts to oppose these perturbations—which
are, as it were, so many furies let loose upon us and urged on by
folly—if we are desirous to pass this share of life that is allotted to
us with ease and satisfaction. But of the other feelings I shall speak
elsewhere: our business at present is to drive away grief if we can, for
that shall be the object of our present discussion, since you have said
that it was your opinion that a wise man might be subject to grief,
which I can by no means allow of; for it is a frightful, miserable, and
detestable thing, which we should fly from with our utmost efforts—with
all our sails and oars, as I may say.
XII. That descendant of Tantalus, how does he appear to you—he who
sprung from Pelops, who formerly stole Hippodamia from her
father-in-law, King Œnomaus, and married her by force?—he who was
descended from Jupiter himself, how broken-hearted and dispirited does
he not seem!
Stand off, my friends, nor come within my shade,
That no pollutions your sound hearts pervade,
So foul a stain my body doth partake.
Will you condemn yourself, Thyestes, and deprive yourself of life, on
account of the greatness of another’s crime? What do you think of that
son of Phœbus? Do you not look upon him as unworthy of his own father’s
light?
Hollow his eyes, his body worn away,
His furrow’d cheeks his frequent tears betray;
His beard neglected, and his hoary hairs
Rough and uncomb’d, bespeak his bitter cares.
O foolish Г†etes! these are evils which you yourself have been the cause
of, and are not occasioned by any accidents with which chance has
visited you; and you behaved as you did, even after you had been inured
to your distress, and after the first swelling of the mind had
subsided!—whereas grief consists (as I shall show) in the notion of
103some recent evil—but your grief, it is very plain, proceeded from the
loss of your kingdom, not of your daughter, for you hated her, and
perhaps with reason, but you could not calmly bear to part with your
kingdom. But surely it is an impudent grief which preys upon a man for
not being able to command those that are free. Dionysius, it is true,
the tyrant of Syracuse, when driven from his country, taught a school at
Corinth; so incapable was he of living without some authority. But what
could be more impudent than Tarquin, who made war upon those who could
not bear his tyranny; and, when he could not recover his kingdom by the
aid of the forces of the Veientians and the Latins, is said to have
betaken himself to Cuma, and to have died in that city of old age and
grief!
XIII. Do you, then, think that it can befall a wise man to be oppressed
with grief, that is to say, with misery? for, as all perturbation is
misery, grief is the rack itself. Lust is attended with heat, exulting
joy with levity, fear with meanness, but grief with something greater
than these; it consumes, torments, afflicts, and disgraces a man; it
tears him, preys upon his mind, and utterly destroys him: if we do not
so divest ourselves of it as to throw it completely off, we cannot be
free from misery. And it is clear that there must be grief where
anything has the appearance of a present sore and oppressing evil.
Epicurus is of opinion that grief arises naturally from the imagination
of any evil; so that whosoever is eye-witness of any great misfortune,
if he conceives that the like may possibly befall himself, becomes sad
instantly from such an idea. The Cyrenaics think that grief is not
engendered by every kind of evil, but only by unexpected, unforeseen
evil; and that circumstance is, indeed, of no small effect on the
heightening of grief; for whatsoever comes of a sudden appears more
formidable. Hence these lines are deservedly commended:
I knew my son, when first he drew his breath,
Destined by fate to an untimely death;
And when I sent him to defend the Greeks,
War was his business, not your sportive freaks.
XIV. Therefore, this ruminating beforehand upon future evils which you
see at a distance makes their approach
104more tolerable; and on this
account what Euripides makes Theseus say is much commended. You will
give me leave to translate them, as is usual with me:
I treasured up what some learn’d sage did tell,
And on my future misery did dwell;
I thought of bitter death, of being drove
Far from my home by exile, and I strove
With every evil to possess my mind,
That, when they came, I the less care might find.
38
But Euripides says that of himself, which Theseus said he had heard from
some learned man, for the poet had been a pupil of Anaxagoras, who, as
they relate, on hearing of the death of his son, said, “I knew that my
son was mortal;” which speech seems to intimate that such things afflict
those men who have not thought on them before. Therefore, there is no
doubt but that all those things which are considered evils are the
heavier from not being foreseen. Though, notwithstanding this is not the
only circumstance which occasions the greatest grief, still, as the
mind, by foreseeing and preparing for it, has great power to make all
grief the less, a man should at all times consider all the events that
may befall him in this life; and certainly the excellence and divine
nature of wisdom consists in taking a near view of, and gaining a
thorough acquaintance with, all human affairs, in not being surprised
when anything happens, and in thinking, before the event, that there is
nothing but what may come to pass.
Wherefore ev’ry man,
When his affairs go on most swimmingly,
E’en then it most behooves to arm himself
Against the coming storm: loss, danger, exile,
Returning ever, let him look to meet;
His son in fault, wife dead, or daughter sick;
All common accidents, and may have happen’d
That nothing shall seem new or strange. But if
Aught has fall’n out beyond his hopes, all that
Let him account clear gain.39
105XV. Therefore, as Terence has so well expressed what he borrowed from
philosophy, shall not we, from whose fountains he drew it, say the same
thing in a better manner, and abide by it with more steadiness? Hence
came that steady countenance, which, according to Xantippe, her husband
Socrates always had; so that she said that she never observed any
difference in his looks when he went out and when he came home. Yet the
look of that old Roman, M. Crassus, who, as Lucilius says, never smiled
but once in his lifetime, was not of this kind, but placid and serene,
for so we are told. He, indeed, might well have had the same look at all
times who never changed his mind, from which the countenance derives its
expression. So that I am ready to borrow of the Cyrenaics those arms
against the accidents and events of life by means of which, by long
premeditation, they break the force of all approaching evils; and at the
same time I think that those very evils themselves arise more from
opinion than nature, for if they were real, no forecast could make them
lighter. But I shall speak more particularly on these matters after I
have first considered Epicurus’s opinion, who thinks that all people
must necessarily be uneasy who believe themselves to be in any evils,
let them be either foreseen and expected, or habitual to them; for with
him evils are not the less by reason of their continuance, nor the
lighter for having been foreseen; and it is folly to ruminate on evils
to come, or such as, perhaps, never may come: every evil is disagreeable
enough when it does come; but he who is constantly considering that some
evil may befall him is loading himself with a perpetual evil; and even
should such evil never light on him, he voluntarily takes upon himself
unnecessary misery, so that he is under constant uneasiness, whether he
actually suffers any evil, or only thinks of it. But he makes the
alleviation of grief depend on two things—a ceasing to think on evil,
and a turning to the contemplation of pleasure. For he thinks that the
mind may possibly be under the power of reason, and follow her
directions: he forbids us, therefore, to mind trouble, and calls us off
from sorrowful reflections; he throws a mist over our eyes to hinder us
from the contemplation of misery. Having sounded a retreat
106from this
statement, he drives our thoughts on again, and encourages them to view
and engage the whole mind in the various pleasures with which he thinks
the life of a wise man abounds, either from reflecting on the past, or
from the hope of what is to come. I have said these things in my own
way; the Epicureans have theirs. However, let us examine what they say;
how they say it is of little consequence.
XVI. In the first place, they are wrong in forbidding men to premeditate
on futurity and blaming their wish to do so; for there is nothing that
breaks the edge of grief and lightens it more than considering, during
one’s whole life, that there is nothing which it is impossible should
happen, or than, considering what human nature is, on what conditions
life was given, and how we may comply with them. The effect of which is
that we are always grieving, but that we never do so; for whoever
reflects on the nature of things, the various turns of life, and the
weakness of human nature, grieves, indeed, at that reflection; but while
so grieving he is, above all other times, behaving as a wise man, for he
gains these two things by it: one, that while he is considering the
state of human nature he is performing the especial duties of
philosophy, and is provided with a triple medicine against adversity—in
the first place, because he has long reflected that such things might
befall him, and this reflection by itself contributes much towards
lessening and weakening all misfortunes; and, secondly, because he is
persuaded that we should bear all the accidents which can happen to man
with the feelings and spirit of a man; and, lastly, because he considers
that what is blamable is the only evil. But it is not your fault that
something has happened to you which it was impossible for man to avoid.
For that withdrawing of our thoughts which he recommends when he calls
us off from contemplating our misfortunes is an imaginary action; for it
is not in our power to dissemble or to forget those evils which lie
heavy on us; they tear, vex, and sting us—they burn us up, and leave no
breathing time. And do you order us to forget them (for such
forgetfulness is contrary to nature), and at the same time deprive us of
the only assistance which nature affords, the being accustomed to them?
107For that, though it is but a slow medicine (I mean that which is
brought by lapse of time), is still a very effectual one. You order me
to employ my thoughts on something good, and forget my misfortunes. You
would say something worthy a great philosopher if you thought those
things good which are best suited to the dignity of human nature.
XVII. Should Pythagoras, Socrates, or Plato say to me, Why are you
dejected or sad? Why do you faint, and yield to fortune, which, perhaps,
may have power to harass and disturb you, but should not quite unman
you? There is great power in the virtues; rouse them, if they chance to
droop. Take fortitude for your guide, which will give you such spirits
that you will despise everything that can befall man, and look on it as
a trifle. Add to this temperance, which is moderation, and which was
just now called frugality, which will not suffer you to do anything base
or bad—for what is worse or baser than an effeminate man? Not even
justice will suffer you to act in this manner, though she seems to have
the least weight in this affair; but still, notwithstanding, even she
will inform you that you are doubly unjust when you both require what
does not belong to you, inasmuch as though you who have been born mortal
demand to be placed in the condition of the immortals, and at the same
time you take it much to heart that you are to restore what was lent
you. What answer will you make to prudence, who informs you that she is
a virtue sufficient of herself both to teach you a good life and also to
secure you a happy one? And, indeed, if she were fettered by external
circumstances, and dependent on others, and if she did not originate in
herself and return to herself, and also embrace everything in herself,
so as to seek no adventitious aid from any quarter, I cannot imagine why
she should appear deserving of such lofty panegyrics, or of being sought
after with such excessive eagerness. Now, Epicurus, if you call me back
to such goods as these, I will obey you, and follow you, and use you as
my guide, and even forget, as you order me, all my misfortunes; and I
will do this the more readily from a persuasion that they are not to be
ranked among evils at all. But you are for bringing my thoughts over to
pleasure.
108What pleasures? Pleasures of the body, I imagine, or such as
are recollected or imagined on account of the body. Is this all? Do I
explain your opinion rightly? for your disciples are used to deny that
we understand at all what Epicurus means. This is what he says, and what
that subtle fellow, old Zeno, who is one of the sharpest of them, used,
when I was attending lectures at Athens, to enforce and talk so loudly
of; saying that he alone was happy who could enjoy present pleasure, and
who was at the same time persuaded that he should enjoy it without pain,
either during the whole or the greatest part of his life; or if, should
any pain interfere, if it was very sharp, then it must be short; should
it be of longer continuance, it would have more of what was sweet than
bitter in it; that whosoever reflected on these things would be happy,
especially if satisfied with the good things which he had already
enjoyed, and if he were without fear of death or of the Gods.
XVIII. You have here a representation of a happy life according to
Epicurus, in the words of Zeno, so that there is no room for
contradiction in any point. What, then? Can the proposing and thinking
of such a life make Thyestes’s grief the less, or Æetes’s, of whom I
spoke above, or Telamon’s, who was driven from his country to penury and
banishment? in wonder at whom men exclaimed thus:
Is this the man surpassing glory raised?
Is this that Telamon so highly praised
By wondering Greece, at whose sight, like the sun,
All others with diminish’d lustre shone?
Now, should any one, as the same author says, find his spirits sink with
the loss of his fortune, he must apply to those grave philosophers of
antiquity for relief, and not to these voluptuaries: for what great
abundance of good do they promise? Suppose that we allow that to be
without pain is the chief good? Yet that is not called pleasure. But it
is not necessary at present to go through the whole: the question is, to
what point are we to advance in order to abate our grief? Grant that to
be in pain is the greatest evil: whosoever, then, has proceeded so far
as not to be in pain, is he, therefore, in immediate possession of the
greatest good? Why, Epicurus, do we use any evasions,
109and not allow in
our own words the same feeling to be pleasure which you are used to
boast of with such assurance? Are these your words or not? This is what
you say in that book which contains all the doctrine of your school; for
I will perform on this occasion the office of a translator, lest any one
should imagine that I am inventing anything. Thus you speak: “Nor can I
form any notion of the chief good, abstracted from those pleasures which
are perceived by taste, or from what depends on hearing music, or
abstracted from ideas raised by external objects visible to the eye, or
by agreeable motions, or from those other pleasures which are perceived
by the whole man by means of any of his senses; nor can it possibly be
said that the pleasures of the mind are excited only by what is good,
for I have perceived men’s minds to be pleased with the hopes of
enjoying those things which I mentioned above, and with the idea that it
should enjoy them without any interruption from pain.” And these are his
exact words, so that any one may understand what were the pleasures with
which Epicurus was acquainted. Then he speaks thus, a little lower down:
“I have often inquired of those who have been called wise men what would
be the remaining good if they should exclude from consideration all
these pleasures, unless they meant to give us nothing but words. I could
never learn anything from them; and unless they choose that all virtue
and wisdom should vanish and come to nothing, they must say with me that
the only road to happiness lies through those pleasures which I
mentioned above.” What follows is much the same, and his whole book on
the chief good everywhere abounds with the same opinions. Will you,
then, invite Telamon to this kind of life to ease his grief? And should
you observe any one of your friends under affliction, would you rather
prescribe him a sturgeon than a treatise of Socrates? or advise him to
listen to the music of a water organ rather than to Plato? or lay before
him the beauty and variety of some garden, put a nosegay to his nose,
burn perfumes before him, and bid him crown himself with a garland of
roses and woodbines? Should you add one thing more, you would certainly
wipe out all his grief.
110XIX. Epicurus must admit these arguments, or he must take out of his
book what I just now said was a literal translation; or, rather, he must
destroy his whole book, for it is crammed full of pleasures. We must
inquire, then, how we can ease him of his grief who speaks in this
manner:
My present state proceeds from fortune’s stings;
By birth I boast of a descent from kings;
Hence may you see from what a noble height
I’m sunk by fortune to this abject plight.
What! to ease his grief, must we mix him a cup of sweet wine, or
something of that kind? Lo! the same poet presents us with another
sentiment somewhere else:
I, Hector, once so great, now claim your aid.
We should assist her, for she looks out for help:
Where shall I now apply, where seek support?
Where hence betake me, or to whom resort?”
No means remain of comfort or of joy,
In flames my palace, and in ruins Troy;
Each wall, so late superb, deformed nods,
And not an altar’s left t’ appease the Gods.
You know what should follow, and particularly this:
Of father, country, and of friends bereft,
Not one of all these sumptuous temples left;
Which, while the fortune of our house did stand,
With rich wrought ceilings spoke the artist’s hand.
O excellent poet! though despised by those who sing the verses of
Euphorion. He is sensible that all things which come on a sudden are
harder to be borne. Therefore, when he had set off the riches of Priam
to the best advantage, which had the appearance of a long continuance,
what does he add?
Lo! these all perish’d in one blazing pile;
The foe old Priam of his life beguiled,
And with his blood, thy altar, Jove, defiled.
Admirable poetry! There is something mournful in the subject, as well as
in the words and measure. We must drive away this grief of hers: how is
that to be done? Shall we lay her on a bed of down; introduce a singer;
111shall we burn cedar, or present here with some pleasant liquor, and
provide her something to eat? Are these the good things which remove the
most afflicting grief? For you but just now said you knew of no other
good. I should agree with Epicurus that we ought to be called off from
grief to contemplate good things, if we could only agree upon what was
good.
XX. It may be said, What! do you imagine Epicurus really meant this, and
that he maintained anything so sensual? Indeed I do not imagine so, for
I am sensible that he has uttered many excellent things and sentiments,
and delivered maxims of great weight. Therefore, as I said before, I am
speaking of his acuteness, not of his morals. Though he should hold
those pleasures in contempt which he just now commended, yet I must
remember wherein he places the chief good. For he was not contented with
barely saying this, but he has explained what he meant: he says that
taste, and embraces, and sports, and music, and those forms which affect
the eyes with pleasure, are the chief good. Have I invented this? have I
misrepresented him? I should be glad to be confuted; for what am I
endeavoring at but to clear up truth in every question? Well, but the
same man says that pleasure is at its height where pain ceases, and that
to be free from all pain is the very greatest pleasure. Here are three
very great mistakes in a very few words. One is, that he contradicts
himself; for, but just now, he could not imagine anything good unless
the senses were in a manner tickled with some pleasure; but now he says
that to be free from pain is the highest pleasure. Can any one
contradict himself more? The next mistake is, that where there is
naturally a threefold division—the first, to be pleased; next, to be in
pain; the last, to be affected neither by pleasure nor pain—he imagines
the first and the last to be the same, and makes no difference between
pleasure and a cessation of pain. The last mistake he falls into in
common with some others, which is this: that as virtue is the most
desirable thing, and as philosophy has been investigated with a view to
the attainment of it, he has separated the chief good from virtue. But
he commends virtue, and that frequently; and indeed C. Gracchus, when he
had made the 112largest distributions of the public money, and had
exhausted the treasury, nevertheless spoke much of defending the
treasury. What signifies what men say when we see what they do? That
Piso, who was surnamed Frugal, had always harangued against the law that
was proposed for distributing the corn; but when it had passed, though a
man of consular dignity, he came to receive the corn. Gracchus observed
Piso standing in the court, and asked him, in the hearing of the people,
how it was consistent for him to take corn by a law he had himself
opposed. “It was,” said he, “against your distributing my goods to every
man as you thought proper; but, as you do so, I claim my share.” Did not
this grave and wise man sufficiently show that the public revenue was
dissipated by the Sempronian law? Read Gracchus’s speeches, and you will
pronounce him the advocate of the treasury. Epicurus denies that any one
can live pleasantly who does not lead a life of virtue; he denies that
fortune has any power over a wise man; he prefers a spare diet to great
plenty, and maintains that a wise man is always happy. All these things
become a philosopher to say, but they are not consistent with pleasure.
But the reply is, that he doth not mean that pleasure: let him mean
any pleasure, it must be such a one as makes no part of virtue. But
suppose we are mistaken as to his pleasure; are we so, too, as to his
pain? I maintain, therefore, the impropriety of language which that man
uses, when talking of virtue, who would measure every great evil by
pain.
XXI. And indeed the Epicureans, those best of men—for there is no order
of men more innocent—complain that I take great pains to inveigh
against Epicurus. We are rivals, I suppose, for some honor or
distinction. I place the chief good in the mind, he in the body; I in
virtue, he in pleasure; and the Epicureans are up in arms, and implore
the assistance of their neighbors, and many are ready to fly to their
aid. But as for my part, I declare that I am very indifferent about the
matter, and that I consider the whole discussion which they are so
anxious about at an end. For what! is the contention about the Punic
war? on which very subject, though M. Cato and L. Lentulus were of
different opinions, still there was no 113difference between them. But
these men behave with too much heat, especially as the opinions which
they would uphold are no very spirited ones, and such as they dare not
plead for either in the senate or before the assembly of the people, or
before the army or the censors. But, however, I will argue with them
another time, and with such a disposition that no quarrel shall arise
between us; for I shall be ready to yield to their opinions when founded
on truth. Only I must give them this advice: That were it ever so true,
that a wise man regards nothing but the body, or, to express myself with
more decency, never does anything except what is expedient, and views
all things with exclusive reference to his own advantage, as such things
are not very commendable, they should confine them to their own breasts,
and leave off talking with that parade of them.
XXII. What remains is the opinion of the Cyrenaics, who think that men
grieve when anything happens unexpectedly. And that is indeed, as I said
before, a great aggravation of a misfortune; and I know that it appeared
so to Chrysippus—“Whatever falls out unexpected is so much the
heavier.” But the whole question does not turn on this; though the
sudden approach of an enemy sometimes occasions more confusion than it
would if you had expected him, and a sudden storm at sea throws the
sailors into a greater fright than one which they have foreseen; and it
is the same in many other cases. But when you carefully consider the
nature of what was expected, you will find nothing more than that all
things which come on a sudden appear greater; and this upon two
accounts: first of all, because you have not time to consider how great
the accident is; and, secondly, because you are probably persuaded that
you could have guarded against it had you foreseen if, and therefore the
misfortune, having been seemingly encountered by your own fault, makes
your grief the greater. That it is so, time evinces; which, as it
advances, brings with it so much mitigation that though the same
misfortunes continue, the grief not only becomes the less, but in some
cases is entirely removed. Many Carthaginians were slaves at Rome, and
many Macedonians, when Perseus their king was taken prisoner. I saw,
114too, when I was a young man, some Corinthians in the Peloponnesus. They
might all have lamented with Andromache,
All these I saw......;
but they had perhaps given over lamenting themselves, for by their
countenances, and speech, and other gestures you might have taken them
for Argives or Sicyonians. And I myself was more concerned at the ruined
walls of Corinth than the Corinthians themselves were, whose minds by
frequent reflection and time had become callous to such sights. I have
read a book of Clitomachus, which he sent to his fellow-citizens who
were prisoners, to comfort them after the destruction of Carthage. There
is in it a treatise written by Carneades, which, as Clitomachus says, he
had inserted into his book; the subject was, “That it appeared probable
that a wise man would grieve at the state of subjection of his country,”
and all the arguments which Carneades used against this proposition are
set down in the book. There the philosopher applies such a strong
medicine to a fresh grief as would be quite unnecessary in one of any
continuance; nor, if this very book had been sent to the captives some
years after, would it have found any wounds to cure, but only scars; for
grief, by a gentle progress and slow degrees, wears away imperceptibly.
Not that the circumstances which gave rise to it are altered, or can be,
but that custom teaches what reason should—that those things which
before seemed to be of some consequence are of no such great importance,
after all.
XXIII. It may be said, What occasion is there to apply to reason, or to
any sort of consolation such as we generally make use of, to mitigate
the grief of the afflicted? For we have this argument always at hand,
that nothing ought to appear unexpected. But how will any one be enabled
to bear his misfortunes the better by knowing that it is unavoidable
that such things should happen to man? Saying this subtracts nothing
from the sum of the grief: it only asserts that nothing has fallen out
but what might have been anticipated; and yet this manner of speaking
has some little consolation in it, though I apprehend not a great deal.
Therefore those unlooked-for things have not so much force as to give
rise to all our 115grief; the blow perhaps may fall the heavier, but
whatever happens does not appear the greater on that account. No, it is
the fact of its having happened lately, and not of its having befallen
us unexpectedly, that makes it seem the greater. There are two ways,
then, of discerning the truth, not only of things that seem evil, but of
those that have the appearance of good. For we either inquire into the
nature of the thing, of what description, and magnitude, and importance
it is—as sometimes with regard to poverty, the burden of which we may
lighten when by our disputations we show how few things nature requires,
and of what a trifling kind they are—or, without any subtle arguing, we
refer them to examples, as here we instance a Socrates, there a
Diogenes, and then again that line in Cæcilius,
Wisdom is oft conceal’d in mean attire.
For as poverty is of equal weight with all, what reason can be given why
what was borne by Fabricius should be spoken of by any one else as
unsupportable when it falls upon themselves? Of a piece with this is
that other way of comforting, which consists in pointing out that
nothing has happened but what is common to human nature; for this
argument doth not only inform us what human nature is, but implies that
all things are tolerable which others have borne and are bearing.
XXIV. Is poverty the subject? They tell you of many who have submitted
to it with patience. Is it the contempt of honors? They acquaint you
with some who never enjoyed any, and were the happier for it; and of
those who have preferred a private retired life to public employment,
mentioning their names with respect; they tell you of the verse40 of
that most powerful king who praises an old man, and pronounces him happy
because he was unknown to fame and seemed likely to arrive at the hour
of death in obscurity and without notice. Thus, too, they have examples
for those who are deprived of their children: they who are under any
great grief are comforted by instances of like affliction; and thus the
endurance 116of every misfortune is rendered more easy by the fact of
others having undergone the same, and the fate of others causes what has
happened to appear less important than it has been previously thought,
and reflection thus discovers to us how much opinion had imposed on us.
And this is what the Telamon declares, “I, when my son was born,” etc.;
and thus Theseus, “I on my future misery did dwell;” and Anaxagoras, “I
knew my son was mortal.” All these men, by frequently reflecting on
human affairs, had discovered that they were by no means to be estimated
by the opinion of the multitude; and, indeed, it seems to me to be
pretty much the same case with those who consider beforehand as with
those who derive their remedies from time, excepting that a kind of
reason cures the one, and the other remedy is provided by nature; by
which we discover (and this contains the whole marrow of the matter)
that what was imagined to be the greatest evil is by no means so great
as to defeat the happiness of life. And the effect of this is, that the
blow is greater by reason of its not having been foreseen, and not, as
they suppose, that when similar misfortunes befall two different people,
that man only is affected with grief whom this calamity has befallen
unexpectedly. So that some persons, under the oppression of grief, are
said to have borne it actually worse for hearing of this common
condition of man, that we are born under such conditions as render it
impossible for a man to be exempt from all evil.
XXV. For this reason Carneades, as I see our friend Antiochus writes,
used to blame Chrysippus for commending these verses of Euripides:
Man, doom’d to care, to pain, disease, and strife,
Walks his short journey thro’ the vale of life:
Watchful attends the cradle and the grave,
And passing generations longs to save:
Last, dies himself: yet wherefore should we mourn?
For man must to his kindred dust return;
Submit to the destroying hand of fate,
As ripen’d ears the harvest-sickle wait.
41
117He would not allow a speech of this kind to avail at all to the cure of
our grief, for he said it was a lamentable case itself that we were
fallen into the hands of such a cruel fate; and that a speech like that,
preaching up comfort from the misfortunes of another, was a comfort
adapted only to those of a malevolent disposition. But to me it appears
far otherwise; for the necessity of bearing what is the common condition
of humanity forbids your resisting the will of the Gods, and reminds you
that you are a man, which reflection greatly alleviates grief; and the
enumeration of these examples is not produced with a view to please
those of a malevolent disposition, but in order that any one in
affliction may be induced to bear what he observes many others have
previously borne with tranquillity and moderation. For they who are
falling to pieces, and cannot hold together through the greatness of
their grief, should be supported by all kinds of assistance. From whence
Chrysippus thinks that grief is called О»бЅ»ПЂО·, as it were О»бЅ»ПѓО№П‚, that is
to say, a dissolution of the whole man—the whole of which I think may
be pulled up by the roots by explaining, as I said at the beginning, the
cause of grief; for it is nothing else but an opinion and judgment
formed of a present acute evil. And thus any bodily pain, let it be ever
so grievous, may be endurable where any hopes are proposed of some
considerable good; and we receive such consolation from a virtuous and
illustrious life that they who lead such lives are seldom attacked by
grief, or but slightly affected by it.
XXVI. But as besides this opinion of great evil there is this other
added also—that we ought to lament what has happened, that it is right
so to do, and part of our duty, then is brought about that terrible
disorder of mind, grief. And it is to this opinion that we owe all those
various and horrid kinds of lamentation, that neglect of our persons,
that womanish tearing of our cheeks, that striking on our thighs,
breasts, and heads. Thus Agamemnon, in Homer and in Accius,
Tears in his grief his uncomb’d locks;
42
from whence comes that pleasant saying of Bion, that the 118foolish king
in his sorrow tore away the hairs of his head, imagining that his grief
would be alleviated by baldness. But men do all these things from being
persuaded that they ought to do so. And thus Г†schines inveighs against
Demosthenes for sacrificing within seven days after the death of his
daughter. But with what eloquence, with what fluency, does he attack
him! what sentiments does he collect! what words does he hurl against
him! You may see by this that an orator may do anything; but nobody
would approve of such license if it were not that we have an idea innate
in our minds that every good man ought to lament the loss of a relation
as bitterly as possible. And it is owing to this that some men, when in
sorrow, betake themselves to deserts, as Homer says of Bellerophon:
Distracted in his mind,
Forsook by heaven, forsaking human kind,
Wide o’er the Aleïan field he chose to stray,
A long, forlorn, uncomfortable way!43
And thus Niobe is feigned to have been turned into stone, from her never
speaking, I suppose, in her grief. But they imagine Hecuba to have been
converted into a bitch, from her rage and bitterness of mind. There are
others who love to converse with solitude itself when in grief, as the
nurse in Ennius,
Fain would I to the heavens find earth relate
Medea’s ceaseless woes and cruel fate.
44
XXVII. Now all these things are done in grief, from a persuasion of
their truth and propriety and necessity; and it is plain that those who
behave thus do so from a conviction of its being their duty; for should
these mourners by chance drop their grief, and either act or speak for a
moment in a more calm or cheerful manner, they presently check
themselves and return to their lamentations again, and blame themselves
for having been guilty of any intermissions
119from their grief; and
parents and masters generally correct children not by words only, but by
blows, if they show any levity by either word or deed when the family is
under affliction, and, as it were, oblige them to be sorrowful. What!
does it not appear, when you have ceased to mourn, and have discovered
that your grief has been ineffectual, that the whole of that mourning
was voluntary on your part? What does that man say in Terence who
punishes himself, the Self-tormentor?
I think I do my son less harm, O Chremes,
As long as I myself am miserable.
He determines to be miserable: and can any one determine on anything
against his will?
I well might think that I deserved all evil.
He would think he deserved any misfortune were he otherwise than
miserable! Therefore, you see, the evil is in opinion, not in nature.
How is it when some things do of themselves prevent your grieving at
them? as in Homer, so many died and were buried daily that they had not
leisure to grieve: where you find these lines—
The great, the bold, by thousands daily fall,
And endless were the grief to weep for all.
Eternal sorrows what avails to shed?
Greece honors not with solemn fasts the dead:
Enough when death demands the brave to pay
The tribute of a melancholy day.
One chief with patience to the grave resign’d,
Our care devolves on others left behind.
45
Therefore it is in our own power to lay aside grief upon occasion; and
is there any opportunity (seeing the thing is in our own power) that we
should let slip of getting rid of care and grief? It was plain that the
friends of Cnæus Pompeius, when they saw him fainting under his wounds,
at the very moment of that most miserable and bitter sight were under
great uneasiness how they themselves,
120surrounded by the enemy as they
were, should escape, and were employed in nothing but encouraging the
rowers and aiding their escape; but when they reached Tyre, they began
to grieve and lament over him. Therefore, as fear with them, prevailed
over grief, cannot reason and true philosophy have the same effect with
a wise man?
XXVIII. But what is there more effectual to dispel grief than the
discovery that it answers no purpose, and has been undergone to no
account? Therefore, if we can get rid of it, we need never have been
subject to it. It must be acknowledged, then, that men take up grief
wilfully and knowingly; and this appears from the patience of those who,
after they have been exercised in afflictions and are better able to
bear whatever befalls them, suppose themselves hardened against fortune;
as that person in Euripides,
Had this the first essay of fortune been,
And I no storms thro’ all my life had seen,
Wild as a colt I’d broke from reason’s sway;
But frequent griefs have taught me to obey.
46
As, then, the frequent bearing of misery makes grief the lighter, we
must necessarily perceive that the cause and original of it does not lie
in the calamity itself. Your principal philosophers, or lovers of
wisdom, though they have not yet arrived at perfect wisdom, are not they
sensible that they are in the greatest evil? For they are foolish, and
foolishness is the greatest of all evils, and yet they lament not. How
shall we account for this? Because opinion is not fixed upon that kind
of evil, it is not our opinion that it is right, meet, and our duty to
be uneasy because we are not all wise men. Whereas this opinion is
strongly affixed to that uneasiness where mourning is concerned, which
is the greatest of all grief. Therefore Aristotle, when he blames some
ancient philosophers for imagining that by their genius they had brought
philosophy 121to the highest perfection, says, they must be either
extremely foolish or extremely vain; but that he himself could see that
great improvements had been made therein in a few years, and that
philosophy would in a little time arrive at perfection. And Theophrastus
is reported to have reproached nature at his death for giving to stags
and crows so long a life, which was of no use to them, but allowing only
so short a span to men, to whom length of days would have been of the
greatest use; for if the life of man could have been lengthened, it
would have been able to provide itself with all kinds of learning, and
with arts in the greatest perfection. He lamented, therefore, that he
was dying just when he had begun to discover these. What! does not every
grave and distinguished philosopher acknowledge himself ignorant of many
things, and confess that there are many things which he must learn over
and over again? And yet, though these men are sensible that they are
standing still in the very midway of folly, than which nothing can be
worse, they are under no great affliction, because no opinion that it is
their duty to lament is ever mingled with this knowledge. What shall we
say of those who think it unbecoming in a man to grieve? among whom we
may reckon Q. Maximus, when he buried his son that had been consul, and
L. Paulus, who lost two sons within a few days of one another. Of the
same opinion was M. Cato, who lost his son just after he had been
elected prætor, and many others, whose names I have collected in my book
on Consolation. Now what made these men so easy, but their persuasion
that grief and lamentation was not becoming in a man? Therefore, as some
give themselves up to grief from an opinion that it is right so to do,
they refrained themselves, from an opinion that it was discreditable;
from which we may infer that grief is owing more to opinion than nature.
XXIX. It may be said, on the other side, Who is so mad as to grieve of
his own accord? Pain proceeds from nature, which you must submit to, say
they, agreeably to what even your own Crantor teaches, for it presses
and gains upon you unavoidably, and cannot possibly be resisted. So that
the very same Oileus, in Sophocles, who had before comforted Telamon on
the death of Ajax, on 122hearing of the death of his own son, is
broken-hearted. On this alteration of his mind we have these lines:
Show me the man so well by wisdom taught
That what he charges to another’s fault,
When like affliction doth himself betide,
True to his own wise counsel will abide.
47
Now, when they urge these things, their endeavor is to prove that nature
is absolutely and wholly irresistible; and yet the same people allow
that we take greater grief on ourselves than nature requires. What
madness is it, then, in us to require the same from others? But there
are many reasons for our taking grief on us. The first is from the
opinion of some evil, on the discovery and certainty of which grief
comes of course. Besides, many people are persuaded that they are doing
something very acceptable to the dead when they lament bitterly over
them. To these may be added a kind of womanish superstition, in
imagining that when they have been stricken by the afflictions sent by
the Gods, to acknowledge themselves afflicted and humbled by them is the
readiest way of appeasing them. But most men appear to be unaware what
contradictions these things are full of. They commend those who die
calmly, but they blame those who can bear the loss of another with the
same calmness, as if it were possible that it should be true, as is
occasionally said in love speeches, that any one can love another more
than himself. There is, indeed, something excellent in this, and, if you
examine it, something no less just than true, that we love those who
ought to be most dear to us as well as we love ourselves; but to love
them more than ourselves is absolutely impossible; nor is it desirable
in friendship that I should love my friend more than myself, or that he
should love me so; for this would occasion much confusion in life, and
break in upon all the duties of it.
123XXX. But we will speak of this another time: at present it is
sufficient not to attribute our misery to the loss of our friends, nor
to love them more than, if they themselves could be sensible of our
conduct, they would approve of, or at least not more than we do
ourselves. Now as to what they say, that some are not at all appeased by
our consolations; and, moreover, as to what they add, that the
comforters themselves acknowledge they are miserable when fortune varies
the attack and falls on them—in both these cases the solution is easy:
for the fault here is not in nature, but in our own folly; and much may
be said against folly. But men who do not admit of consolation seem to
bespeak misery for themselves; and they who cannot bear their
misfortunes with that temper which they recommend to others are not more
faulty in this particular than most other persons; for we see that
covetous men find fault with others who are covetous, as do the
vainglorious with those who appear too wholly devoted to the pursuit of
glory. For it is the peculiar characteristic of folly to perceive the
vices of others, but to forget its own. But since we find that grief is
removed by length of time, we have the greatest proof that the strength
of it depends not merely on time, but on the daily consideration of it.
For if the cause continues the same, and the man be the same, how can
there be any alteration in the grief, if there is no change in what
occasioned the grief, nor in him who grieves? Therefore it is from daily
reflecting that there is no real evil in the circumstance for which you
grieve, and not from the length of time, that you procure a remedy for
your grief.
XXXI. Here some people talk of moderate grief; but if such be natural,
what occasion is there for consolation? for nature herself will
determine, the measure of it: but if it depends on and is caused by
opinion, the whole opinion should be destroyed. I think that it has been
sufficiently said, that grief arises from an opinion of some present
evil, which includes this belief, that it is incumbent on us to grieve.
To this definition Zeno has added, very justly, that the opinion of this
present evil should be recent. Now this word recent they explain thus:
those are not the only recent things which happened a little while ago;
but as 124long as there shall be any force, or vigor, or freshness in that
imagined evil, so long it is entitled to the name of recent. Take the
case of Artemisia, the wife of Mausolus, King of Caria, who made that
noble sepulchre at Halicarnassus; while she lived, she lived in grief,
and died of it, being worn out by it, for that opinion was always recent
with her: but you cannot call that recent which has already begun to
decay through time. Now the duty of a comforter is, to remove grief
entirely, to quiet it, or draw it off as much as you can, or else to
keep it under, and prevent its spreading any further, and to divert
one’s attention to other matters. There are some who think, with
Cleanthes, that the only duty of a comforter is to prove that what one
is lamenting is by no means an evil. Others, as the Peripatetics, prefer
urging that the evil is not great. Others, with Epicurus, seek to divert
your attention from the evil to good: some think it sufficient to show
that nothing has happened but what you had reason to expect; and this is
the practice of the Cyrenaics. But Chrysippus thinks that the main thing
in comforting is, to remove the opinion from the person who is grieving,
that to grieve is his bounden duty. There are others who bring together
all these various kinds of consolations, for people are differently
affected; as I have done myself in my book on Consolation; for as my own
mind was much disordered, I have attempted in that book to discover
every method of cure. But the proper season is as much to be attended to
in the cure of the mind as of the body; as Prometheus in Г†schylus, on
its being said to him,
I think, Prometheus, you this tenet hold,
That all men’s reason should their rage control?
answers,
Yes, when one reason properly applies;
Ill-timed advice will make the storm but rise.
48
XXXII. But the principal medicine to be applied in consolation is, to
maintain either that it is no evil at all,
125or a very inconsiderable
one: the next best to that is, to speak of the common condition of life,
having a view, if possible, to the state of the person whom you comfort
particularly. The third is, that it is folly to wear one’s self out with
grief which can avail nothing. For the comfort of Cleanthes is suitable
only for a wise man, who is in no need of any comfort at all; for could
you persuade one in grief that nothing is an evil but what is base, you
would not only cure him of grief, but folly. But the time for such
precepts is not well chosen. Besides, Cleanthes does not seem to me
sufficiently aware that affliction may very often proceed from that very
thing which he himself allows to be the greatest misfortune. For what
shall we say? When Socrates had convinced Alcibiades, as we are told,
that he had no distinctive qualifications as a man different from other
people, and that, in fact, there was no difference between him, though a
man of the highest rank, and a porter; and when Alcibiades became uneasy
at this, and entreated Socrates, with tears in his eyes, to make him a
man of virtue, and to cure him of that mean position; what shall we say
to this, Cleanthes? Was there no evil in what afflicted Alcibiades thus?
What strange things does Lycon say? who, making light of grief, says
that it arises from trifles, from things that affect our fortune or
bodies, not from the evils of the mind. What, then? did not the grief of
Alcibiades proceed from the defects and evils of the mind? I have
already said enough of Epicurus’s consolation.
XXXIII. Nor is that consolation much to be relied on, though it is
frequently practised, and sometimes has some effect, namely, “That you
are not alone in this.” It has its effect, as I said, but not always,
nor with every person, for some reject it; but much depends on the
application of it; for you ought rather to show, not how men in general
have been affected with such evils, but how men of sense have borne
them. As to Chrysippus’s method, it is certainly founded in truth; but
it is difficult to apply it in time of distress. It is a work of no
small difficulty to persuade a person in affliction that he grieves
merely because he thinks it right so to do. Certainly, then, as in
pleadings we do not state all cases alike (if I may adopt
126the language
of lawyers for a moment), but adapt what we have to say to the time, to
the nature of the subject under debate, and to the person; so, too, in
alleviating grief, regard should be had to what kind of cure the party
to be comforted can admit of. But, somehow or other, we have rambled
from what you originally proposed. For your question was concerning a
wise man, with whom nothing can have the appearance of evil that is not
dishonorable; or at least, anything else would seem so small an evil
that by his wisdom he would so overmatch it as to make it wholly
disappear; and such a man makes no addition to his grief through
opinion, and never conceives it right to torment himself above measure,
nor to wear himself out with grief, which is the meanest thing
imaginable. Reason, however, it seems, has demonstrated (though it was
not directly our object at the moment to inquire whether anything can be
called an evil except what is base) that it is in our power to discern
that all the evil which there is in affliction has nothing natural in
it, but is contracted by our own voluntary judgment of it, and the error
of opinion.
XXXIV. But the kind of affliction of which I have treated is that which
is the greatest; in order that when we have once got rid of that, it may
appear a business of less consequence to look after remedies for the
others. For there are certain things which are usually said about
poverty; and also certain statements ordinarily applied to retired and
undistinguished life. There are particular treatises on banishment, on
the ruin of one’s country, on slavery, on weakness, on blindness, and on
every incident that can come under the name of an evil. The Greeks
divide these into different treatises and distinct books; but they do it
for the sake of employment: not but that all such discussions are full
of entertainment. And yet, as physicians, in curing the whole body,
attend to even the most insignificant part of the body which is at all
disordered, so does philosophy act, after it has removed grief in
general; still, if any other deficiency exists—should poverty bite,
should ignominy sting, should banishment bring a dark cloud over us, or
should any of those things which I have just mentioned appear, there is
for each its appropriate
127consolation, which you shall hear whenever you
please. But we must have recourse again to the same original principle,
that a wise man is free from all sorrow, because it is vain, because it
answers no purpose, because it is not founded in nature, but on opinion
and prejudice, and is engendered by a kind of invitation to grieve, when
once men have imagined that it is their duty to do so. When, then, we
have subtracted what is altogether voluntary, that mournful uneasiness
will be removed; yet some little anxiety, some slight pricking, will
still remain. They may indeed call this natural, provided they give it
not that horrid, solemn, melancholy name of grief, which can by no means
consist with wisdom. But how various and how bitter are the roots of
grief! Whatever they are, I propose, after having felled the trunk, to
destroy them all; even if it should be necessary, by allotting a
separate dissertation to each, for I have leisure enough to do so,
whatever time it may take up. But the principle of every uneasiness is
the same, though they may appear under different names. For envy is an
uneasiness; so are emulation, detraction, anguish, sorrow, sadness,
tribulation, lamentation, vexation, grief, trouble, affliction, and
despair. The Stoics define all these different feelings; and all those
words which I have mentioned belong to different things, and do not, as
they seem, express the same ideas; but they are to a certain extent
distinct, as I shall make appear perhaps in another place. These are
those fibres of the roots which, as I said at first, must be traced back
and cut off and destroyed, so that not one shall remain. You say it is a
great and difficult undertaking: who denies it? But what is there of any
excellency which has not its difficulty? Yet philosophy undertakes to
effect it, provided we admit its superintendence. But enough of this.
The other books, whenever you please, shall be ready for you here or
anywhere else.
128BOOK IV.
On other perturbations of the mind.
I.
I have often wondered, Brutus, on many occasions, at the ingenuity
and virtues of our countrymen; but nothing has surprised me more than
their development in those studies, which, though they came somewhat
late to us, have been transported into this city from Greece. For the
system of auspices, and religious ceremonies, and courts of justice, and
appeals to the people, the senate, the establishment of an army of
cavalry and infantry, and the whole military discipline, were instituted
as early as the foundation of the city by royal authority, partly too by
laws, not without the assistance of the Gods. Then with what a
surprising and incredible progress did our ancestors advance towards all
kind of excellence, when once the republic was freed from the regal
power! Not that this is a proper occasion to treat of the manners and
customs of our ancestors, or of the discipline and constitution of the
city; for I have elsewhere, particularly in the six books I wrote on the
Republic, given a sufficiently accurate account of them. But while I am
on this subject, and considering the study of philosophy, I meet with
many reasons to imagine that those studies were brought to us from
abroad, and not merely imported, but preserved and improved; for they
had Pythagoras, a man of consummate wisdom and nobleness of character,
in a manner, before their eyes, who was in Italy at the time that Lucius
Brutus, the illustrious founder of your nobility, delivered his country
from tyranny. As the doctrine of Pythagoras spread itself on all sides,
it seems probable to me that it reached this city; and this is not only
probable of itself, but it does really appear to have been the case from
many remains of it. For who can imagine that, when it flourished so much
in that part of Italy which was called Magna Græcia, and in some of the
129largest and most powerful cities, in which, first the name of
Pythagoras, and then that of those men who were afterward his followers,
was in so high esteem; who can imagine, I say, that our people could
shut their ears to what was said by such learned men? Besides, it is
even my opinion that it was the great esteem in which the Pythagoreans
were held, that gave rise to that opinion among those who came after
him, that King Numa was a Pythagorean. For, being acquainted with the
doctrine and principles of Pythagoras, and having heard from their
ancestors that this king was a very wise and just man, and not being
able to distinguish accurately between times and periods that were so
remote, they inferred, from his being so eminent for his wisdom, that he
had been a pupil of Pythagoras.
II. So far we proceed on conjecture. As to the vestiges of the
Pythagoreans, though I might collect many, I shall use but a few;
because they have no connection with our present purpose. For, as it is
reported to have been a custom with them to deliver certain precepts in
a more abstruse manner in verse, and to bring their minds from severe
thought to a more composed state by songs and musical instruments; so
Cato, a writer of the very highest authority, says in his Origins, that
it was customary with our ancestors for the guests at their
entertainments, every one in his turn, to celebrate the praises and
virtues of illustrious men in song to the sound of the flute; from
whence it is clear that poems and songs were then composed for the
voice. And, indeed, it is also clear that poetry was in fashion from the
laws of the Twelve Tables, wherein it is provided that no song should be
made to the injury of another. Another argument of the erudition of
those times is, that they played on instruments before the shrines of
their Gods, and at the entertainments of their magistrates; but that
custom was peculiar to the sect I am speaking of. To me, indeed, that
poem of Appius Cæcus, which Panætius commends so much in a certain
letter of his which is addressed to Quintus Tubero, has all the marks of
a Pythagorean author. We have many things derived from the Pythagoreans
in our customs, which I pass over, that we may
130not seem to have learned
that elsewhere which we look upon ourselves as the inventors of. But to
return to our purpose. How many great poets as well as orators have
sprung up among us! and in what a short time! so that it is evident that
our people could arrive at any learning as soon as they had an
inclination for it. But of other studies I shall speak elsewhere if
there is occasion, as I have already often done.
III. The study of philosophy is certainly of long standing with us; but
yet I do not find that I can give you the names of any philosopher
before the age of Lælius and Scipio, in whose younger days we find that
Diogenes the Stoic, and Carneades the Academic, were sent as ambassadors
by the Athenians to our senate. And as these had never been concerned in
public affairs, and one of them was a Cyrenean, the other a Babylonian,
they certainly would never have been forced from their studies, nor
chosen for that employment, unless the study of philosophy had been in
vogue with some of the great men at that time; who, though they might
employ their pens on other subjects—some on civil law, others on
oratory, others on the history of former times—yet promoted this most
extensive of all arts, the principle of living well, even more by their
life than by their writings. So that of that true and elegant philosophy
(which was derived from Socrates, and is still preserved by the
Peripatetics and by the Stoics, though they express themselves
differently in their disputes with the Academics) there are few or no
Latin records; whether this proceeds from the importance of the thing
itself, or from men’s being otherwise employed, or from their concluding
that the capacity of the people was not equal to the apprehension of
them. But, during this silence, C. Amafinius arose and took upon himself
to speak; on the publishing of whose writings the people were moved, and
enlisted themselves chiefly under this sect, either because the doctrine
was more easily understood, or because they were invited thereto by the
pleasing thoughts of amusement, or that, because there was nothing
better, they laid hold of what was offered them. And after Amafinius,
when many of the same sentiments had written much about them, the
Pythagoreans
131spread over all Italy: but that these doctrines should be
so easily understood and approved of by the unlearned is a great proof
that they were not written with any great subtlety, and they think their
establishment to be owing to this.
IV. But let every one defend his own opinion, for every one is at
liberty to choose what he likes: I shall keep to my old custom; and,
being under no restraint from the laws of any particular school, which
in philosophy every one must necessarily confine himself to, I shall
always inquire what has the most probability in every question, and this
system, which I have often practised on other occasions, I have adhered
closely to in my Tusculan Disputations. Therefore, as I have acquainted
you with the disputations of the three former days, this book shall
conclude the discussion of the fourth day. When we had come down into
the Academy, as we had done the former days, the business was carried on
thus:
M. Let any one say, who pleases, what he would wish to have discussed.
A. I do not think a wise man can possibly be free from every
perturbation of mind.
M. He seemed by yesterday’s discourse to be free from grief; unless
you agreed with us only to avoid taking up time.
A. Not at all on that account, for I was extremely satisfied with your
discourse.
M. You do not think, then, that a wise man is subject to grief?
A. No, by no means.
M. But if that cannot disorder the mind of a wise man, nothing else
can. For what—can such a man be disturbed by fear? Fear proceeds from
the same things when absent which occasion grief when present. Take away
grief, then, and you remove fear.
The two remaining perturbations are, a joy elate above measure, and
lust; and if a wise man is not subject to these, his mind will be always
at rest.
A. I am entirely of that opinion.
M. Which, then, shall we do? Shall I immediately crowd all my sails?
or shall I make use of my oars, as if I were just endeavoring to get
clear of the harbor?
132A. What is it that you mean, for I do not exactly comprehend you?
V.
M. Because, Chrysippus and the Stoics, when they discuss the
perturbations of the mind, make great part of their debate to consist in
definitions and distinctions; while they employ but few words on the
subject of curing the mind, and preventing it from being disordered.
Whereas the Peripatetics bring a great many things to promote the cure
of it, but have no regard to their thorny partitions and definitions. My
question, then, was, whether I should instantly unfold the sails of my
eloquence, or be content for a while to make less way with the oars of
logic?
A. Let it be so; for by the employment of both these means the subject
of our inquiry will be more thoroughly discussed.
M. It is certainly the better way; and should anything be too obscure,
you may examine that afterward.
A. I will do so; but those very obscure points you will, as usual,
deliver with more clearness than the Greeks.
M. I will, indeed, endeavor to do so; but it well requires great
attention, lest, by losing one word, the whole should escape you. What
the Greeks call
ПЂбЅ±ОёО· we choose to name perturbations (or disorders)
rather than diseases; in explaining which, I shall follow, first, that
very old description of Pythagoras, and afterward that of Plato; for
they both divide the mind into two parts, and make one of these partake
of reason, and the other they represent without it. In that which
partakes of reason they place tranquillity, that is to say, a placid and
undisturbed constancy; to the other they assign the turbid motions of
anger and desire, which are contrary and opposite to reason. Let this,
then, be our principle, the spring of all our reasonings. But
notwithstanding, I shall use the partitions and definitions of the
Stoics in describing these perturbations; who seem to me to have shown
very great acuteness on this question.
VI. Zeno’s definition, then, is this: “A perturbation” (which he calls a
πάθος) “is a commotion of the mind repugnant to reason, and against
nature.” Some of them define it even more briefly, saying that a
perturbation is a somewhat too vehement appetite; but by too vehement
they mean an appetite
133that recedes further from the constancy of
nature. But they would have the divisions of perturbations to arise from
two imagined goods, and from two imagined evils; and thus they become
four: from the good proceed lust and joy—joy having reference to some
present good, and lust to some future one. They suppose fear and grief
to proceed from evils: fear from something future, grief from something
present; for whatever things are dreaded as approaching always occasion
grief when present. But joy and lust depend on the opinion of good; as
lust, being inflamed and provoked, is carried on eagerly towards what
has the appearance of good; and joy is transported and exults on
obtaining what was desired: for we naturally pursue those things that
have the appearance of good, and avoid the contrary. Wherefore, as soon
as anything that has the appearance of good presents itself, nature
incites us to endeavor to obtain it. Now, where this strong desire is
consistent and founded on prudence, it is by the Stoics called
ОІОїбЅ»О»О·ПѓО№П‚,
and the name which we give it is volition; and this they allow to none
but their wise man, and define it thus: Volition is a reasonable desire;
but whatever is incited too violently in opposition to reason, that is a
lust, or an unbridled desire, which is discoverable in all fools. And,
therefore, when we are affected so as to be placed in any good
condition, we are moved in two ways; for when the mind is moved in a
placid and calm motion, consistent with reason, that is called joy; but
when it exults with a vain, wanton exultation, or immoderate joy, then
that feeling may be called immoderate ecstasy or transport, which they
define to be an elation of the mind without reason. And as we naturally
desire good things, so in like manner we naturally seek to avoid what is
evil; and this avoidance of which, if conducted in accordance with
reason, is called caution; and this the wise man alone is supposed to
have: but that caution which is not under the guidance of reason, but is
attended with a base and low dejection, is called fear. Fear is,
therefore, caution destitute of reason. But a wise man is not affected
by any present evil; while the grief of a fool proceeds from being
affected with an imaginary evil, by which his mind is contracted and
sunk, since it is not under the dominion
134of reason. This, then, is the
first definition, which makes grief to consist in a shrinking of the
mind contrary to the dictates of reason. Thus, there are four
perturbations, and but three calm rational emotions; for grief has no
exact opposite.
VII. But they insist upon it that all perturbations depend on opinion
and judgment; therefore they define them more strictly, in order not
only the better to show how blamable they are, but to discover how much
they are in our power. Grief, then, is a recent opinion of some present
evil, in which it seems to be right that the mind should shrink and be
dejected. Joy is a recent opinion of a present good, in which it seems
to be right that the mind should be elated. Fear is an opinion of an
impending evil which we apprehend will be intolerable. Lust is an
opinion of a good to come, which would be of advantage were it already
come, and present with us. But however I have named the judgments and
opinions of perturbations, their meaning is, not that merely the
perturbations consist in them, but that the effects likewise of these
perturbations do so; as grief occasions a kind of painful pricking, and
fear engenders a recoil or sudden abandonment of the mind, joy gives
rise to a profuse mirth, while lust is the parent of an unbridled habit
of coveting. But that imagination, which I have included in all the
above definitions, they would have to consist in assenting without
warrantable grounds. Now, every perturbation has many subordinate parts
annexed to it of the same kind. Grief is attended with enviousness
(
invidentia)—I use that word for instruction’s sake, though it is not
so common; because envy (
invidia) takes in not only the person who
envies, but the person, too, who is envied—emulation, detraction, pity,
vexation, mourning, sadness, tribulation, sorrow, lamentation,
solicitude, disquiet of mind, pain, despair, and many other similar
feelings are so too. Under fear are comprehended sloth, shame, terror,
cowardice, fainting, confusion, astonishment. In pleasure they
comprehend malevolence—that is, pleased at another’s
misfortune—delight, boastfulness, and the like. To lust they associate
anger, fury, hatred, enmity, discord, wants, desire, and other feelings
of that kind.
135But they define these in this manner:
VIII. Enviousness (
invidentia), they say, is a grief arising from the
prosperous circumstances of another, which are in no degree injurious to
the person who envies; for where any one grieves at the prosperity of
another, by which he is injured, such a one is not properly said to
envy—as when Agamemnon grieves at Hector’s success; but where any one,
who is in no way hurt by the prosperity of another, is in pain at his
success, such a one envies indeed. Now the name “emulation” is taken in
a double sense, so that the same word may stand for praise and
dispraise: for the imitation of virtue is called emulation (however,
that sense of it I shall have no occasion for here, for that carries
praise with it); but emulation is also a term applied to grief at
another’s enjoying what I desired to have, and am without. Detraction
(and I mean by that, jealousy) is a grief even at another’s enjoying
what I had a great inclination for. Pity is a grief at the misery of
another who suffers wrongfully; for no one is moved by pity at the
punishment of a parricide or of a betrayer of his country. Vexation is a
pressing grief. Mourning is a grief at the bitter death of one who was
dear to you. Sadness is a grief attended with tears. Tribulation is a
painful grief. Sorrow, an excruciating grief. Lamentation, a grief where
we loudly bewail ourselves. Solicitude, a pensive grief. Trouble, a
continued grief. Affliction, a grief that harasses the body. Despair, a
grief that excludes all hope of better things to come. But those
feelings which are included under fear, they define thus: There is
sloth, which is a dread of some ensuing labor; shame and terror, which
affect the body—hence blushing attends shame; a paleness, and tremor,
and chattering of the teeth attend terror—cowardice, which is an
apprehension of some approaching evil; dread, a fear that unhinges the
mind, whence comes that line of Ennius,
Then dread discharged all wisdom from my mind;
fainting is the associate and constant attendant on dread; confusion, a
fear that drives away all thought; alarm, a continued fear.
136IX. The different species into which they divide pleasure come under
this description; so that malevolence is a pleasure in the misfortunes
of another, without any advantage to yourself; delight, a pleasure that
soothes the mind by agreeable impressions on the ear. What is said of
the ear may be applied to the sight, to the touch, smell, and taste. All
feelings of this kind are a sort of melting pleasure that dissolves the
mind. Boastfulness is a pleasure that consists in making an appearance,
and setting off yourself with insolence.—The subordinate species of
lust they define in this manner: Anger is a lust of punishing any one
who, as we imagine, has injured us without cause. Heat is anger just
forming and beginning to exist, which the Greeks call ОёбЅ»ОјП‰ПѓО№П‚. Hatred is
a settled anger. Enmity is anger waiting for an opportunity of revenge.
Discord is a sharper anger conceived deeply in the mind and heart. Want
an insatiable lust. Regret is when one eagerly wishes to see a person
who is absent. Now here they have a distinction; so that with them
regret is a lust conceived on hearing of certain things reported of some
one, or of many, which the Greeks call ОєО±П„О·ОіОїПЃбЅµОјО±П„О±, or predicaments; as
that they are in possession of riches and honors: but want is a lust for
those very honors and riches. But these definers make intemperance the
fountain of all these perturbations; which is an absolute revolt from
the mind and right reason—a state so averse to all rules of reason that
the appetites of the mind can by no means be governed and restrained.
As, therefore, temperance appeases these desires, making them obey right
reason, and maintains the well-weighed judgments of the mind, so
intemperance, which is in opposition to this, inflames, confounds, and
puts every state of the mind into a violent motion. Thus, grief and
fear, and every other perturbation of the mind, have their rise from
intemperance.
X. Just as distempers and sickness are bred in the body from the
corruption of the blood, and the too great abundance of phlegm and bile,
so the mind is deprived of its health, and disordered with sickness,
from a confusion of depraved opinions that are in opposition to one
another. From these perturbations arise, first, diseases, which they
call ОЅОїПѓбЅµОјО±П„О±; and also those feelings which are in opposition 137to these
diseases, and which admit certain faulty distastes or loathings; then
come sicknesses, which are called ἀῤῥωστήματα by the Stoics, and these
two have their opposite aversions. Here the Stoics, especially
Chrysippus, give themselves unnecessary trouble to show the analogy
which the diseases of the mind have to those of the body: but,
overlooking all that they say as of little consequence, I shall treat
only of the thing itself. Let us, then, understand perturbation to imply
a restlessness from the variety and confusion of contradictory opinions;
and that when this heat and disturbance of the mind is of any standing,
and has taken up its residence, as it were, in the veins and marrow,
then commence diseases and sickness, and those aversions which are in
opposition to these diseases and sicknesses.
XI. What I say here may be distinguished in thought, though they are in
fact the same; inasmuch as they both have their rise from lust and joy.
For should money be the object of our desire, and should we not
instantly apply to reason, as if it were a kind of Socratic medicine to
heal this desire, the evil glides into our veins, and cleaves to our
bowels, and from thence proceeds a distemper or sickness, which, when it
is of any continuance, is incurable, and the name of this disease is
covetousness. It is the same with other diseases; as the desire of
glory, a passion for women, to which the Greeks give the name of
П†О№О»ОїОіП…ОЅОµбЅ·О±: and thus all other diseases and sicknesses are generated.
But those feelings which are the contrary of these are supposed to have
fear for their foundation, as a hatred of women, such as is displayed in
the Woman-hater of Atilius; or the hatred of the whole human species, as
Timon is reported to have done, whom they call the Misanthrope. Of the
same kind is inhospitality. And all these diseases proceed from a
certain dread of such things as they hate and avoid. But they define
sickness of mind to be an overweening opinion, and that fixed and deeply
implanted in the heart, of something as very desirable which is by no
means so. What proceeds from aversion, they define thus: a vehement idea
of something to be avoided, deeply implanted, and inherent in our minds,
when there is no reason for avoiding it; and this kind of opinion is a
deliberate 138belief that one understands things of which one is wholly
ignorant. Now, sickness of the mind has all these subordinate divisions:
avarice, ambition, fondness for women, obstinacy, gluttony, drunkenness,
covetousness, and other similar vices. But avarice is a violent opinion
about money, as if it were vehemently to be desired and sought after,
which opinion is deeply implanted and inherent in our minds; and the
definition of all the other similar feelings resembles these. But the
definitions of aversions are of this sort: inhospitality is a vehement
opinion, deeply implanted and inherent in your mind, that you should
avoid a stranger. Thus, too, the hatred of women, like that felt by
Hippolytus, is defined; and the hatred of the human species like that
displayed by Timon.
XII. But to come to the analogy of the state of body and mind, which I
shall sometimes make use of, though more sparingly than the Stoics. Some
men are more inclined to particular disorders than others; and,
therefore, we say that some people are rheumatic, others dropsical, not
because they are so at present, but because they are often so: some are
inclined to fear, others to some other perturbation. Thus in some there
is a continual anxiety, owing to which they are anxious; in some a
hastiness of temper, which differs from anger, as anxiety differs from
anguish: for all are not anxious who are sometimes vexed, nor are they
who are anxious always uneasy in that manner: as there is a difference
between being drunk and drunkenness; and it is one thing to be a lover,
another to be given to women. And this disposition of particular people
to particular disorders is very common: for it relates to all
perturbations; it appears in many vices, though it has no name. Some
are, therefore, said to be envious, malevolent, spiteful, fearful,
pitiful, from a propensity to those perturbations, not from their being
always carried away by them. Now this propensity to these particular
disorders may be called a sickness from analogy with the body; meaning,
that is to say, nothing more than a propensity towards sickness. But
with regard to whatever is good, as some are more inclined to different
good qualities than others, we may call this a facility or tendency:
this tendency to evil is a proclivity or inclination to falling; 139but
where anything is neither good nor bad, it may have the former name.
XIII. Even as there may be, with respect to the body, a disease, a
sickness, and a defect, so it is with the mind. They call that a disease
where the whole body is corrupted; they call that sickness where a
disease is attended with a weakness, and that a defect where the parts
of the body are not well compacted together; from whence it follows that
the members are misshapen, crooked, and deformed. So that these two, a
disease and sickness, proceed from a violent concussion and perturbation
of the health of the whole body; but a defect discovers itself even when
the body is in perfect health. But a disease of the mind is
distinguishable only in thought from a sickness. But a viciousness is a
habit or affection discordant and inconsistent with itself through life.
Thus it happens that, in the one case, a disease and sickness may arise
from a corruption of opinions; in the other case, the consequence may be
inconstancy and inconsistency. For every vice of the mind does not imply
a disunion of parts; as is the case with those who are not far from
being wise men. With them there is that affection which is inconsistent
with itself while it is foolish; but it is not distorted, nor depraved.
But diseases and sicknesses are parts of viciousness; but it is a
question whether perturbations are parts of the same, for vices are
permanent affections: perturbations are such as are restless; so that
they cannot be parts of permanent ones. As there is some analogy between
the nature of the body and mind in evil, so is there in good; for the
distinctions of the body are beauty, strength, health, firmness,
quickness of motion: the same may be said of the mind. The body is said
to be in a good state when all those things on which health depends are
consistent: the same may be said of the mind when its judgments and
opinions are not at variance with one another. And this union is the
virtue of the mind, which, according to some people, is temperance
itself; others make it consist in an obedience to the precepts of
temperance, and a compliance with them, not allowing it to be any
distinct species of itself. But, be it one or the other, it is to be
found only in a wise man. But there is a certain 140soundness of mind,
which even a fool may have, when the perturbation of his mind is removed
by the care and management of his physicians. And as what is called
beauty arises from an exact proportion of the limbs, together with a
certain sweetness of complexion, so the beauty of the mind consists in
an equality and constancy of opinions and judgments, joined to a certain
firmness and stability, pursuing virtue, or containing within itself the
very essence of virtue. Besides, we give the very same names to the
faculties of the mind as we do to the powers of the body, the nerves,
and other powers of action. Thus the velocity of the body is called
swiftness: a praise which we ascribe to the mind, from its running over
in its thoughts so many things in so short a time.
XIV. Herein, indeed, the mind and body are unlike: that though the mind
when in perfect health may be visited by sickness, as the body may, yet
the body may be disordered without our fault; the mind cannot. For all
the disorders and perturbations of the mind proceed from a neglect of
reason; these disorders, therefore, are confined to men: the beasts are
not subject to such perturbations, though they act sometimes as if they
had reason. There is a difference, too, between ingenious and dull men;
the ingenious, like the Corinthian brass, which is long before it
receives rust, are longer before they fall into these perturbations, and
are recovered sooner: the case is different with the dull. Nor does the
mind of an ingenious man fall into every kind of perturbation, for it
never yields to any that are brutish and savage; and some of their
perturbations have at first even the appearance of humanity, as mercy,
grief, and fear. But the sicknesses and diseases of the mind are thought
to be harder to eradicate than those leading vices which are in
opposition to virtues; for vices may be removed, though the diseases of
the mind should continue, which diseases are not cured with that
expedition with which vices are removed. I have now acquainted you with
the arguments which the Stoics put forth with such exactness; which they
call logic, from their close arguing: and since my discourse has got
clear of these rocks, I will proceed with the remainder of it, provided
I have been sufficiently clear in what I have already 141said, considering
the obscurity of the subject I have treated.
A. Clear enough; but should there be occasion for a more exact
inquiry, I shall take another opportunity of asking you. I expect you
now to hoist your sails, as you just now called them, and proceed on
your course.
XV. M. Since I have spoken before of virtue in other places, and shall
often have occasion to speak again (for a great many questions that
relate to life and manners arise from the spring of virtue); and since,
as I say, virtue consists in a settled and uniform affection of mind,
making those persons praiseworthy who are possessed of her, she herself
also, independent of anything else, without regard to any advantage,
must be praiseworthy; for from her proceed good inclinations, opinions,
actions, and the whole of right reason; though virtue may be defined in
a few words to be right reason itself. The opposite to this is
viciousness (for so I choose to translate what the Greeks call ОєО±ОєбЅ·О±,
rather than by perverseness; for perverseness is the name of a
particular vice; but viciousness includes all), from whence arise those
perturbations which, as I just now said, are turbid and violent motions
of the mind, repugnant to reason, and enemies in a high degree to the
peace of the mind and a tranquil life, for they introduce piercing and
anxious cares, and afflict and debilitate the mind through fear; they
violently inflame our hearts with exaggerated appetite, which is in
reality an impotence of mind, utterly irreconcilable with temperance and
moderation, which we sometimes call desire, and sometimes lust, and
which, should it even attain the object of its wishes, immediately
becomes so elated that it loses all its resolution, and knows not what
to pursue; so that he was in the right who said “that exaggerated
pleasure was the very greatest of mistakes.” Virtue, then, alone can
effect the cure of these evils.
XVI. For what is not only more miserable, but more base and sordid, than
a man afflicted, weakened, and oppressed with grief? And little short of
this misery is one who dreads some approaching evil, and who, through
faintheartedness, is under continual suspense. The poets, to express the
greatness of this evil, imagine a stone to 142hang over the head of
Tantalus, as a punishment for his wickedness, his pride, and his
boasting. And this is the common punishment of folly; for there hangs
over the head of every one whose mind revolts from reason some similar
fear. And as these perturbations of the mind, grief and fear, are of a
most wasting nature, so those two others, though of a more merry cast (I
mean lust, which is always coveting something with eagerness, and empty
mirth, which is an exulting joy), differ very little from madness. Hence
you may understand what sort of person he is whom we call at one time
moderate, at another modest or temperate, at another constant and
virtuous; while sometimes we include all these names in the word
frugality, as the crown of all; for if that word did not include all
virtues, it would never have been proverbial to say that a frugal man
does everything rightly. But when the Stoics apply this saying to their
wise man, they seem to exalt him too much, and to speak of him with too
much admiration.
XVII. Whoever, then, through moderation and constancy, is at rest in his
mind, and in calm possession of himself, so as neither to pine with
care, nor be dejected with fear, nor to be inflamed with desire,
coveting something greedily, nor relaxed by extravagant mirth—such a
man is that identical wise man whom we are inquiring for: he is the
happy man, to whom nothing in this life seems intolerable enough to
depress him; nothing exquisite enough to transport him unduly. For what
is there in this life that can appear great to him who has acquainted
himself with eternity and the utmost extent of the universe? For what is
there in human knowledge, or the short span of this life, that can
appear great to a wise man? whose mind is always so upon its guard that
nothing can befall him which is unforeseen, nothing which is unexpected,
nothing, in short, which is new. Such a man takes so exact a survey on
all sides of him, that he always knows the proper place and spot to live
in free from all the troubles and annoyances of life, and encounters
every accident that fortune can bring upon him with a becoming calmness.
Whoever conducts himself in this manner will be free from grief, and
from every other perturbation; and a mind free from these feelings
renders men completely happy; whereas 143a mind disordered and drawn off
from right and unerring reason loses at once, not only its resolution,
but its health.—Therefore the thoughts and declarations of the
Peripatetics are soft and effeminate, for they say that the mind must
necessarily be agitated, but at the same time they lay down certain
bounds beyond which that agitation is not to proceed. And do you set
bounds to vice? or is it no vice to disobey reason? Does not reason
sufficiently declare that there is no real good which you should desire
too ardently, or the possession of which you should allow to transport
you? and that there is no evil that should be able to overwhelm you, or
the suspicion of which should distract you? and that all these things
assume too melancholy or too cheerful an appearance through our own
error? But if fools find this error lessened by time, so that, though
the cause remains the same, they are not affected, in the same manner,
after some time, as they were at first, why, surely a wise man ought not
to be influenced at all by it. But what are those degrees by which we
are to limit it? Let us fix these degrees in grief, a difficult subject,
and one much canvassed.—Fannius writes that P. Rutilius took it much to
heart that his brother was refused the consulship; but he seems to have
been too much affected by this disappointment, for it was the occasion
of his death: he ought, therefore, to have borne it with more
moderation. But let us suppose that while he was bearing this with
moderation, the death of his children had intervened; here would have
started a fresh grief, which, admitting it to be moderate in itself, yet
still must have been a great addition to the other. Now, to these let us
add some acute pains of body, the loss of his fortune, blindness,
banishment. Supposing, then, each separate misfortune to occasion a
separate additional grief, the whole would be too great to be
supportable.
XVIII. The man who attempts to set bounds to vice acts like one who
should throw himself headlong from Leucate, persuaded that he could stop
himself whenever he pleased. Now, as that is impossible, so a perturbed
and disordered mind cannot restrain itself, and stop where it pleases.
Certainly whatever is bad in its increase is bad in its birth. Now grief
and all other perturbations 144are doubtless baneful in their progress,
and have, therefore, no small share of evil at the beginning; for they
go on of themselves when once they depart from reason, for every
weakness is self-indulgent, and indiscreetly launches out, and does not
know where to stop. So that it makes no difference whether you approve
of moderate perturbations of mind, or of moderate injustice, moderate
cowardice, and moderate intemperance; for whoever prescribes bounds to
vice admits a part of it, which, as it is odious of itself, becomes the
more so as it stands on slippery ground, and, being once set forward,
glides on headlong, and cannot by any means be stopped.
XIX. Why should I say more? Why should I add that the Peripatetics say
that these perturbations, which we insist upon it should be extirpated,
are not only natural, but were given to men by nature for a good
purpose? They usually talk in this manner. In the first place, they say
much in praise of anger; they call it the whetstone of courage, and they
say that angry men exert themselves most against an enemy or against a
bad citizen: that those reasons are of little weight which are the
motives of men who think thus, as—it is a just war; it becomes us to
fight for our laws, our liberties, our country: they will allow no force
to these arguments unless our courage is warmed by anger.—Nor do they
confine their argument to warriors; but their opinion is that no one can
issue any rigid commands without some bitterness and anger. In short,
they have no notion of an orator either accusing or even defending a
client without he is spurred on by anger. And though this anger should
not be real, still they think his words and gestures ought to wear the
appearance of it, so that the action of the orator may excite the anger
of his hearer. And they deny that any man has ever been seen who does
not know what it is to be angry; and they name what we call lenity by
the bad appellation of indolence. Nor do they commend only this lust
(for anger is, as I defined it above, the lust of revenge), but they
maintain that kind of lust or desire to be given us by nature for very
good purposes, saying that no one can execute anything well but what he
is in earnest about. Themistocles used to walk in the public places in
the night because he could 145not sleep; and when asked the reason, his
answer was, that Miltiades’s trophies kept him awake. Who has not heard
how Demosthenes used to watch, who said that it gave him pain if any
mechanic was up in a morning at his work before him? Lastly, they urge
that some of the greatest philosophers would never have made that
progress in their studies without some ardent desire spurring them
on.—We are informed that Pythagoras, Democritus, and Plato visited the
remotest parts of the world; for they thought that they ought to go
wherever anything was to be learned. Now, it is not conceivable that
these things could be effected by anything but by the greatest ardor of
mind.
XX. They say that even grief, which we have already said ought to be
avoided as a monstrous and fierce beast, was appointed by nature, not
without some good purpose, in order that men should lament when they had
committed a fault, well knowing they had exposed themselves to
correction, rebuke, and ignominy; for they think that those who can bear
ignominy and infamy without pain have acquired a complete impunity for
all sorts of crimes; for with them reproach is a stronger check than
conscience. From whence we have that scene in Afranius borrowed from
common life; for when the abandoned son saith, “Wretched that I am!” the
severe father replies,
Let him but grieve, no matter what the cause.
And they say the other divisions of sorrow have their use; that pity
incites us to hasten to the assistance of others, and to alleviate the
calamities of men who have undeservedly fallen into them; that even envy
and detraction are not without their use, as when a man sees that
another person has attained what he cannot, or observes another to be
equally successful with himself; that he who should take away fear would
take away all industry in life, which those men exert in the greatest
degree who are afraid of the laws and of the magistrates, who dread
poverty, ignominy, death, and pain. But while they argue thus, they
allow indeed of these feelings being retrenched, though they deny that
they either can or should be plucked up by the roots; so that their
opinion is that mediocrity is 146best in everything. When they reason in
this manner, what think you—is what they say worth attending to or not?
A. I think it is. I wait, therefore, to hear what you will say in
reply to them.
XXI. M. Perhaps I may find something to say; but I will make this
observation first: do you take notice with what modesty the Academics
behave themselves? for they speak plainly to the purpose. The
Peripatetics are answered by the Stoics; they have my leave to fight it
out, who think myself no otherwise concerned than to inquire for what
may seem to be most probable. Our present business is, then, to see if
we can meet with anything in this question which is the probable, for
beyond such approximation to truth as that human nature cannot proceed.
The definition of a perturbation, as Zeno, I think, has rightly
determined it, is thus: That a perturbation is a commotion of the mind
against nature, in opposition to right reason; or, more briefly, thus,
that a perturbation is a somewhat too vehement appetite; and when he
says somewhat too vehement, he means such as is at a greater distance
from the constant course of nature. What can I say to these definitions?
The greater part of them we have from those who dispute with sagacity
and acuteness: some of them expressions, indeed, such as the “ardors of
the mind,” and “the whetstones of virtue,” savoring of the pomp of
rhetoricians. As to the question, if a brave man can maintain his
courage without becoming angry, it may be questioned with regard to the
gladiators; though we often observe much resolution even in them: they
meet, converse, they make objections and demands, they agree about
terms, so that they seem calm rather than angry. But let us admit a man
of the name of Placideianus, who was one of that trade, to be in such a
mind, as Lucilius relates of him,
If for his blood you thirst, the task be mine;
His laurels at my feet he shall resign;
Not but I know, before I reach his heart,
First on myself a wound he will impart.
I hate the man; enraged I fight, and straight
In action we had been, but that I wait
Till each his sword had fitted to his hand.
My rage I scarce can keep within command.
147XXII. But we see Ajax in Homer advancing to meet Hector in battle
cheerfully, without any of this boisterous wrath. For he had no sooner
taken up his arms than the first step which he made inspired his
associates with joy, his enemies with fear; so that even Hector, as he
is represented by Homer,
49 trembling, condemned himself for having
challenged him to fight. Yet these heroes conversed together, calmly and
quietly, before they engaged; nor did they show any anger or outrageous
behavior during the combat. Nor do I imagine that Torquatus, the first
who obtained this surname, was in a rage when he plundered the Gaul of
his collar; or that Marcellus’s courage at Clastidium was only owing to
his anger. I could almost swear that Africanus, with whom we are better
acquainted, from our recollection of him being more recent, was noways
inflamed by anger when he covered Alienus Pelignus with his shield, and
drove his sword into the enemy’s breast. There may be some doubt of L.
Brutus, whether he was not influenced by extraordinary hatred of the
tyrant, so as to attack Aruns with more than usual rashness; for I
observe that they mutually killed each other in close fight. Why, then,
do you call in the assistance of anger? Would courage, unless it began
to get
148furious, lose its energy? What! do you imagine that Hercules,
whom the very courage which you would try to represent as anger raised
to heaven, was angry when he engaged the Erymanthian boar, or the Nemæan
lion? Or was Theseus in a passion when he seized on the horns of the
Marathonian bull? Take care how you make courage to depend in the least
on rage. For anger is altogether irrational, and that is not courage
which is void of reason.
XXIII. We ought to hold all things here in contempt; death is to be
looked on with indifference; pains and labors must be considered as
easily supportable. And when these sentiments are established on
judgment and conviction, then will that stout and firm courage take
place; unless you attribute to anger whatever is done with vehemence,
alacrity, and spirit. To me, indeed, that very Scipio
50 who was chief
priest, that favorer of the saying of the Stoics, “That no private man
could be a wise man,” does not seem to be angry with Tiberius Gracchus,
even when he left the consul in a hesitating frame of mind, and, though
a private man himself, commanded, with the authority of a consul, that
all who meant well to the republic should follow him. I do not know
whether I have done anything in the republic that has the appearance of
courage; but if I have, I certainly did not do it in wrath. Doth
anything come nearer madness than anger? And indeed Ennius has well
defined it as the beginning of madness. The changing color, the
alteration of our voice, the look of our eyes, our manner of fetching
our breath, the little command we have over our words and actions, how
little do all these things indicate a sound mind! What can make a worse
appearance than Homer’s Achilles, or Agamemnon, during the quarrel? And
as to Ajax, anger drove him into downright madness, and was the occasion
of his death. Courage, therefore, does not want the assistance of anger;
it is sufficiently provided, armed, and prepared of itself. We may as
well say that drunkenness or madness is of service to courage, because
those who
149are mad or drunk often do a great many things with unusual
vehemence. Ajax was always brave; but still he was most brave when he
was in that state of frenzy:
The greatest feat that Ajax e’er achieved
Was, when his single arm the Greeks relieved.
Quitting the field; urged on by rising rage,
Forced the declining troops again t’engage.
Shall we say, then, that madness has its use?
XXIV. Examine the definitions of courage: you will find it does not
require the assistance of passion. Courage is, then, an affection of
mind that endures all things, being itself in proper subjection to the
highest of all laws; or it may be called a firm maintenance of judgment
in supporting or repelling everything that has a formidable appearance,
or a knowledge of what is formidable or otherwise, and maintaining
invariably a stable judgment of all such things, so as to bear them or
despise them; or, in fewer words, according to Chrysippus (for the above
definitions are Sphærus’s, a man of the first ability as a layer-down of
definitions, as the Stoics think. But they are all pretty much alike:
they give us only common notions, some one way, and some another). But
what is Chrysippus’s definition? Fortitude, says he, is the knowledge of
all things that are bearable, or an affection of the mind which bears
and supports everything in obedience to the chief law of reason without
fear. Now, though we should attack these men in the same manner as
Carneades used to do, I fear they are the only real philosophers; for
which of these definitions is there which does not explain that obscure
and intricate notion of courage which every man conceives within
himself? And when it is thus explained, what can a warrior, a commander,
or an orator want more? And no one can think that they will be unable to
behave themselves courageously without anger. What! do not even the
Stoics, who maintain that all fools are mad, make the same inferences?
for, take away perturbations, especially a hastiness of temper, and they
will appear to talk very absurdly. But what they assert is this: they
say that all fools are mad, as all dunghills stink; not that they always
do so, but stir them, and you will perceive it. And in like manner, a
warm-tempered man is 150not always in a passion; but provoke him, and you
will see him run mad. Now, that very warlike anger, which is of such
service in war, what is the use of it to him when he is at home with his
wife, children, and family? Is there, then, anything that a disturbed
mind can do better than one which is calm and steady? Or can any one be
angry without a perturbation of mind? Our people, then, were in the
right, who, as all vices depend on our manners, and nothing is worse
than a passionate disposition, called angry men the only morose men.51
XXV. Anger is in no wise becoming in an orator, though it is not amiss
to affect it. Do you imagine that I am angry when in pleading I use any
extraordinary vehemence and sharpness? What! when I write out my
speeches after all is over and past, am I then angry while writing? Or
do you think Г†sopus was ever angry when he acted, or Accius was so when
he wrote? Those men, indeed, act very well, but the orator acts better
than the player, provided he be really an orator; but, then, they carry
it on without passion, and with a composed mind. But what wantonness is
it to commend lust! You produce Themistocles and Demosthenes; to these
you add Pythagoras, Democritus, and Plato. What! do you then call
studies lust? But these studies of the most excellent and admirable
things, such as those were which you bring forward on all occasions,
ought to be composed and tranquil; and what kind of philosophers are
they who commend grief, than which nothing is more detestable? Afranius
has said much to this purpose:
Let him but grieve, no matter what the cause.
But he spoke this of a debauched and dissolute youth. But we are
inquiring into the conduct of a constant and wise man. We may even allow
a centurion or standard-bearer to be angry, or any others, whom, not to
explain too far the mysteries of the rhetoricians, I shall not mention
here; for to touch the passions, where reason cannot be come at, may
have its use; but my inquiry, as I often repeat, is about a wise man.
151XXVI. But even envy, detraction, pity, have their use. Why should you
pity rather than assist, if it is in your power to do so? Is it because
you cannot be liberal without pity? We should not take sorrows on
ourselves upon another’s account; but we ought to relieve others of
their grief if we can. But to detract from another’s reputation, or to
rival him with that vicious emulation which resembles an enmity, of what
use can that conduct be? Now, envy implies being uneasy at another’s
good because one does not enjoy it one’s self; but detraction is the
being uneasy at another’s good, merely because he enjoys it. How can it
be right that you should voluntarily grieve, rather than take the
trouble of acquiring what you want to have? for it is madness in the
highest degree to desire to be the only one that has any particular
happiness. But who can with correctness speak in praise of a mediocrity
of evils? Can any one in whom there is lust or desire be otherwise than
libidinous or desirous? or can a man who is occupied by anger avoid
being angry? or can one who is exposed to any vexation escape being
vexed? or if he is under the influence of fear, must he not be fearful?
Do we look, then, on the libidinous, the angry, the anxious, and the
timid man, as persons of wisdom, of excellence? of which I could speak
very copiously and diffusely, but I wish to be as concise as possible.
And so I will merely say that wisdom is an acquaintance with all divine
and human affairs, and a knowledge of the cause of everything. Hence it
is that it imitates what is divine, and looks upon all human concerns as
inferior to virtue. Did you, then, say that it was your opinion that
such a man was as naturally liable to perturbation as the sea is exposed
to winds? What is there that can discompose such gravity and constancy?
Anything sudden or unforeseen? How can anything of this kind befall one
to whom nothing is sudden and unforeseen that can happen to man? Now, as
to their saying that redundancies should be pared off, and only what is
natural remain, what, I pray you, can be natural which may be too
exuberant?
XXVII. All these assertions proceed from the roots of errors, which must
be entirely plucked up and destroyed, not pared and amputated. But as I
suspect that your inquiry 152is not so much respecting the wise man as
concerning yourself (for you allow that he is free from all
perturbations, and you would willingly be so too yourself), let us see
what remedies there are which may be applied by philosophy to the
diseases of the mind. There is certainly some remedy; nor has nature
been so unkind to the human race as to have discovered so many things
salutary to the body, and none which are medicinal to the mind. She has
even been kinder to the mind than to the body; inasmuch as you must seek
abroad for the assistance which the body requires, while the mind has
all that it requires within itself. But in proportion as the excellency
of the mind is of a higher and more divine nature, the more diligence
does it require; and therefore reason, when it is well applied,
discovers what is best, but when it is neglected, it becomes involved in
many errors. I shall apply, then, all my discourse to you; for though
you pretend to be inquiring about the wise man, your inquiry may
possibly be about yourself. Various, then, are the cures of those
perturbations which I have expounded, for every disorder is not to be
appeased the same way. One medicine must be applied to the man who
mourns, another to the pitiful, another to the person who envies; for
there is this difference to be maintained in all the four perturbations:
we are to consider whether our discourse had better be directed to
perturbations in general, which are a contempt of reason, or a somewhat
too vehement appetite; or whether it would be better applied to
particular descriptions, as, for instance, to fear, lust, and the rest,
and whether it appears preferable to endeavor to remove that which has
occasioned the grief, or rather to attempt wholly to eradicate every
kind of grief. As, should any one grieve that he is poor, the question
is, Would you maintain poverty to be no evil, or would you contend that
a man ought not to grieve at anything? Certainly this last is the best
course; for should you not convince him with regard to poverty, you must
allow him to grieve; but if you remove grief by particular arguments,
such as I used yesterday, the evil of poverty is in some manner removed.
XXVIII. But any perturbation of the mind of this sort may be, as it
were, wiped away by the method of appeasing 153the mind, if you succeed in
showing that there is no good in that which has given rise to joy and
lust, nor any evil in that which has occasioned fear or grief. But
certainly the most effectual cure is to be achieved by showing that all
perturbations are of themselves vicious, and have nothing natural or
necessary in them. As we see, grief itself is easily softened when we
charge those who grieve with weakness and an effeminate mind; or when we
commend the gravity and constancy of those who bear calmly whatever
befalls them here, as accidents to which all men are liable; and,
indeed, this is generally the feeling of those who look on these as real
evils, but yet think they should be borne with resignation. One imagines
pleasure to be a good, another money; and yet the one may be called off
from intemperance, the other from covetousness. The other method and
address, which, at the same time that it removes the false opinion,
withdraws the disorder, has more subtlety in it; but it seldom succeeds,
and is not applicable to vulgar minds, for there are some diseases which
that medicine can by no means remove. For, should any one be uneasy
because he is without virtue, without courage, destitute of a sense of
duty or honesty, his anxiety proceeds from a real evil; and yet we must
apply another method of cure to him, and such a one as all the
philosophers, however they may differ about other things, agree in. For
they must necessarily agree in this, that commotions of the mind in
opposition to right reason are vicious; and that even admitting those
things to be evils which occasion fear or grief, and those to be goods
which provoke desire or joy, yet that very commotion itself is vicious;
for we mean by the expressions magnanimous and brave, one who is
resolute, sedate, grave, and superior to everything in this life; but
one who either grieves, or fears, or covets, or is transported with
passion, cannot come under that denomination; for these things are
consistent only with those who look on the things of this world as
things with which their minds are unequal to contend.
XXIX. Wherefore, as I before said, the philosophers have all one method
of cure, so that we need say nothing about what sort of thing that is
which 154disturbs the mind, but we must speak only concerning the
perturbation itself. Thus, first, with regard to desire itself, when the
business is only to remove that, the inquiry is not to be, whether that
thing be good or evil which provokes lust, but the lust itself is to be
removed; so that whether whatever is honest is the chief good, or
whether it consists in pleasure, or in both these things together, or in
the other three kinds of goods, yet should there be in any one too
vehement an appetite for even virtue itself, the whole discourse should
be directed to the deterring him from that vehemence. But human nature,
when placed in a conspicuous point of view, gives us every argument for
appeasing the mind, and, to make this the more distinct, the laws and
conditions of life should be explained in our discourse. Therefore, it
was not without reason that Socrates is reported, when Euripides was
exhibiting his play called Orestes, to have repeated the first three
verses of that tragedy—
What tragic story men can mournful tell,
Whate’er from fate or from the gods befell,
That human nature can support—
52
But, in order to persuade those to whom any misfortune has happened that
they can and ought to bear it, it is very useful to set before them an
enumeration of other persons who have borne similar calamities. Indeed,
the method of appeasing grief was explained in my dispute of yesterday,
and in my book on Consolation, which I wrote in the midst of my own
grief; for I was not myself so wise a man as to be insensible to grief,
and I used this, notwithstanding Chrysippus’s advice to the contrary,
who is against applying a medicine to the agitations of the mind while
they are fresh; but I did it, and committed a violence on nature, that
the greatness of my grief might give way to the greatness of the
medicine.
XXX. But fear borders upon grief, of which I have already said enough;
but I must say a little more on that. Now, as grief proceeds from what
is present, so does fear 155from future evil; so that some have said that
fear is a certain part of grief: others have called fear the harbinger
of trouble, which, as it were, introduces the ensuing evil. Now, the
reasons that make what is present supportable, make what is to come very
contemptible; for, with regard to both, we should take care to do
nothing low or grovelling, soft or effeminate, mean or abject. But,
notwithstanding we should speak of the inconstancy, imbecility, and
levity of fear itself, yet it is of very great service to speak
contemptuously of those very things of which we are afraid. So that it
fell out very well, whether it was by accident or design, that I
disputed the first and second day on death and pain—the two things that
are the most dreaded: now, if what I then said was approved of, we are
in a great degree freed from fear. And this is sufficient, as far as
regards the opinion of evils.
XXXI. Proceed we now to what are goods—that is to say, to joy and
desire. To me, indeed, one thing alone seems to embrace the question of
all that relates to the perturbations of the mind—the fact, namely,
that all perturbations are in our own power; that they are taken up upon
opinion, and are voluntary. This error, then, must be got rid of; this
opinion must be removed; and, as with regard to imagined evils, we are
to make them more supportable, so with respect to goods, we are to
lessen the violent effects of those things which are called great and
joyous. But one thing is to be observed, that equally relates both to
good and evil: that, should it be difficult to persuade any one that
none of those things which disturb the mind are to be looked on as good
or evil, yet a different cure is to be applied to different feelings;
and the malevolent person is to be corrected by one way of reasoning,
the lover by another, the anxious man by another, and the fearful by
another: and it would be easy for any one who pursues the best approved
method of reasoning, with regard to good and evil, to maintain that no
fool can be affected with joy, as he never can have anything good. But,
at present, my discourse proceeds upon the common received notions. Let,
then, honors, riches, pleasures, and the rest be the very good things
which they are imagined to be; yet a too elevated and exulting joy on
the possession 156of them is unbecoming; just as, though it might be
allowable to laugh, to giggle would be indecent. Thus, a mind enlarged
by joy is as blamable as a contraction of it by grief; and eager longing
is a sign of as much levity in desiring as immoderate joy is in
possessing; and, as those who are too dejected are said to be
effeminate, so they who are too elated with joy are properly called
volatile; and as feeling envy is a part of grief, and the being pleased
with another’s misfortune is a kind of joy, both these feelings are
usually corrected by showing the wildness and insensibility of them: and
as it becomes a man to be cautious, but it is unbecoming in him to be
fearful, so to be pleased is proper, but to be joyful improper. I have,
in order that I might be the better understood, distinguished pleasure
from joy. I have already said above, that a contraction of the mind can
never be right, but that an elation of it may; for the joy of Hector in
Nævius is one thing—
’Tis joy indeed to hear my praises sung
By you, who are the theme of honor’s tongue—
but that of the character in Trabea another: “The kind procuress,
allured by my money, will observe my nod, will watch my desires, and
study my will. If I but move the door with my little finger, instantly
it flies open; and if Chrysis should unexpectedly discover me, she will
run with joy to meet me, and throw herself into my arms.”
Now he will tell you how excellent he thinks this:
Not even fortune herself is so fortunate.
XXXII. Any one who attends the least to the subject will be convinced
how unbecoming this joy is. And as they are very shameful who are
immoderately delighted with the enjoyment of venereal pleasures, so are
they very scandalous who lust vehemently after them. And all that which
is commonly called love (and, believe me, I can find out no other name
to call it by) is of such a trivial nature that nothing, I think, is to
be compared to it: of which Cæcilius says,
I hold the man of every sense bereaved
Who grants not Love to be of Gods the chief:
157Whose mighty power whate’er is good effects,
Who gives to each his beauty and defects:
Hence, health and sickness; wit and folly, hence,
The God that love and hatred doth dispense!
An excellent corrector of life this same poetry, which thinks that love,
the promoter of debauchery and vanity, should have a place in the
council of the Gods! I am speaking of comedy, which could not subsist at
all without our approving of these debaucheries. But what said that
chief of the Argonauts in tragedy?
My life I owe to honor less than love.
What, then, are we to say of this love of Medea?—what a train of
miseries did it occasion! And yet the same woman has the assurance to
say to her father, in another poet, that she had a husband
Dearer by love than ever fathers were.
XXXIII. However, we may allow the poets to trifle, in whose fables we
see Jupiter himself engaged in these debaucheries: but let us apply to
the masters of virtue—the philosophers who deny love to be anything
carnal; and in this they differ from Epicurus, who, I think, is not much
mistaken. For what is that love of friendship? How comes it that no one
is in love with a deformed young man, or a handsome old one? I am of
opinion that this love of men had its rise from the Gymnastics of the
Greeks, where these kinds of loves are admissible and permitted;
therefore Ennius spoke well:
The censure of this crime to those is due
Who naked bodies first exposed to view.
Now, supposing them chaste, which I think is hardly possible, they are
uneasy and distressed, and the more so because they contain and refrain
themselves. But, to pass over the love of women, where nature has
allowed more liberty, who can misunderstand the poets in their rape of
Ganymede, or not apprehend what Laius says, and what he desires, in
Euripides? Lastly, what have the principal poets and the most learned
men published of themselves in their poems and songs? What doth Alcæus,
who was 158distinguished in his own republic for his bravery, write on the
love of young men? And as for Anacreon’s poetry, it is wholly on love.
But Ibycus of Rhegium appears, from his writings, to have had this love
stronger on him than all the rest.
XXXIV. Now we see that the loves of all these writers were entirely
libidinous. There have arisen also some among us philosophers (and Plato
is at the head of them, whom Dicæarchus blames not without reason) who
have countenanced love. The Stoics, in truth, say, not only that their
wise man may be a lover, but they even define love itself as an endeavor
to originate friendship out of the appearance of beauty. Now, provided
there is any one in the nature of things without desire, without care,
without a sigh, such a one may be a lover; for he is free from all lust:
but I have nothing to say to him, as it is lust of which I am now
speaking. But should there be any love—as there certainly is—which is
but little, or perhaps not at all, short of madness, such as his is in
the Leucadia—
Should there be any God whose care I am—
it is incumbent on all the Gods to see that he enjoys his amorous
pleasure.
Wretch that I am!
Nothing is more true, and he says very appropriately,
What, are you sane, who at this rate lament?
He seems even to his friends to be out of his senses: then how tragical
he becomes!
Thy aid, divine Apollo, I implore,
And thine, dread ruler of the wat’ry store!
Oh! all ye winds, assist me!
He thinks that the whole world ought to apply itself to help his love:
he excludes Venus alone, as unkind to him.
Thy aid, O Venus, why should I invoke?
He thinks Venus too much employed in her own lust to have regard to
anything else, as if he himself had not said and committed these
shameful things from lust.
159XXXV. Now, the cure for one who is affected in this manner is to show
how light, how contemptible, how very trifling he is in what he desires;
how he may turn his affections to another object, or accomplish his
desires by some other means; or else to persuade him that he may
entirely disregard it: sometimes he is to be led away to objects of
another kind, to study, business, or other different engagements and
concerns: very often the cure is effected by change of place, as sick
people, that have not recovered their strength, are benefited by change
of air. Some people think an old love may be driven out by a new one, as
one nail drives out another: but, above all things, the man thus
afflicted should be advised what madness love is: for of all the
perturbations of the mind, there is not one which is more vehement; for
(without charging it with rapes, debaucheries, adultery, or even incest,
the baseness of any of these being very blamable; not, I say, to mention
these) the very perturbation of the mind in love is base of itself, for,
to pass over all its acts of downright madness, what weakness do not
those very things which are looked upon as indifferent argue?
Affronts and jealousies, jars, squabbles, wars,
Then peace again. The man who seeks to fix
These restless feelings, and to subjugate
Them to some regular law, is just as wise
As one who’d try to lay down rules by which
Men should go mad.
53
Now, is not this inconstancy and mutability of mind enough to deter any
one by its own deformity? We are to demonstrate, as was said of every
perturbation, that there are no such feelings which do not consist
entirely of opinion and judgment, and are not owing to ourselves. For if
love were natural, all would be in love, and always so, and all love the
same object; nor would one be deterred by shame, another by reflection,
another by satiety.
XXXVI. Anger, too, when it disturbs the mind any time, leaves no room to
doubt its being madness: by the 160instigation of which we see such
contention as this between brothers:
Where was there ever impudence like thine?
Who on thy malice ever could refine?
54
You know what follows: for abuses are thrown out by these brothers with
great bitterness in every other verse; so that you may easily know them
for the sons of Atreus, of that Atreus who invented a new punishment for
his brother:
I who his cruel heart to gall am bent,
Some new, unheard-of torment must invent.
Now, what were these inventions? Hear Thyestes:
My impious brother fain would have me eat
My children, and thus serves them up for meat.
To what length now will not anger go? even as far as madness. Therefore
we say, properly enough, that angry men have given up their power, that
is, they are out of the power of advice, reason, and understanding; for
these ought to have power over the whole mind. Now, you should put those
out of the way whom they endeavor to attack till they have recollected
themselves; but what does recollection here imply but getting together
again the dispersed parts of their mind into their proper place? or else
you must beg and entreat them, if they have the means of revenge, to
defer it to another opportunity, till their anger cools. But the
expression of cooling implies, certainly, that there was a heat raised
in their minds in opposition to reason; from which consideration that
saying of Archytas is commended, who being somewhat provoked at his
steward, “How would I have treated you,” said he, “if I had not been in
a passion?”
XXXVII. Where, then, are they who say that anger has its use? Can
madness be of any use? But still it is natural. Can anything be natural
that is against reason? or how is it, if anger is natural, that one
person is more inclined to anger than another? or that the lust of
revenge should cease before it has revenged itself? or that any one
161should repent of what he had done in a passion? as we see that
Alexander the king did, who could scarcely keep his hands from himself,
when he had killed his favorite Clytus, so great was his compunction.
Now who that is acquainted with these instances can doubt that this
motion of the mind is altogether in opinion and voluntary? for who can
doubt that disorders of the mind, such as covetousness and a desire of
glory, arise from a great estimation of those things by which the mind
is disordered? from whence we may understand that every perturbation of
the mind is founded in opinion. And if boldness—that is to say, a firm
assurance of mind—is a kind of knowledge and serious opinion not
hastily taken up, then diffidence is a fear of an expected and impending
evil; and if hope is an expectation of good, fear must, of course, be an
expectation of evil. Thus fear and other perturbations are evils.
Therefore, as constancy proceeds from knowledge, so does perturbation
from error. Now, they who are said to be naturally inclined to anger, or
to pity, or to envy, or to any feeling of this kind, their minds are
constitutionally, as it were, in bad health; yet they are curable, as
the disposition of Socrates is said to have been; for when Zopyrus, who
professed to know the character of every one from his person, had heaped
a great many vices on him in a public assembly, he was laughed at by
others, who could perceive no such vices in Socrates; but Socrates kept
him in countenance by declaring that such vices were natural to him, but
that he had got the better of them by his reason. Therefore, as any one
who has the appearance of the best constitution may yet appear to be
naturally rather inclined to some particular disorder, so different
minds may be more particularly inclined to different diseases. But as to
those men who are said to be vicious, not by nature, but their own
fault, their vices proceed from wrong opinions of good and bad things,
so that one is more prone than another to different motions and
perturbations. But, just as it is in the case of the body, an inveterate
disease is harder to be got rid of than a sudden disorder; and it is
more easy to cure a fresh tumor in the eyes than to remove a defluxion
of any continuance.
XXXVIII. But as the cause of perturbations is now discovered, 162for all
of them arise from the judgment or opinion, or volition, I shall put an
end to this discourse. But we ought to be assured, since the boundaries
of good and evil are now discovered, as far as they are discoverable by
man, that nothing can be desired of philosophy greater or more useful
than the discussions which we have held these four days. For besides
instilling a contempt of death, and relieving pain so as to enable men
to bear it, we have added the appeasing of grief, than which there is no
greater evil to man. For though every perturbation of mind is grievous,
and differs but little from madness, yet we are used to say of others
when they are under any perturbation, as of fear, joy, or desire, that
they are agitated and disturbed; but of those who give themselves up to
grief, that they are miserable, afflicted, wretched, unhappy. So that it
doth not seem to be by accident, but with reason proposed by you, that I
should discuss grief, and the other perturbations separately; for there
lies the spring and head of all our miseries; but the cure of grief, and
of other disorders, is one and the same in that they are all voluntary,
and founded on opinion; we take them on ourselves because it seems right
so to do. Philosophy undertakes to eradicate this error, as the root of
all our evils: let us therefore surrender ourselves to be instructed by
it, and suffer ourselves to be cured; for while these evils have
possession of us, we not only cannot be happy, but cannot be right in
our minds. We must either deny that reason can effect anything, while,
on the other hand, nothing can be done right without reason, or else,
since philosophy depends on the deductions of reason, we must seek from
her, if we would be good or happy, every help and assistance for living
well and happily.
163BOOK V.
WHETHER VIRTUE ALONE BE SUFFICIENT FOR A HAPPY LIFE.
I.
This fifth day, Brutus, shall put an end to our Tusculan
Disputations: on which day we discussed your favorite subject. For I
perceive from that book which you wrote for me with the greatest
accuracy, as well as from your frequent conversation, that you are
clearly of this opinion, that virtue is of itself sufficient for a happy
life: and though it may be difficult to prove this, on account of the
many various strokes of fortune, yet it is a truth of such a nature that
we should endeavor to facilitate the proof of it. For among all the
topics of philosophy, there is not one of more dignity or importance.
For as the first philosophers must have had some inducement to neglect
everything for the search of the best state of life: surely, the
inducement must have been the hope of living happily, which impelled
them to devote so much care and pains to that study. Now, if virtue was
discovered and carried to perfection by them, and if virtue is a
sufficient security for a happy life, who can avoid thinking the work of
philosophizing excellently recommended by them, and undertaken by me?
But if virtue, as being subject to such various and uncertain accidents,
were but the slave of fortune, and were not of sufficient ability to
support herself, I am afraid that it would seem desirable rather to
offer up prayers, than to rely on our own confidence in virtue as the
foundation for our hope of a happy life. And, indeed, when I reflect on
those troubles with which I have been so severely exercised by fortune,
I begin to distrust this opinion; and sometimes even to dread the
weakness and frailty of human nature, for I am afraid lest, when nature
had given us infirm bodies, and had joined to them incurable diseases
and intolerable pains, she perhaps also gave us minds participating in
these bodily pains, and harassed
164also with troubles and uneasinesses,
peculiarly their own. But here I correct myself for forming my judgment
of the power of virtue more from the weakness of others, or of myself
perhaps, than from virtue itself: for she herself (provided there is
such a thing as virtue; and your uncle Brutus has removed all doubt of
it) has everything that can befall mankind in subjection to her; and by
disregarding such things, she is far removed from being at all concerned
at human accidents; and, being free from every imperfection, she thinks
that nothing which is external to herself can concern her. But we, who
increase every approaching evil by our fear, and every present one by
our grief, choose rather to condemn the nature of things than our own
errors.
II. But the amendment of this fault, and of all our other vices and
offences, is to be sought for in philosophy: and as my own inclination
and desire led me, from my earliest youth upward, to seek her
protection, so, under my present misfortunes, I have had recourse to the
same port from whence I set out, after having been tossed by a violent
tempest. O Philosophy, thou guide of life! thou discoverer of virtue and
expeller of vices! what had not only I myself, but the whole life of
man, been without you? To you it is that we owe the origin of cities;
you it was who called together the dispersed race of men into social
life; you united them together, first, by placing them near one another,
then by marriages, and lastly, by the communication of speech and
languages. You have been the inventress of laws; you have been our
instructress in morals and discipline; to you we fly for refuge; from
you we implore assistance; and as I formerly submitted to you in a great
degree, so now I surrender up myself entirely to you. For one day spent
well, and agreeably to your precepts, is preferable to an eternity of
error. Whose assistance, then, can be of more service to me than yours,
when you have bestowed on us tranquillity of life, and removed the fear
of death? But Philosophy is so far from being praised as much as she has
deserved by mankind, that she is wholly neglected by most men, and
actually evil spoken of by many. Can any person speak ill of the parent
of life, and dare to pollute himself thus with parricide, and be so
impiously
165ungrateful as to accuse her whom he ought to reverence, even
were he less able to appreciate the advantages which he might derive
from her? But this error, I imagine, and this darkness has spread itself
over the minds of ignorant men, from their not being able to look so far
back, and from their not imagining that those men by whom human life was
first improved were philosophers; for though we see philosophy to have
been of long standing, yet the name must be acknowledged to be but
modern.
III. But, indeed, who can dispute the antiquity of philosophy, either in
fact or name? For it acquired this excellent name from the ancients, by
the knowledge of the origin and causes of everything, both divine and
human. Thus those seven
ОЈбЅ№П†ОїО№, as they were considered and called by the
Greeks, have always been esteemed and called wise men by us; and thus
Lycurgus many ages before, in whose time, before the building of this
city, Homer is said to have lived, as well as Ulysses and Nestor in the
heroic ages, are all handed down to us by tradition as having really
been what they were called, wise men; nor would it have been said that
Atlas supported the heavens, or that Prometheus was bound to Caucasus,
nor would Cepheus, with his wife, his son-in-law, and his daughter have
been enrolled among the constellations, but that their more than human
knowledge of the heavenly bodies had transferred their names into an
erroneous fable. From whence all who occupied themselves in the
contemplation of nature were both considered and called wise men; and
that name of theirs continued to the age of Pythagoras, who is reported
to have gone to Phlius, as we find it stated by Heraclides Ponticus, a
very learned man, and a pupil of Plato, and to have discoursed very
learnedly and copiously on certain subjects with Leon, prince of the
Phliasii; and when Leon, admiring his ingenuity and eloquence, asked him
what art he particularly professed, his answer was, that he was
acquainted with no art, but that he was a philosopher. Leon, surprised
at the novelty of the name, inquired what he meant by the name of
philosopher, and in what philosophers differed from other men; on which
Pythagoras replied, “That the life of man seemed to him to resemble
those games which were celebrated with the
166greatest possible variety of
sports and the general concourse of all Greece. For as in those games
there were some persons whose object was glory and the honor of a crown,
to be attained by the performance of bodily exercises, so others were
led thither by the gain of buying and selling, and mere views of profit;
but there was likewise one class of persons, and they were by far the
best, whose aim was neither applause nor profit, but who came merely as
spectators through curiosity, to observe what was done, and to see in
what manner things were carried on there. And thus, said he, we come
from another life and nature unto this one, just as men come out of some
other city, to some much frequented mart; some being slaves to glory,
others to money; and there are some few who, taking no account of
anything else, earnestly look into the nature of things; and these men
call themselves studious of wisdom, that is, philosophers: and as there
it is the most reputable occupation of all to be a looker-on without
making any acquisition, so in life, the contemplating things, and
acquainting one’s self with them, greatly exceeds every other pursuit of
life.”
IV. Nor was Pythagoras the inventor only of the name, but he enlarged
also the thing itself, and, when he came into Italy after this
conversation at Phlius, he adorned that Greece, which is called Great
Greece, both privately and publicly, with the most excellent
institutions and arts; but of his school and system I shall, perhaps,
find another opportunity to speak. But numbers and motions, and the
beginning and end of all things, were the subjects of the ancient
philosophy down to Socrates, who was a pupil of Archelaus, who had been
the disciple of Anaxagoras. These made diligent inquiry into the
magnitude of the stars, their distances, courses, and all that relates
to the heavens. But Socrates was the first who brought down philosophy
from the heavens, placed it in cities, introduced it into families, and
obliged it to examine into life and morals, and good and evil. And his
different methods of discussing questions, together with the variety of
his topics, and the greatness of his abilities, being immortalized by
the memory and writings of Plato, gave rise to many sects of
philosophers of different sentiments, of all which I have principally
adhered
167to that one which, in my opinion, Socrates himself followed;
and argue so as to conceal my own opinion, while I deliver others from
their errors, and so discover what has the greatest appearance of
probability in every question. And the custom Carneades adopted with
great copiousness and acuteness, and I myself have often given in to it
on many occasions elsewhere, and in this manner, too, I disputed lately,
in my Tusculan villa; indeed, I have sent you a book of the four former
days’ discussions; but the fifth day, when we had seated ourselves as
before, what we were to dispute on was proposed thus:
V.
A. I do not think virtue can possibly be sufficient for a happy
life.
M. But my friend Brutus thinks so, whose judgment, with submission, I
greatly prefer to yours.
A. I make no doubt of it; but your regard for him is not the business
now: the question is now, what is the real character of that quality of
which I have declared my opinion. I wish you to dispute on that.
M. What! do you deny that virtue can possibly be sufficient for a
happy life?
A. It is what I entirely deny.
M. What! is not virtue sufficient to enable us to live as we ought,
honestly, commendably, or, in fine, to live well?
A. Certainly sufficient.
M. Can you, then, help calling any one miserable who lives ill? or
will you deny that any one who you allow lives well must inevitably live
happily?
A. Why may I not? for a man may be upright in his life, honest,
praiseworthy, even in the midst of torments, and therefore live well.
Provided you understand what I mean by well; for when I say well, I mean
with constancy, and dignity, and wisdom, and courage; for a man may
display all these qualities on the rack; but yet the rack is
inconsistent with a happy life.
M. What, then? is your happy life left on the outside of the prison,
while constancy, dignity, wisdom, and the other virtues, are surrendered
up to the executioner, and bear punishment and pain without reluctance?
A. You must look out for something new if you would
168do any good.
These things have very little effect on me, not merely from their being
common, but principally because, like certain light wines that will not
bear water, these arguments of the Stoics are pleasanter to taste than
to swallow. As when that assemblage of virtues is committed to the rack,
it raises so reverend a spectacle before our eyes that happiness seems
to hasten on towards them, and not to suffer them to be deserted by her.
But when you take your attention off from this picture and these images
of the virtues to the truth and the reality, what remains without
disguise is, the question whether any one can be happy in torment?
Wherefore let us now examine that point, and not be under any
apprehensions, lest the virtues should expostulate, and complain that
they are forsaken by happiness. For if prudence is connected with every
virtue, then prudence itself discovers this, that all good men are not
therefore happy; and she recollects many things of Marcus Atilius
55,
Quintus Cæpio
56, Marcus Aquilius
57; and prudence herself, if these
representations are more agreeable to you than the things themselves,
restrains happiness when it is endeavoring to throw itself into
torments, and denies that it has any connection with pain and torture.
VI.
M. I can easily bear with your behaving in this manner, though it
is not fair in you to prescribe to me how you would have me carry on
this discussion. But I ask you if I have effected anything or nothing in
the preceding days?
A. Yes; something was done, some little matter indeed.
M. But if that is the case, this question is settled, and almost put
an end to.
A. How so?
M. Because turbulent motions and violent agitations of
169the mind, when
it is raised and elated by a rash impulse, getting the better of reason,
leave no room for a happy life. For who that fears either pain or death,
the one of which is always present, the other always impending, can be
otherwise than miserable? Now, supposing the same person—which is often
the case—to be afraid of poverty, ignominy, infamy, or weakness, or
blindness, or, lastly, slavery, which doth not only befall individual
men, but often even the most powerful nations; now can any one under the
apprehension of these evils be happy? What shall we say of him who not
only dreads these evils as impending, but actually feels and bears them
at present? Let us unite in the same person banishment, mourning, the
loss of children; now, how can any one who is broken down and rendered
sick in body and mind by such affliction be otherwise than very
miserable indeed? What reason, again, can there be why a man should not
rightly enough be called miserable whom we see inflamed and raging with
lust, coveting everything with an insatiable desire, and, in proportion
as he derives more pleasure from anything, thirsting the more violently
after them? And as to a man vainly elated, exulting with an empty joy,
and boasting of himself without reason, is not he so much the more
miserable in proportion as he thinks himself happier? Therefore, as
these men are miserable, so, on the other hand, those are happy who are
alarmed by no fears, wasted by no griefs, provoked by no lusts, melted
by no languid pleasures that arise from vain and exulting joys. We look
on the sea as calm when not the least breath of air disturbs its waves;
and, in like manner, the placid and quiet state of the mind is
discovered when unmoved by any perturbation. Now, if there be any one
who holds the power of fortune, and everything human, everything that
can possibly befall any man, as supportable, so as to be out of the
reach of fear or anxiety, and if such a man covets nothing, and is
lifted up by no vain joy of mind, what can prevent his being happy? And
if these are the effects of virtue, why cannot virtue itself make men
happy?
VII.
A. But the other of these two propositions is undeniable, that
they who are under no apprehensions, who are
170noways uneasy, who covet
nothing, who are lifted up by no vain joy, are happy: and therefore I
grant you that. But as for the other, that is not now in a fit state for
discussion; for it has been proved by your former arguments that a wise
man is free from every perturbation of mind.
M. Doubtless, then, the dispute is over; for the question appears to
have been entirely exhausted.
A. I think, indeed, that that is almost the case.
M. But yet that is more usually the case with the mathematicians than
philosophers. For when the geometricians teach anything, if what they
have before taught relates to their present subject, they take that for
granted which has been already proved, and explain only what they had
not written on before. But the philosophers, whatever subject they have
in hand, get together everything that relates to it, notwithstanding
they may have dilated on it somewhere else. Were not that the case, why
should the Stoics say so much on that question, Whether virtue was
abundantly sufficient to a happy life? when it would have been answer
enough that they had before taught that nothing was good but what was
honorable; for, as this had been proved, the consequence must be that
virtue was sufficient to a happy life; and each premise may be made to
follow from the admission of the other, so that if it be admitted that
virtue is sufficient to secure a happy life, it may also be inferred
that nothing is good except what is honorable. They, however, do not
proceed in this manner; for they would separate books about what is
honorable, and what is the chief good; and when they have demonstrated
from the one that virtue has power enough to make life happy, yet they
treat this point separately; for everything, and especially a subject of
such great consequence, should be supported by arguments and
exhortations which belong to that alone. For you should have a care how
you imagine philosophy to have uttered anything more noble, or that she
has promised anything more fruitful or of greater consequence, for, good
Gods! doth she not engage that she will render him who submits to her
laws so accomplished as to be always armed against fortune, and to have
every assurance within himself of living well and happily—that he
shall, in short, be forever
171happy? But let us see what she will
perform? In the mean while, I look upon it as a great thing that she has
even made such a promise. For Xerxes, who was loaded with all the
rewards and gifts of fortune, not satisfied with his armies of horse and
foot, nor the multitude of his ships, nor his infinite treasure of gold,
offered a reward to any one who could find out a new pleasure; and yet,
when it was discovered, he was not satisfied with it; nor can there ever
be an end to lust. I wish we could engage any one by a reward to produce
something the better to establish us in this belief.
VIII.
A. I wish that, indeed, myself; but I want a little information.
For I allow that in what you have stated the one proposition is the
consequence of the other; that as, if what is honorable be the only
good, it must follow that a happy life is the effect of virtue: so that
if a happy life consists in virtue, nothing can be good but virtue. But
your friend Brutus, on the authority of Aristo and Antiochus, does not
see this; for he thinks the case would be the same even if there were
anything good besides virtue.
M. What, then? do you imagine that I am going to argue against Brutus?
A. You may do what you please; for it is not for me to prescribe what
you shall do.
M. How these things agree together shall be examined somewhere else;
for I frequently discussed that point with Antiochus, and lately with
Aristo, when, during the period of my command as general, I was lodging
with him at Athens. For to me it seemed that no one could possibly be
happy under any evil; but a wise man might be afflicted with evil, if
there are any things arising from body or fortune deserving the name of
evils. These things were said, which Antiochus has inserted in his books
in many places—that virtue itself was sufficient to make life happy,
but yet not perfectly happy; and that many things derive their names
from the predominant portion of them, though they do not include
everything, as strength, health, riches, honor, and glory: which
qualities are determined by their kind, not their number. Thus a happy
life is so called from its being so in a great degree, even though it
172should fall short in some point. To clear this up is not absolutely
necessary at present, though it seems to be said without any great
consistency; for I cannot imagine what is wanting to one that is happy
to make him happier, for if anything be wanting to him, he cannot be so
much as happy; and as to what they say, that everything is named and
estimated from its predominant portion, that may be admitted in some
things. But when they allow three kinds of evils—when any one is
oppressed with every imaginable evil of two kinds, being afflicted with
adverse fortune, and having at the same time his body worn out and
harassed with all sorts of pains—shall we say that such a one is but
little short of a happy life, to say nothing about the happiest possible
life?
IX. This is the point which Theophrastus was unable to maintain; for
after he had once laid down the position that stripes, torments,
tortures, the ruin of one’s country, banishment, the loss of children,
had great influence on men’s living miserably and unhappily, he durst
not any longer use any high and lofty expressions when he was so low and
abject in his opinion. How right he was is not the question; he
certainly was consistent. Therefore, I am not for objecting to
consequences where the premises are admitted. But this most elegant and
learned of all the philosophers is not taken to task very severely when
he asserts his three kinds of good; but he is attacked by every one for
that book which he wrote on a happy life, in which book he has many
arguments why one who is tortured and racked cannot be happy. For in
that book he is supposed to say that a man who is placed on the wheel
(that is a kind of torture in use among the Greeks) cannot attain to a
completely happy life. He nowhere, indeed, says so absolutely; but what
he says amounts to the same thing. Can I, then, find fault with him,
after having allowed that pains of the body are evils, that the ruin of
a man’s fortunes is an evil, if he should say that every good man is not
happy, when all those things which he reckons as evils may befall a good
man? The same Theophrastus is found fault with by all the books and
schools of the philosophers for commending that sentence in his
Callisthenes,
Fortune, not wisdom, rules the life of man.
173They say never did philosopher assert anything so languid. They are
right, indeed, in that; but I do not apprehend anything could be more
consistent, for if there are so many good things that depend on the
body, and so many foreign to it that depend on chance and fortune, is it
inconsistent to say that fortune, which governs everything, both what is
foreign and what belongs to the body, has greater power than counsel. Or
would we rather imitate Epicurus? who is often excellent in many things
which he speaks, but quite indifferent how consistent he may be, or how
much to the purpose he is speaking. He commends spare diet, and in that
he speaks as a philosopher; but it is for Socrates or Antisthenes to say
so, and not for one who confines all good to pleasure. He denies that
any one can live pleasantly unless he lives honestly, wisely, and
justly. Nothing is more dignified than this assertion, nothing more
becoming a philosopher, had he not measured this very expression of
living honestly, justly, and wisely by pleasure. What could be better
than to assert that fortune interferes but little with a wise man? But
does he talk thus, who, after he has said that pain is the greatest
evil, or the only evil, might himself be afflicted with the sharpest
pains all over his body, even at the time he is vaunting himself the
most against fortune? And this very thing, too, Metrodorus has said, but
in better language: “I have anticipated you, Fortune; I have caught you,
and cut off every access, so that you cannot possibly reach me.” This
would be excellent in the mouth of Aristo the Chian, or Zeno the Stoic,
who held nothing to be an evil but what was base; but for you,
Metrodorus, to anticipate the approaches of fortune, who confine all
that is good to your bowels and marrow—for you to say so, who define
the chief good by a strong constitution of body, and well-assured hope
of its continuance—for you to cut off every access of fortune! Why, you
may instantly be deprived of that good. Yet the simple are taken with
these propositions, and a vast crowd is led away by such sentences to
become their followers.
X. But it is the duty of one who would argue accurately to consider not
what is said, but what is said consistently. 174As in that very opinion
which we have adopted in this discussion, namely, that every good man is
always happy, it is clear what I mean by good men: I call those both
wise and good men who are provided and adorned with every virtue. Let us
see, then, who are to be called happy. I imagine, indeed, that those men
are to be called so who are possessed of good without any alloy of evil;
nor is there any other notion connected with the word that expresses
happiness but an absolute enjoyment of good without any evil. Virtue
cannot attain this, if there is anything good besides itself. For a
crowd of evils would present themselves, if we were to allow poverty,
obscurity, humility, solitude, the loss of friends, acute pains of the
body, the loss of health, weakness, blindness, the ruin of one’s
country, banishment, slavery, to be evils; for a wise man may be
afflicted by all these evils, numerous and important as they are, and
many others also may be added, for they are brought on by chance, which
may attack a wise man; but if these things are evils, who can maintain
that a wise man is always happy when all these evils may light on him at
the same time? I therefore do not easily agree with my friend Brutus,
nor with our common masters, nor those ancient ones, Aristotle,
Speusippus, Xenocrates, Polemon, who reckon all that I have mentioned
above as evils, and yet they say that a wise man is always happy; nor
can I allow them, because they are charmed with this beautiful and
illustrious title, which would very well become Pythagoras, Socrates,
and Plato, to persuade my mind that strength, health, beauty, riches,
honors, power, with the beauty of which they are ravished, are
contemptible, and that all those things which are the opposites of these
are not to be regarded. Then might they declare openly, with a loud
voice, that neither the attacks of fortune, nor the opinion of the
multitude, nor pain, nor poverty, occasions them any apprehensions; and
that they have everything within themselves, and that there is nothing
whatever which they consider as good but what is within their own power.
Nor can I by any means allow the same person who falls into the vulgar
opinion of good and evil to make use of these expressions, which can
only become 175a great and exalted man. Struck with which glory, up starts
Epicurus, who, with submission to the Gods, thinks a wise man always
happy. He is much charmed with the dignity of this opinion, but he never
would have owned that, had he attended to himself; for what is there
more inconsistent than for one who could say that pain was the greatest
or the only evil to think also that a wise man can possibly say in the
midst of his torture, How sweet is this! We are not, therefore, to form
our judgment of philosophers from detached sentences, but from their
consistency with themselves, and their ordinary manner of talking.
XI. A. You compel me to be of your opinion; but have a care that you
are not inconsistent yourself.
M. In what respect?
A. Because I have lately read your fourth book on Good and Evil: and
in that you appeared to me, while disputing against Cato, to be
endeavoring to show, which in my opinion means to prove, that Zeno and
the Peripatetics differ only about some new words; but if we allow that,
what reason can there be, if it follows from the arguments of Zeno that
virtue contains all that is necessary to a happy life, that the
Peripatetics should not be at liberty to say the same? For, in my
opinion, regard should be had to the thing, not to words.
M. What! you would convict me from my own words, and bring against me
what I had said or written elsewhere. You may act in that manner with
those who dispute by established rules. We live from hand to mouth, and
say anything that strikes our mind with probability, so that we are the
only people who are really at liberty. But, since I just now spoke of
consistency, I do not think the inquiry in this place is, if the opinion
of Zeno and his pupil Aristo be true that nothing is good but what is
honorable; but, admitting that, then, whether the whole of a happy life
can be rested on virtue alone. Wherefore, if we certainly grant Brutus
this, that a wise man is always happy, how consistent he is, is his own
business; for who, indeed, is more worthy than himself of the glory of
that opinion? Still, we may maintain that such a man is more happy than
any one else.
176XII. Though Zeno the Cittiæan, a stranger and an inconsiderable coiner
of words, appears to have insinuated himself into the old philosophy;
still, the prevalence of this opinion is due to the authority of Plato,
who often makes use of this expression, “That nothing but virtue can be
entitled to the name of good,” agreeably to what Socrates says in
Plato’s Gorgias; for it is there related that when some one asked him if
he did not think Archelaus the son of Perdiccas, who was then looked
upon as a most fortunate person, a very happy man, “I do not know,”
replied he, “for I never conversed with him.” “What! is there no other
way you can know it by?” “None at all.” “You cannot, then, pronounce of
the great king of the Persians whether he is happy or not?” “How can I,
when I do not know how learned or how good a man he is?” “What! do you
imagine that a happy life depends on that?” “My opinion entirely is,
that good men are happy, and the wicked miserable.” “Is Archelaus, then,
miserable?” “Certainly, if unjust.” Now, does it not appear to you that
he is here placing the whole of a happy life in virtue alone? But what
does the same man say in his funeral oration? “For,” saith he, “whoever
has everything that relates to a happy life so entirely dependent on
himself as not to be connected with the good or bad fortune of another,
and not to be affected by, or made in any degree uncertain by, what
befalls another; and whoever is such a one has acquired the best rule of
living; he is that moderate, that brave, that wise man, who submits to
the gain and loss of everything, and especially of his children, and
obeys that old precept; for he will never be too joyful or too sad,
because he depends entirely upon himself.”
XIII. From Plato, therefore, all my discourse shall be deduced, as if
from some sacred and hallowed fountain. Whence can I, then, more
properly begin than from Nature, the parent of all? For whatsoever she
produces (I am not speaking only of animals, but even of those things
which have sprung from the earth in such a manner as to rest on their
own roots) she designed it to be perfect in its respective kind. So that
among trees and vines, and those lower plants and trees which cannot
advance themselves 177high above the earth, some are evergreen, others are
stripped of their leaves in winter, and, warmed by the spring season,
put them out afresh, and there are none of them but what are so
quickened by a certain interior motion, and their own seeds enclosed in
every one, so as to yield flowers, fruit, or berries, that all may have
every perfection that belongs to it; provided no violence prevents it.
But the force of Nature itself may be more easily discovered in animals,
as she has bestowed sense on them. For some animals she has taught to
swim, and designed to be inhabitants of the water; others she has
enabled to fly, and has willed that they should enjoy the boundless air;
some others she has made to creep, others to walk. Again, of these very
animals, some are solitary, some gregarious, some wild, others tame,
some hidden and buried beneath the earth, and every one of these
maintains the law of nature, confining itself to what was bestowed on
it, and unable to change its manner of life. And as every animal has
from nature something that distinguishes it, which every one maintains
and never quits; so man has something far more excellent, though
everything is said to be excellent by comparison. But the human mind,
being derived from the divine reason, can be compared with nothing but
with the Deity itself, if I may be allowed the expression. This, then,
if it is improved, and when its perception is so preserved as not to be
blinded by errors, becomes a perfect understanding, that is to say,
absolute reason, which is the very same as virtue. And if everything is
happy which wants nothing, and is complete and perfect in its kind, and
that is the peculiar lot of virtue, certainly all who are possessed of
virtue are happy. And in this I agree with Brutus, and also with
Aristotle, Xenocrates, Speusippus, Polemon.
XIV. To me such are the only men who appear completely happy; for what
can he want to a complete happy life who relies on his own good
qualities, or how can he be happy who does not rely on them? But he who
makes a threefold division of goods must necessarily be diffident, for
how can he depend on having a sound body, or that his fortune shall
continue? But no one can be happy without an immovable, fixed, and
permanent good. What, 178then, is this opinion of theirs? So that I think
that saying of the Spartan may be applied to them, who, on some
merchant’s boasting before him that he had despatched ships to every
maritime coast, replied that a fortune which depended on ropes was not
very desirable. Can there be any doubt that whatever may be lost cannot
be properly classed in the number of those things which complete a happy
life? for of all that constitutes a happy life, nothing will admit of
withering, or growing old, or wearing out, or decaying; for whoever is
apprehensive of any loss of these things cannot be happy: the happy man
should be safe, well fenced, well fortified, out of the reach of all
annoyance, not like a man under trifling apprehensions, but free from
all such. As he is not called innocent who but slightly offends, but he
who offends not at all, so it is he alone who is to be considered
without fear who is free from all fear, not he who is but in little
fear. For what else is courage but an affection of mind that is ready to
undergo perils, and patient in the endurance of pain and labor without
any alloy of fear? Now, this certainly could not be the case if there
were anything else good but what depended on honesty alone. But how can
any one be in possession of that desirable and much-coveted security
(for I now call a freedom from anxiety a security, on which freedom a
happy life depends) who has, or may have, a multitude of evils attending
him? How can he be brave and undaunted, and hold everything as trifles
which can befall a man? for so a wise man should do, unless he be one
who thinks that everything depends on himself. Could the Lacedæmonians
without this, when Philip threatened to prevent all their attempts, have
asked him if he could prevent their killing themselves? Is it not
easier, then, to find one man of such a spirit as we are inquiring
after, than to meet with a whole city of such men? Now, if to this
courage I am speaking of we add temperance, that it may govern all our
feelings and agitations, what can be wanting to complete his happiness
who is secured by his courage from uneasiness and fear, and is prevented
from immoderate desires and immoderate insolence of joy by temperance? I
could easily show that virtue is able to 179produce these effects, but
that I have explained on the foregoing days.
XV. But as the perturbations of the mind make life miserable, and
tranquillity renders it happy; and as these perturbations are of two
sorts, grief and fear, proceeding from imagined evils, and as immoderate
joy and lust arise from a mistake about what is good, and as all these
feelings are in opposition to reason and counsel; when you see a man at
ease, quite free and disengaged from such troublesome commotions, which
are so much at variance with one another, can you hesitate to pronounce
such a one a happy man? Now, the wise man is always in such a
disposition; therefore the wise man is always happy. Besides, every good
is pleasant; whatever is pleasant may be boasted and talked of; whatever
may be boasted of is glorious; but whatever is glorious is certainly
laudable, and whatever is laudable doubtless, also, honorable: whatever,
then, is good is honorable (but the things which they reckon as goods
they themselves do not call honorable); therefore what is honorable
alone is good. Hence it follows that a happy life is comprised in
honesty alone. Such things, then, are not to be called or considered
goods, when a man may enjoy an abundance of them, and yet be most
miserable. Is there any doubt but that a man who enjoys the best health,
and who has strength and beauty, and his senses flourishing in their
utmost quickness and perfection—suppose him likewise, if you please,
nimble and active, nay, give him riches, honors, authority, power,
glory—now, I say, should this person, who is in possession of all
these, be unjust, intemperate, timid, stupid, or an idiot—could you
hesitate to call such a one miserable? What, then, are those goods in
the possession of which you may be very miserable? Let us see if a happy
life is not made up of parts of the same nature, as a heap implies a
quantity of grain of the same kind. And if this be once admitted,
happiness must be compounded of different good things, which alone are
honorable; if there is any mixture of things of another sort with these,
nothing honorable can proceed from such a composition: now, take away
honesty, and how can you imagine anything happy? For whatever is good is
desirable on that account; whatever is desirable 180must certainly be
approved of; whatever you approve of must be looked on as acceptable and
welcome. You must consequently impute dignity to this; and if so, it
must necessarily be laudable: therefore, everything that is laudable is
good. Hence it follows that what is honorable is the only good. And
should we not look upon it in this light, there will be a great many
things which we must call good.
XVI. I forbear to mention riches, which, as any one, let him be ever so
unworthy, may have them, I do not reckon among goods; for what is good
is not attainable by all. I pass over notoriety and popular fame, raised
by the united voice of knaves and fools. Even things which are absolute
nothings may be called goods; such as white teeth, handsome eyes, a good
complexion, and what was commended by Euryclea, when she was washing
Ulysses’s feet, the softness of his skin and the mildness of his
discourse. If you look on these as goods, what greater encomiums can the
gravity of a philosopher be entitled to than the wild opinion of the
vulgar and the thoughtless crowd? The Stoics give the name of excellent
and choice to what the others call good: they call them so, indeed; but
they do not allow them to complete a happy life. But these others think
that there is no life happy without them; or, admitting it to be happy,
they deny it to be the most happy. But our opinion is, that it is the
most happy; and we prove it from that conclusion of Socrates. For thus
that author of philosophy argued: that as the disposition of a man’s
mind is, so is the man; such as the man is, such will be his discourse;
his actions will correspond with his discourse, and his life with his
actions. But the disposition of a good man’s mind is laudable; the life,
therefore, of a good man is laudable; it is honorable, therefore,
because laudable; the unavoidable conclusion from which is that the life
of good men is happy. For, good Gods! did I not make it appear, by my
former arguments—or was I only amusing myself and killing time in what
I then said?—that the mind of a wise man was always free from every
hasty motion which I call a perturbation, and that the most undisturbed
peace always reigned in his breast? A man, then, who is temperate and
consistent, free from fear or 181grief, and uninfluenced by any immoderate
joy or desire, cannot be otherwise than happy; but a wise man is always
so, therefore he is always happy. Moreover, how can a good man avoid
referring all his actions and all his feelings to the one standard of
whether or not it is laudable? But he does refer everything to the
object of living happily: it follows, then, that a happy life is
laudable; but nothing is laudable without virtue: a happy life, then, is
the consequence of virtue. And this is the unavoidable conclusion to be
drawn from these arguments.
XVII. A wicked life has nothing which we ought to speak of or glory in;
nor has that life which is neither happy nor miserable. But there is a
kind of life that admits of being spoken of, and gloried in, and boasted
of, as Epaminondas saith,
The wings of Sparta’s pride my counsels clipp’d.
And Africanus boasts,
Who, from beyond Mæotis to the place
Where the sun rises, deeds like mine can trace?
If, then, there is such a thing as a happy life, it is to be gloried in,
spoken of, and commended by the person who enjoys it; for there is
nothing excepting that which can be spoken of or gloried in; and when
that is once admitted, you know what follows. Now, unless an honorable
life is a happy life, there must, of course, be something preferable to
a happy life; for that which is honorable all men will certainly grant
to be preferable to anything else. And thus there will be something
better than a happy life: but what can be more absurd than such an
assertion? What! when they grant vice to be effectual to the rendering
life miserable, must they not admit that there is a corresponding power
in virtue to make life happy? For contraries follow from contraries. And
here I ask what weight they think there is in the balance of Critolaus,
who having put the goods of the mind into one scale, and the goods of
the body and other external advantages into the other, thought the goods
of the mind outweighed the others so far that they would require the
whole earth and sea to equalize the scale.
182XVIII. What hinders Critolaus, then, or that gravest of philosophers,
Xenocrates (who raises virtue so high, and who lessens and depreciates
everything else), from not only placing a happy life, but the happiest
possible life, in virtue? And, indeed, if this were not the case, virtue
would be absolutely lost. For whoever is subject to grief must
necessarily be subject to fear too, for fear is an uneasy apprehension
of future grief; and whoever is subject to fear is liable to dread,
timidity, consternation, cowardice. Therefore, such a person may, some
time or other, be defeated, and not think himself concerned with that
precept of Atreus,
And let men so conduct themselves in life,
As to be always strangers to defeat.
But such a man, as I have said, will be defeated; and not only defeated,
but made a slave of. But we would have virtue always free, always
invincible; and were it not so, there would be an end of virtue. But if
virtue has in herself all that is necessary for a good life, she is
certainly sufficient for happiness: virtue is certainly sufficient, too,
for our living with courage; if with courage, then with a magnanimous
spirit, and indeed so as never to be under any fear, and thus to be
always invincible. Hence it follows that there can be nothing to be
repented of, no wants, no lets or hinderances. Thus all things will be
prosperous, perfect, and as you would have them, and, consequently,
happy; but virtue is sufficient for living with courage, and therefore
virtue is able by herself to make life happy. For as folly, even when
possessed of what it desires, never thinks it has acquired enough, so
wisdom is always satisfied with the present, and never repents on her
own account.
XIX. Look but on the single consulship of Lælius, and that, too, after
having been set aside (though when a wise and good man like him is
outvoted, the people are disappointed of a good consul, rather than be
disappointed by a vain people); but the point is, would you prefer, were
it in your power, to be once such a consul as Lælius, or be elected four
times, like Cinna? I have no doubt in the world what answer you will
make, and it is on that account I put the question to you.
183I would not ask every one this question; for some one perhaps might
answer that he would not only prefer four consulates to one, but even
one day of Cinna’s life to whole ages of many famous men. Lælius would
have suffered had he but touched any one with his finger; but Cinna
ordered the head of his colleague consul, Cn. Octavius, to be struck
off; and put to death P. Crassus58, and L. Cæsar59, those excellent
men, so renowned both at home and abroad; and even M. Antonius60, the
greatest orator whom I ever heard; and C. Cæsar, who seems to me to have
been the pattern of humanity, politeness, sweetness of temper, and wit.
Could he, then, be happy who occasioned the death of these men? So far
from it, that he seems to be miserable, not only for having performed
these actions, but also for acting in such a manner that it was lawful
for him to do it, though it is unlawful for any one to do wicked
actions; but this proceeds from inaccuracy, of speech, for we call
whatever a man is allowed to do lawful. Was not Marius happier, I pray
you, when he shared the glory of the victory gained over the Cimbrians
with his colleague Catulus (who was almost another Lælius; for I look
upon the two men as very like one another), than when, conqueror in the
civil war, he in a passion answered the friends of Catulus, who were
interceding for him, “Let him die?” And this answer he gave, not once
only, but often. But in such a case, he was happier who submitted to
that barbarous decree than he who issued it. And it is better to receive
an injury than to do one; and so it was better to advance a little to
meet that death that was making its approaches, as Catulus did, than,
like Marius, to sully the glory of six consulships, and disgrace his
latter days, by the death of such a man.
XX. Dionysius exercised his tyranny over the Syracusans thirty-eight
years, being but twenty-five years old 184when he seized on the
government. How beautiful and how wealthy a city did he oppress with
slavery! And yet we have it from good authority that he was remarkably
temperate in his manner of living, that he was very active and energetic
in carrying on business, but naturally mischievous and unjust; from
which description every one who diligently inquires into truth must
inevitably see that he was very miserable. Neither did he attain what he
so greatly desired, even when he was persuaded that he had unlimited
power; for, notwithstanding he was of a good family and reputable
parents (though that is contested by some authors), and had a very large
acquaintance of intimate friends and relations, and also some youths
attached to him by ties of love after the fashion of the Greeks, he
could not trust any one of them, but committed the guard of his person
to slaves, whom he had selected from rich men’s families and made free,
and to strangers and barbarians. And thus, through an unjust desire of
governing, he in a manner shut himself up in a prison. Besides, he would
not trust his throat to a barber, but had his daughters taught to shave;
so that these royal virgins were forced to descend to the base and
slavish employment of shaving the head and beard of their father. Nor
would he trust even them, when they were grown up, with a razor; but
contrived how they might burn off the hair of his head and beard with
red-hot nutshells. And as to his two wives, Aristomache, his
countrywoman, and Doris of Locris, he never visited them at night before
everything had been well searched and examined. And as he had surrounded
the place where his bed was with a broad ditch, and made a way over it
with a wooden bridge, he drew that bridge over after shutting his
bedchamber door. And as he did not dare to stand on the ordinary pulpits
from which they usually harangued the people, he generally addressed
them from a high tower. And it is said that when he was disposed to play
at ball—for he delighted much in it—and had pulled off his clothes, he
used to give his sword into the keeping of a young man whom he was very
fond of. On this, one of his intimates said pleasantly, “You certainly
trust your life with him;” and as the young man happened to smile at
this, he ordered them both to be slain, 185the one for showing how he
might be taken off, the other for approving of what had been said by
smiling. But he was so concerned at what he had done that nothing
affected him more during his whole life; for he had slain one to whom he
was extremely partial. Thus do weak men’s desires pull them different
ways, and while they indulge one, they act counter to another.
XXI. This tyrant, however, showed himself how happy he really was; for
once, when Damocles, one of his flatterers, was dilating in conversation
on his forces, his wealth, the greatness of his power, the plenty he
enjoyed, the grandeur of his royal palaces, and maintaining that no one
was ever happier, “Have you an inclination,” said he, “Damocles, as this
kind of life pleases you, to have a taste of it yourself, and to make a
trial of the good fortune that attends me?” And when he said that he
should like it extremely, Dionysius ordered him to be laid on a bed of
gold with the most beautiful covering, embroidered and wrought with the
most exquisite work, and he dressed out a great many sideboards with
silver and embossed gold. He then ordered some youths, distinguished for
their handsome persons, to wait at his table, and to observe his nod, in
order to serve him with what he wanted. There were ointments and
garlands; perfumes were burned; tables provided with the most exquisite
meats. Damocles thought himself very happy. In the midst of this
apparatus, Dionysius ordered a bright sword to be let down from the
ceiling, suspended by a single horse-hair, so as to hang over the head
of that happy man. After which he neither cast his eye on those handsome
waiters, nor on the well-wrought plate; nor touched any of the
provisions: presently the garlands fell to pieces. At last he entreated
the tyrant to give him leave to go, for that now he had no desire to be
happy61. Does not Dionysius, then, seem to have declared there can be
no happiness for one who is under constant apprehensions? But it was not
now in his power 186to return to justice, and restore his citizens their
rights and privileges; for, by the indiscretion of youth, he had engaged
in so many wrong steps and committed such extravagances, that, had he
attempted to have returned to a right way of thinking, he must have
endangered his life.
XXII. Yet, how desirous he was of friendship, though at the same time he
dreaded the treachery of friends, appears from the story of those two
Pythagoreans: one of these had been security for his friend, who was
condemned to die; the other, to release his security, presented himself
at the time appointed for his dying: “I wish,” said Dionysius,“ you
would admit me as the third in your friendship.” What misery was it for
him to be deprived of acquaintance, of company at his table, and of the
freedom of conversation! especially for one who was a man of learning,
and from his childhood acquainted with liberal arts, very fond of music,
and himself a tragic poet—how good a one is not to the purpose, for I
know not how it is, but in this way, more than any other, every one
thinks his own performances excellent. I never as yet knew any poet (and
I was very intimate with Aquinius), who did not appear to himself to be
very admirable. The case is this: you are pleased with your own works; I
like mine. But to return to Dionysius. He debarred himself from all
civil and polite conversation, and spent his life among fugitives,
bondmen, and barbarians; for he was persuaded that no one could be his
friend who was worthy of liberty, or had the least desire of being free.
XXIII. Shall I not, then, prefer the life of Plato and Archytas,
manifestly wise and learned men, to his, than which nothing can possibly
be more horrid, or miserable, or detestable?
I will present you with an humble and obscure mathematician of the same
city, called Archimedes, who lived many years after; whose tomb,
overgrown with shrubs and briers, I in my quæstorship discovered, when
the Syracusans knew nothing of it, and even denied that there was any
such thing remaining; for I remembered some verses, which I had been
informed were engraved on his monument, and these set forth that on the
top of the tomb 187there was placed a sphere with a cylinder. When I had
carefully examined all the monuments (for there are a great many tombs
at the gate Achradinæ), I observed a small column standing out a little
above the briers, with the figure of a sphere and a cylinder upon it;
whereupon I immediately said to the Syracusans—for there were some of
their principal men with me there—that I imagined that was what I was
inquiring for. Several men, being sent in with scythes, cleared the way,
and made an opening for us. When we could get at it, and were come near
to the front of the pedestal, I found the inscription, though the latter
parts of all the verses were effaced almost half away. Thus one of the
noblest cities of Greece, and one which at one time likewise had been
very celebrated for learning, had known nothing of the monument of its
greatest genius, if it had not been discovered to them by a native of
Arpinum. But to return to the subject from which I have been digressing.
Who is there in the least degree acquainted with the Muses, that is,
with liberal knowledge, or that deals at all in learning, who would not
choose to be this mathematician rather than that tyrant? If we look into
their methods of living and their employments, we shall find the mind of
the one strengthened and improved with tracing the deductions of reason,
amused with his own ingenuity, which is the one most delicious food of
the mind; the thoughts of the other engaged in continual murders and
injuries, in constant fears by night and by day. Now imagine a
Democritus, a Pythagoras, and an Anaxagoras; what kingdom, what riches,
would you prefer to their studies and amusements? For you must
necessarily look for that excellence which we are seeking for in that
which is the most perfect part of man; but what is there better in man
than a sagacious and good mind? The enjoyment, therefore, of that good
which proceeds from that sagacious mind can alone make us happy; but
virtue is the good of the mind: it follows, therefore, that a happy life
depends on virtue. Hence proceed all things that are beautiful,
honorable, and excellent, as I said above (but this point must, I think,
be treated of more at large), and they are well stored with joys. For,
as it is clear that a happy life consists in perpetual and unexhausted
188pleasures, it follows, too, that a happy life must arise from honesty.
XXIV. But that what I propose to demonstrate to you may not rest on mere
words only, I must set before you the picture of something, as it were,
living and moving in the world, that may dispose us more for the
improvement of the understanding and real knowledge. Let us, then, pitch
upon some man perfectly acquainted with the most excellent arts; let us
present him for awhile to our own thoughts, and figure him to our own
imaginations. In the first place, he must necessarily be of an
extraordinary capacity; for virtue is not easily connected with dull
minds. Secondly, he must have a great desire of discovering truth, from
whence will arise that threefold production of the mind; one of which
depends on knowing things, and explaining nature; the other, in defining
what we ought to desire and what to avoid; the third, in judging of
consequences and impossibilities, in which consists both subtlety in
disputing and also clearness of judgment. Now, with what pleasure must
the mind of a wise man be affected which continually dwells in the midst
of such cares and occupations as these, when he views the revolutions
and motions of the whole world, and sees those innumerable stars in the
heavens, which, though fixed in their places, have yet one motion in
common with the whole universe, and observes the seven other stars, some
higher, some lower, each maintaining their own course, while their
motions, though wandering, have certain defined and appointed spaces to
run through! the sight of which doubtless urged and encouraged those
ancient philosophers to exercise their investigating spirit on many
other things. Hence arose an inquiry after the beginnings, and, as it
were, seeds from which all things were produced and composed; what was
the origin of every kind of thing, whether animate or inanimate,
articulately speaking or mute; what occasioned their beginning and end,
and by what alteration and change one thing was converted into another;
whence the earth originated, and by what weights it was balanced; by
what caverns the seas were supplied; by what gravity all things being
carried down tend always to the middle of the world, which in any round
body is the lowest place.
189XXV. A mind employed on such subjects, and which night and day
contemplates them, contains in itself that precept of the Delphic God,
so as to “know itself,” and to perceive its connection with the divine
reason, from whence it is filled with an insatiable joy. For reflections
on the power and nature of the Gods raise in us a desire of imitating
their eternity. Nor does the mind, that sees the necessary dependences
and connections that one cause has with another, think it possible that
it should be itself confined to the shortness of this life. Those
causes, though they proceed from eternity to eternity, are governed by
reason and understanding. And he who beholds them and examines them, or
rather he whose view takes in all the parts and boundaries of things,
with what tranquillity of mind does he look on all human affairs, and on
all that is nearer him! Hence proceeds the knowledge of virtue; hence
arise the kinds and species of virtues; hence are discovered those
things which nature regards as the bounds and extremities of good and
evil; by this it is discovered to what all duties ought to be referred,
and which is the most eligible manner of life. And when these and
similar points have been investigated, the principal consequence which
is deduced from them, and that which is our main object in this
discussion, is the establishment of the point, that virtue is of itself
sufficient to a happy life.
The third qualification of our wise man is the next to be considered,
which goes through and spreads itself over every part of wisdom; it is
that whereby we define each particular thing, distinguish the genus from
its species, connect consequences, draw just conclusions, and
distinguish truth from falsehood, which is the very art and science of
disputing; which is not only of the greatest use in the examination of
what passes in the world, but is likewise the most rational
entertainment, and that which is most becoming to true wisdom. Such are
its effects in retirement. Now, let our wise man be considered as
protecting the republic; what can be more excellent than such a
character? By his prudence he will discover the true interests of his
fellow-citizens; by his justice he will be prevented from applying what
belongs to the public to his own use; and, in short, he will be ever
governed by all the 190virtues, which are many and various. To these let
us add the advantage of his friendships; in which the learned reckon not
only a natural harmony and agreement of sentiments throughout the
conduct of life, but the utmost pleasure and satisfaction in conversing
and passing our time constantly with one another. What can be wanting to
such a life as this to make it more happy than it is? Fortune herself
must yield to a life stored with such joys. Now, if it be a happiness to
rejoice in such goods of the mind, that is to say, in such virtues, and
if all wise men enjoy thoroughly these pleasures, it must necessarily be
granted that all such are happy.
XXVI. A. What, when in torments and on the rack?
M. Do you imagine I am speaking of him as laid on roses and violets?
Is it allowable even for Epicurus (who only puts on the appearance of
being a philosopher, and who himself assumed that name for himself) to
say (though, as matters stand, I commend him for his saying) that a wise
man might at all times cry out, though he be burned, tortured, cut to
pieces, “How little I regard it!” Shall this be said by one who defines
all evil as pain, and measures every good by pleasure; who could
ridicule whatever we call either honorable or base, and could declare of
us that we were employed about words, and uttering mere empty sounds;
and that nothing is to be regarded by us but as it is perceived to be
smooth or rough by the body? What! shall such a man as this, as I said,
whose understanding is little superior to the beasts’, be at liberty to
forget himself; and not only to despise fortune, when the whole of his
good and evil is in the power of fortune, but to say that he is happy in
the most racking torture, when he had actually declared pain to be not
only the greatest evil, but the only one? Nor did he take any trouble to
provide himself with those remedies which might have enabled him to bear
pain, such as firmness of mind, a shame of doing anything base,
exercise, and the habit of patience, precepts of courage, and a manly
hardiness; but he says that he supports himself on the single
recollection of past pleasures, as if any one, when the weather was so
hot as that he was scarcely able to bear it, should comfort himself by
recollecting that he was once in my country, 191Arpinum, where he was
surrounded on every side by cooling streams. For I do not apprehend how
past pleasures can allay present evils. But when he says that a wise man
is always happy who would have no right to say so if he were consistent
with himself, what may they not do who allow nothing to be desirable,
nothing to be looked on as good but what is honorable? Let, then, the
Peripatetics and Old Academics follow my example, and at length leave
off muttering to themselves; and openly and with a clear voice let them
be bold to say that a happy life may not be inconsistent with the
agonies of Phalaris’s bull.
XXVII. But to dismiss the subtleties of the Stoics, which I am sensible
I have employed more than was necessary, let us admit of three kinds of
goods; and let them really be kinds of goods, provided no regard is had
to the body and to external circumstances, as entitled to the
appellation of good in any other sense than because we are obliged to
use them: but let those other divine goods spread themselves far in
every direction, and reach the very heavens. Why, then, may I not call
him happy, nay, the happiest of men, who has attained them? Shall a wise
man be afraid of pain? which is, indeed, the greatest enemy to our
opinion. For I am persuaded that we are prepared and fortified
sufficiently, by the disputations of the foregoing days, against our own
death or that of our friends, against grief, and the other perturbations
of the mind. But pain seems to be the sharpest adversary of virtue; that
it is which menaces us with burning torches; that it is which threatens
to crush our fortitude, and greatness of mind, and patience. Shall
virtue, then, yield to this? Shall the happy life of a wise and
consistent man succumb to this? Good. Gods! how base would this be!
Spartan boys will bear to have their bodies torn by rods without
uttering a groan. I myself have seen at Lacedæmon troops of young men,
with incredible earnestness contending together with their hands and
feet, with their teeth and nails, nay, even ready to expire, rather than
own themselves conquered. Is any country of barbarians more uncivilized
or desolate than India? Yet they have among them some that are held for
wise men, who never wear any clothes all their life long, and who bear
the 192snow of Caucasus, and the piercing cold of winter, without any
pain; and who if they come in contact with fire endure being burned
without a groan. The women, too, in India, on the death of their
husbands have a regular contest, and apply to the judge to have it
determined which of them was best beloved by him; for it is customary
there for one man to have many wives. She in whose favor it is
determined exults greatly, and being attended by her relations, is laid
on the funeral pile with her husband; the others, who are postponed,
walk away very much dejected. Custom can never be superior to nature,
for nature is never to be got the better of. But our minds are infected
by sloth and idleness, and luxury, and languor, and indolence: we have
enervated them by opinions and bad customs. Who is there who is
unacquainted with the customs of the Egyptians? Their minds being
tainted by pernicious opinions, they are ready to bear any torture
rather than hurt an ibis, a snake, a cat, a dog, or a crocodile; and
should any one inadvertently have hurt any of these animals, he will
submit to any punishment. I am speaking of men only. As to the beasts,
do they not bear cold and hunger, running about in woods, and on
mountains and deserts? Will they not fight for their young ones till
they are wounded? Are they afraid of any attacks or blows? I mention not
what the ambitious will suffer for honor’s sake, or those who are
desirous of praise on account of glory, or lovers to gratify their lust.
Life is full of such instances.
XXVIII. But let us not dwell too much on these questions, but rather let
us return to our subject. I say, and say again, that happiness will
submit even to be tormented; and that in pursuit of justice, and
temperance, and still more especially and principally fortitude, and
greatness of soul, and patience, it will not stop short at sight of the
executioner; and when all other virtues proceed calmly to the torture,
that one will never halt, as I said, on the outside and threshold of the
prison; for what can be baser, what can carry a worse appearance, than
to be left alone, separated from those beautiful attendants? Not,
however, that this is by any means possible; for neither can the virtues
hold together without happiness, nor happiness 193without the virtues; so
that they will not suffer her to desert them, but will carry her along
with them, to whatever torments, to whatever pain they are led. For it
is the peculiar quality of a wise man to do nothing that he may repent
of, nothing against his inclination, but always to act nobly, with
constancy, gravity, and honesty; to depend on nothing as certainty; to
wonder at nothing, when it falls out, as if it appeared strange and
unexpected to him; to be independent of every one, and abide by his own
opinion. For my part, I cannot form an idea of anything happier than
this. The conclusion of the Stoics is indeed easy; for since they are
persuaded that the end of good is to live agreeably to nature, and to be
consistent with that—as a wise man should do so, not only because it is
his duty, but because it is in his power—it must, of course, follow
that whoever has the chief good in his power has his happiness so too.
And thus the life of a wise man is always happy. You have here what I
think may be confidently said of a happy life; and as things now stand,
very truly also, unless you can advance something better.
XXIX. A. Indeed I cannot; but I should be glad to prevail on you,
unless it is troublesome (as you are under no confinement from
obligations to any particular sect, but gather from all of them whatever
strikes you most as having the appearance of probability), as you just
now seemed to advise the Peripatetics and the Old Academy boldly to
speak out without reserve, “that wise men are always the happiest”—I
should be glad to hear how you think it consistent for them to say so,
when you have said so much against that opinion, and the conclusions of
the Stoics.
M. I will make use, then, of that liberty which no one has the
privilege of using in philosophy but those of our school, whose
discourses determine nothing, but take in everything, leaving them
unsupported by the authority of any particular person, to be judged of
by others, according to their weight. And as you seem desirous of
knowing how it is that, notwithstanding the different opinions of
philosophers with regard to the ends of goods, virtue has still
sufficient security for the effecting of a happy life—which security,
as we are informed, Carneades used indeed to dispute against; but he
disputed as against the 194Stoics, whose opinions he combated with great
zeal and vehemence. I, however, shall handle the question with more
temper; for if the Stoics have rightly settled the ends of goods, the
affair is at an end; for a wise man must necessarily be always happy.
But let us examine, if we can, the particular opinions of the others,
that so this excellent decision, if I may so call it, in favor of a
happy life, may be agreeable to the opinions and discipline of all.
XXX. These, then, are the opinions, as I think, that are held and
defended—the first four are simple ones: “that nothing is good but what
is honest,” according to the Stoics; “nothing good but pleasure,” as
Epicurus maintains; “nothing good but a freedom from pain,” as
Hieronymus62 asserts; “nothing good but an enjoyment of the principal,
or all, or the greatest goods of nature,” as Carneades maintained
against the Stoics—these are simple, the others are mixed propositions.
Then there are three kinds of goods: the greatest being those of the
mind; the next best those of the body; the third are external goods, as
the Peripatetics call them, and the Old Academics differ very little
from them. Dinomachus63 and Callipho64 have coupled pleasure with
honesty; but Diodorus65 the Peripatetic has joined indolence to
honesty. These are the opinions that have some footing; for those of
Aristo,66 Pyrrho,67 Herillus,68 and of some others, are quite out
of date. Now let us see what weight these men have in 195them, excepting the
Stoics, whose opinion I think I have sufficiently defended; and indeed I
have explained what the Peripatetics have to say; excepting that
Theophrastus, and those who followed him, dread and abhor pain in too
weak a manner. The others may go on to exaggerate the gravity and
dignity of virtue, as usual; and then, after they have extolled it to
the skies, with the usual extravagance of good orators, it is easy to
reduce the other topics to nothing by comparison, and to hold them up to
contempt. They who think that praise deserves to be sought after, even
at the expense of pain, are not at liberty to deny those men to be happy
who have obtained it. Though they may be under some evils, yet this name
of happy has a very wide application.
XXXI. For even as trading is said to be lucrative, and farming
advantageous, not because the one never meets with any loss, nor the
other with any damage from the inclemency of the weather, but because
they succeed in general; so life may be properly called happy, not from
its being entirely made up of good things, but because it abounds with
these to a great and considerable degree. By this way of reasoning,
then, a happy life may attend virtue even to the moment of execution;
nay, may descend with her into Phalaris’s bull, according to Aristotle,
Xenocrates, Speusippus, Polemon; and will not be gained over by any
allurements to forsake her. Of the same opinion will Calliphon and
Diodorus be; for they are both of them such friends to virtue as to
think that all things should be discarded and far removed that are
incompatible with it. The rest seem to be more hampered with these
doctrines, but yet they get clear of them; such as Epicurus, Hieronymus,
and whoever else thinks it worth while to defend the deserted Carneades:
for there is not one of them who does not think the mind to be judge of
those goods, and able sufficiently to instruct him how to despise what
has the appearance only of good or evil. For what seems to you to be the
case with Epicurus is the case also with Hieronymus and Carneades, and,
indeed, with all the rest of them; for who is there who is not
sufficiently prepared against death and pain? I will begin, with your
leave, with him whom we call soft and voluptuous. What! 196does he seem,
to you to be afraid of death or pain when he calls the day of his death
happy; and who, when he is afflicted by the greatest pains, silences
them all by recollecting arguments of his own discovering? And this is
not done in such a manner as to give room for imagining that he talks
thus wildly from some sudden impulse; but his opinion of death is, that
on the dissolution of the animal all sense is lost; and what is deprived
of sense is, as he thinks, what we have no concern at all with. And as
to pain, too, he has certain rules to follow then: if it be great, the
comfort is that it must be short; if it be of long continuance, then it
must be supportable. What, then? Do those grandiloquent gentlemen state
anything better than Epicurus in opposition to these two things which
distress us the most? And as to other things, do not Epicurus and the
rest of the philosophers seem sufficiently prepared? Who is there who
does not dread poverty? And yet no true philosopher ever can dread it.
XXXII. But with how little is this man himself satisfied! No one has
said more on frugality. For when a man is far removed from those things
which occasion a desire of money, from love, ambition, or other daily
extravagance, why should he be fond of money, or concern himself at all
about it? Could the Scythian Anacharsis69 disregard money, and shall
not our philosophers be able to do so? We are informed of an epistle of
his in these words: “Anacharsis to Hanno, greeting. My clothing is the
same as that with which the Scythians cover themselves; the hardness of
my feet supplies the want of shoes; the ground is my bed, hunger my
sauce, my food milk, cheese, and flesh. So you may come to me as to a
man in want of nothing. But as to those presents you take so much
pleasure in, you may dispose of them to your own citizens, or to the
immortal Gods.” And almost all philosophers, of all schools, excepting
those who are warped 197from right reason by a vicious disposition, might
have been of this same opinion. Socrates, when on one occasion he saw a
great quantity of gold and silver carried in a procession, cried out,
“How many things are there which I do not want!” Xenocrates, when some
ambassadors from Alexander had brought him fifty talents, which was a
very large sum of money in those times, especially at Athens, carried
the ambassadors to sup in the Academy, and placed just a sufficiency
before them, without any apparatus. When they asked him, the next day,
to whom he wished the money which they had for him to be paid: “What!”
said he, “did you not perceive by our slight repast of yesterday that I
had no occasion for money?” But when he perceived that they were
somewhat dejected, he accepted of thirty minas, that he might not seem
to treat with disrespect the king’s generosity. But Diogenes took a
greater liberty, like a Cynic, when Alexander asked him if he wanted
anything: “Just at present,” said he, “I wish that you would stand a
little out of the line between me and the sun,” for Alexander was
hindering him from sunning himself. And, indeed, this very man used to
maintain how much he surpassed the Persian king in his manner of life
and fortune; for that he himself was in want of nothing, while the other
never had enough; and that he had no inclination for those pleasures of
which the other could never get enough to satisfy himself; and that the
other could never obtain his.
XXXIII. You see, I imagine, how Epicurus has divided his kinds of
desires, not very acutely perhaps, but yet usefully: saying that they
are “partly natural and necessary; partly natural, but not necessary;
partly neither. That those which are necessary may be supplied almost
for nothing; for that the things which nature requires are easily
obtained.” As to the second kind of desires, his opinion is that any one
may easily either enjoy or go without them. And with regard to the
third, since they are utterly frivolous, being neither allied to
necessity nor nature, he thinks that they should be entirely rooted out.
On this topic a great many arguments are adduced by the Epicureans; and
those pleasures which they do not despise in a body, they disparage one
by one, and seem rather 198for lessening the number of them; for as to
wanton pleasures, on which subject they say a great deal, these, say
they, are easy, common, and within any one’s reach; and they think that
if nature requires them, they are not to be estimated by birth,
condition, or rank, but by shape, age, and person: and that it is by no
means difficult to refrain from them, should health, duty, or reputation
require it; but that pleasures of this kind may be desirable, where they
are attended with no inconvenience, but can never be of any use. And the
assertions which Epicurus makes with respect to the whole of pleasure
are such as show his opinion to be that pleasure is always desirable,
and to be pursued merely because it is pleasure; and for the same reason
pain is to be avoided, because it is pain. So that a wise man will
always adopt such a system of counterbalancing as to do himself the
justice to avoid pleasure, should pain ensue from it in too great a
proportion; and will submit to pain, provided the effects of it are to
produce a greater pleasure: so that all pleasurable things, though the
corporeal senses are the judges of them, are still to be referred to the
mind, on which account the body rejoices while it perceives a present
pleasure; but that the mind not only perceives the present as well as
the body, but foresees it while it is coming, and even when it is past
will not let it quite slip away. So that a wise man enjoys a continual
series of pleasures, uniting the expectation of future pleasure to the
recollection of what he has already tasted. The like notions are applied
by them to high living; and the magnificence and expensiveness of
entertainments are deprecated, because nature is satisfied at a small
expense.
XXXIV. For who does not see this, that an appetite is the best sauce?
When Darius, in his flight from the enemy, had drunk some water which
was muddy and tainted with dead bodies, he declared that he had never
drunk anything more pleasant; the fact was, that he had never drunk
before when he was thirsty. Nor had Ptolemy ever eaten when he was
hungry; for as he was travelling over Egypt, his company not keeping up
with him, he had some coarse bread presented him in a cottage, upon
which he said, “Nothing ever seemed to him pleasanter 199than that bread.”
They relate, too, of Socrates, that, once when he was walking very fast
till the evening, on his being asked why he did so, his reply was that
he was purchasing an appetite by walking, that he might sup the better.
And do we not see what the Lacedæmonians provide in their Phiditia?
where the tyrant Dionysius supped, but told them he did not at all like
that black broth, which was their principal dish; on which he who
dressed it said, “It was no wonder, for it wanted seasoning.” Dionysius
asked what that seasoning was; to which it was replied, “Fatigue in
hunting, sweating, a race on the banks of Eurotas, hunger and thirst,”
for these are the seasonings to the Lacedæmonian banquets. And this may
not only be conceived from the custom of men, but from the beasts, who
are satisfied with anything that is thrown before them, provided it is
not unnatural, and they seek no farther. Some entire cities, taught by
custom, delight in parsimony, as I said but just now of the
Lacedæmonians. Xenophon has given an account of the Persian diet, who
never, as he saith, use anything but cresses with their bread; not but
that, should nature require anything more agreeable, many things might
be easily supplied by the ground, and plants in great abundance, and of
incomparable sweetness. Add to this strength and health, as the
consequence of this abstemious way of living. Now, compare with this
those who sweat and belch, being crammed with eating, like fatted oxen;
then will you perceive that they who pursue pleasure most attain it
least; and that the pleasure of eating lies not in satiety, but
appetite.
XXXV. They report of Timotheus, a famous man at Athens, and the head of
the city, that having supped with Plato, and being extremely delighted
with his entertainment, on seeing him the next day, he said, “Your
suppers are not only agreeable while I partake of them, but the next day
also.” Besides, the understanding is impaired when we are full with
overeating and drinking. There is an excellent epistle of Plato to
Dion’s relations, in which there occurs as nearly as possible these
words: “When I came there, that happy life so much talked of, devoted to
Italian and Syracusan entertainments, was noways agreeable to me; to be
crammed twice a day, and never to 200have the night to yourself, and the
other things which are the accompaniments of this kind of life, by which
a man will never be made the wiser, but will be rendered much less
temperate; for it must be an extraordinary disposition that can be
temperate in such circumstances.” How, then, can a life be pleasant
without prudence and temperance? Hence you discover the mistake of
Sardanapalus, the wealthiest king of the Assyrians, who ordered it to be
engraved on his tomb,
I still have what in food I did exhaust;
But what I left, though excellent, is lost.
“What less than this,” says Aristotle, “could be inscribed on the tomb,
not of a king, but an ox?” He said that he possessed those things when
dead, which, in his lifetime, he could have no longer than while he was
enjoying them. Why, then, are riches desired? And wherein doth poverty
prevent us from being happy? In the want, I imagine, of statues,
pictures, and diversions. But if any one is delighted with these things,
have not the poor people the enjoyment of them more than they who are
the owners of them in the greatest abundance? For we have great numbers
of them displayed publicly in our city. And whatever store of them
private people have, they cannot have a great number, and they but
seldom see them, only when they go to their country seats; and some of
them must be stung to the heart when they consider how they came by
them. The day would fail me, should I be inclined to defend the cause of
poverty. The thing is manifest; and nature daily informs us how few
things there are, and how trifling they are, of which she really stands
in need.
XXXVI. Let us inquire, then, if obscurity, the want of power, or even
the being unpopular, can prevent a wise man from being happy. Observe if
popular favor, and this glory which they are so fond of, be not attended
with more uneasiness than pleasure. Our friend Demosthenes was certainly
very weak in declaring himself pleased with the whisper of a woman who
was carrying water, as is the custom in Greece, and who whispered to
another, “That is he—that is Demosthenes.” What could be weaker than
201this? and yet what an orator he was! But although he had learned to
speak to others, he had conversed but little with himself. We may
perceive, therefore, that popular glory is not desirable of itself; nor
is obscurity to be dreaded. “I came to Athens,” saith Democritus, “and
there was no one there that knew me:” this was a moderate and grave man
who could glory in his obscurity. Shall musicians compose their tunes to
their own tastes? and shall a philosopher, master of a much better art,
seek to ascertain, not what is most true, but what will please the
people? Can anything be more absurd than to despise the vulgar as mere
unpolished mechanics, taken singly, and to think them of consequence
when collected into a body? These wise men would contemn our ambitious
pursuits and our vanities, and would reject all the honors which the
people could voluntarily offer to them; but we know not how to despise
them till we begin to repent of having accepted them. There is an
anecdote related by Heraclitus, the natural philosopher, of Hermodorus,
the chief of the Ephesians, that he said “that all the Ephesians ought
to be punished with death for saying, when they had expelled Hermodorus
out of their city, that they would have no one among them better than
another; but that if there were any such, he might go elsewhere to some
other people.” Is not this the case with the people everywhere? Do they
not hate every virtue that distinguishes itself? What! was not Aristides
(I had rather instance in the Greeks than ourselves) banished his
country for being eminently just? What troubles, then, are they free
from who have no connection whatever with the people? What is more
agreeable than a learned retirement? I speak of that learning which
makes us acquainted with the boundless extent of nature and the
universe, and which even while we remain in this world discovers to us
both heaven, earth, and sea.
XXXVII. If, then, honor and riches have no value, what is there else to
be afraid of? Banishment, I suppose; which is looked on as the greatest
evil. Now, if the evil of banishment proceeds not from ourselves, but
from the froward disposition of the people, I have just now declared how
contemptible it is. But if to leave one’s country be miserable,
202the
provinces are full of miserable men, very few of the settlers in which
ever return to their country again. But exiles are deprived of their
property! What, then! has there not been enough said on bearing poverty?
But with regard to banishment, if we examine the nature of things, not
the ignominy of the name, how little does it differ from constant
travelling! in which some of the most famous philosophers have spent
their whole life, as Xenocrates, Crantor, Arcesilas, Lacydes, Aristotle,
Theophrastus, Zeno, Cleanthes, Chrysippus, Antipater, Carneades,
Panætius, Clitomachus, Philo, Antiochus, Posidonius, and innumerable
others, who from their first setting-out never returned home again.
Now, what ignominy can a wise man be affected with (for it is of such a
one that I am speaking) who can be guilty of nothing which deserves it?
for there is no occasion to comfort one who is banished for his deserts.
Lastly, they can easily reconcile themselves to every accident who
measure all their objects and pursuits in life by the standard of
pleasure; so that in whatever place that is supplied, there they may
live happily. Thus what Teucer said may be applied to every case:
“Wherever I am happy is my country.”
Socrates, indeed, when he was asked where he belonged to, replied, “The
world;” for he looked upon himself as a citizen and inhabitant of the
whole world. How was it with T. Altibutius? Did he not follow his
philosophical studies with the greatest satisfaction at Athens, although
he was banished? which, however, would not have happened to him if he
had obeyed the laws of Epicurus and lived peaceably in the republic. In
what was Epicurus happier, living in his own country, than Metrodorus,
who lived at Athens? Or did Plato’s happiness exceed that of Xenocrates,
or Polemo, or Arcesilas? Or is that city to be valued much that banishes
all her good and wise men? Demaratus, the father of our King Tarquin,
not being able to bear the tyrant Cypselus, fled from Corinth to
Tarquinii, settled there, and had children. Was it, then, an unwise act
in him to prefer the liberty of banishment to slavery at home?
XXXVIII. Besides the emotions of the mind, all griefs
203and anxieties are
assuaged by forgetting them, and turning our thoughts to pleasure.
Therefore, it was not without reason that Epicurus presumed to say that
a wise man abounds with good things, because he may always have his
pleasures; from whence it follows, as he thinks, that that point is
gained which is the subject of our present inquiry, that a wise man is
always happy. What! though he should be deprived of the senses of seeing
and hearing? Yes; for he holds those things very cheap. For, in the
first place, what are the pleasures of which we are deprived by that
dreadful thing, blindness? For though they allow other pleasures to be
confined to the senses, yet the things which are perceived by the sight
do not depend wholly on the pleasure the eyes receive; as is the case
when we taste, smell, touch, or hear; for, in respect of all these
senses, the organs themselves are the seat of pleasure; but it is not so
with the eyes. For it is the mind which is entertained by what we see;
but the mind may be entertained in many ways, even though we could not
see at all. I am speaking of a learned and a wise man, with whom to
think is to live. But thinking in the case of a wise man does not
altogether require the use of his eyes in his investigations; for if
night does not strip him of his happiness, why should blindness, which
resembles night, have that effect? For the reply of Antipater the
Cyrenaic to some women who bewailed his being blind, though it is a
little too obscene, is not without its significance. “What do you mean?”
saith he; “do you think the night can furnish no pleasure?” And we find
by his magistracies and his actions that old Appius,
70 too, who was
blind for many years, was not prevented from doing whatever was required
of him with respect either to the republic or his own affairs. It is
said that C. Drusus’s house was crowded with clients. When they whose
business it was could not see how to conduct themselves, they applied to
a blind guide.
XXXIX. When I was a boy, Cn. Aufidius, a blind man,
204who had served the
office of prætor, not only gave his opinion in the Senate, and was ready
to assist his friends, but wrote a Greek history, and had a considerable
acquaintance with literature. Diodorus the Stoic was blind, and lived
many years at my house. He, indeed, which is scarcely credible, besides
applying himself more than usual to philosophy, and playing on the
flute, agreeably to the custom of the Pythagoreans, and having books
read to him night and day, in all which he did not want eyes, contrived
to teach geometry, which, one would think, could hardly be done without
the assistance of eyes, telling his scholars how and where to draw every
line. They relate of Asclepiades, a native of Eretria, and no obscure
philosopher, when some one asked him what inconvenience he suffered from
his blindness, that his reply was, “He was at the expense of another
servant.” So that, as the most extreme poverty may be borne if you
please, as is daily the case with some in Greece, so blindness may
easily be borne, provided you have the support of good health in other
respects. Democritus was so blind he could not distinguish white from
black; but he knew the difference between good and evil, just and
unjust, honorable and base, the useful and useless, great and small.
Thus one may live happily without distinguishing colors; but without
acquainting yourself with things, you cannot; and this man was of
opinion that the intense application of the mind was taken off by the
objects that presented themselves to the eye; and while others often
could not see what was before their feet, he travelled through all
infinity. It is reported also that Homer
71 was blind, but we observe
205his painting as well as his poetry. What country, what coast, what part
of Greece, what military attacks, what dispositions of battle, what
array, what ship, what motions of men and animals, can be mentioned
which he has not described in such a manner as to enable us to see what
he could not see himself? What, then! can we imagine that Homer, or any
other learned man, has ever been in want of pleasure and entertainment
for his mind? Were it not so, would Anaxagoras, or this very Democritus,
have left their estates and patrimonies, and given themselves up to the
pursuit of acquiring this divine pleasure? It is thus that the poets who
have represented Tiresias the Augur as a wise man and blind never
exhibit him as bewailing his blindness. And Homer, too, after he had
described Polyphemus as a monster and a wild man, represents him talking
with his ram, and speaking of his good fortune, inasmuch as he could go
wherever he pleased and touch what he would. And so far he was right,
for that Cyclops was a being of not much more understanding than his
ram.
XL. Now, as to the evil of being deaf. M. Crassus was a little thick of
hearing; but it was more uneasiness to him that he heard himself ill
spoken of, though, in my opinion, he did not deserve it. Our Epicureans
cannot understand Greek, nor the Greeks Latin: now, they are deaf
reciprocally as to each other’s language, and we are all truly deaf with
regard to those innumerable languages which we do not understand. They
do not hear the voice of the harper; but, then, they do not hear the
grating of a saw when it is setting, or the grunting of a hog when his
206throat is being cut, nor the roaring of the sea when they are desirous
of rest. And if they should chance to be fond of singing, they ought, in
the first place, to consider that many wise men lived happily before
music was discovered; besides, they may have more pleasure in reading
verses than in hearing them sung. Then, as I before referred the blind
to the pleasures of hearing, so I may the deaf to the pleasures of
sight: moreover, whoever can converse with himself doth not need the
conversation of another. But suppose all these misfortunes to meet in
one person: suppose him blind and deaf—let him be afflicted with the
sharpest pains of body, which, in the first place, generally of
themselves make an end of him; still, should they continue so long, and
the pain be so exquisite, that we should be unable to assign any reason
for our being so afflicted—still, why, good Gods! should we be under
any difficulty? For there is a retreat at hand: death is that retreat—a
shelter where we shall forever be insensible. Theodorus said to
Lysimachus, who threatened him with death, “It is a great matter,
indeed, for you to have acquired the power of a Spanish fly!” When
Perses entreated Paulus not to lead him in triumph, “That is a matter
which you have in your own power,” said Paulus. I said many things about
death in our first day’s disputation, when death was the subject; and
not a little the next day, when I treated of pain; which things if you
recollect, there can be no danger of your looking upon death as
undesirable, or, at least, it will not be dreadful.
That custom which is common among the Grecians at their banquets should,
in my opinion, be observed in life: Drink, say they, or leave the
company; and rightly enough; for a guest should either enjoy the
pleasure of drinking with others, or else not stay till he meets with
affronts from those that are in liquor. Thus, those injuries of fortune
which you cannot bear you should flee from.
XLI. This is the very same which is said by Epicurus and Hieronymus.
Now, if those philosophers, whose opinion it is that virtue has no power
of itself, and who say that the conduct which we denominate honorable
and laudable is really nothing, and is only an empty circumstance
207set
off with an unmeaning sound, can nevertheless maintain that a wise man
is always happy, what, think you, may be done by the Socratic and
Platonic philosophers? Some of these allow such superiority to the goods
of the mind as quite to eclipse what concerns the body and all external
circumstances. But others do not admit these to be goods; they make
everything depend on the mind: whose disputes Carneades used, as a sort
of honorary arbitrator, to determine. For, as what seemed goods to the
Peripatetics were allowed to be advantages by the Stoics, and as the
Peripatetics allowed no more to riches, good health; and other things of
that sort than the Stoics, when these things were considered according
to their reality, and not by mere names, his opinion was that there was
no ground for disagreeing. Therefore, let the philosophers of other
schools see how they can establish this point also. It is very agreeable
to me that they make some professions worthy of being uttered by the
mouth of a philosopher with regard to a wise man’s having always the
means of living happily.
XLII. But as we are to depart in the morning, let us remember these five
days’ discussions; though, indeed, I think I shall commit them to
writing: for how can I better employ the leisure which I have, of
whatever kind it is, and whatever it be owing to? And I will send these
five books also to my friend Brutus, by whom I was not only incited to
write on philosophy, but, I may say, provoked. And by so doing it is not
easy to say what service I may be of to others. At all events, in my own
various and acute afflictions, which surround me on all sides, I cannot
find any better comfort for myself.
209THE NATURE OF THE GODS.
BOOK I.
I.
There are many things in philosophy, my dear Brutus, which are not as
yet fully explained to us, and particularly (as you very well know) that
most obscure and difficult question concerning the Nature of the Gods,
so extremely necessary both towards a knowledge of the human mind and
the practice of true religion: concerning which the opinions of men are
so various, and so different from each other, as to lead strongly to the
inference that ignorance
72 is the cause, or origin, of philosophy, and
that the Academic philosophers have been prudent in refusing their
assent to things uncertain: for what is more unbecoming to a wise man
than to judge rashly? or what rashness is so unworthy of the gravity and
stability of a philosopher as either to maintain false opinions, or,
without the least hesitation, to support and defend what he has not
thoroughly examined and does not clearly comprehend?
In the question now before us, the greater part of mankind have united
to acknowledge that which is most probable, and which we are all by
nature led to suppose, namely, that there are Gods. Protagoras
73
doubted whether there were any. Diagoras the Melian and Theodorus of
Cyrene entirely believed there were no such beings. But they who have
affirmed that there are Gods, have expressed such a variety of
sentiments on the subject, and the disagreement between them is so
great, that it would be
210tiresome to enumerate their opinions; for they
give us many statements respecting the forms of the Gods, and their
places of abode, and the employment of their lives. And these are
matters on which the philosophers differ with the most exceeding
earnestness. But the most considerable part of the dispute is, whether
they are wholly inactive, totally unemployed, and free from all care and
administration of affairs; or, on the contrary, whether all things were
made and constituted by them from the beginning; and whether they will
continue to be actuated and governed by them to eternity. This is one of
the greatest points in debate; and unless this is decided, mankind must
necessarily remain in the greatest of errors, and ignorant of what is
most important to be known.
II. For there are some philosophers, both ancient and modern, who have
conceived that the Gods take not the least cognizance of human affairs.
But if their doctrine be true, of what avail is piety, sanctity, or
religion? for these are feelings and marks of devotion which are offered
to the Gods by men with uprightness and holiness, on the ground that men
are the objects of the attention of the Gods, and that many benefits are
conferred by the immortal Gods on the human race. But if the Gods have
neither the power nor the inclination to help us; if they take no care
of us, and pay no regard to our actions; and if there is no single
advantage which can possibly accrue to the life of man; then what reason
can we have to pay any adoration, or any honors, or to prefer any
prayers to them? Piety, like the other virtues, cannot have any
connection with vain show or dissimulation; and without piety, neither
sanctity nor religion can be supported; the total subversion of which
must be attended with great confusion and disturbance in life.
I do not even know, if we cast off piety towards the Gods, but that
faith, and all the associations of human life, and that most excellent
of all virtues, justice, may perish with it.
There are other philosophers, and those, too, very great and illustrious
men, who conceive the whole world to be directed and governed by the
will and wisdom of the Gods; nor do they stop here, but conceive
likewise that the Deities
211consult and provide for the preservation of
mankind. For they think that the fruits, and the produce of the earth,
and the seasons, and the variety of weather, and the change of climates,
by which all the productions of the earth are brought to maturity, are
designed by the immortal Gods for the use of man. They instance many
other things, which shall be related in these books; and which would
almost induce us to believe that the immortal Gods had made them all
expressly and solely for the benefit and advantage of men. Against these
opinions Carneades has advanced so much that what he has said should
excite a desire in men who are not naturally slothful to search after
truth; for there is no subject on which the learned as well as the
unlearned differ so strenuously as in this; and since their opinions are
so various, and so repugnant one to another, it is possible that none of
them may be, and absolutely impossible that more than one should be,
right.
III. Now, in a cause like this, I may be able to pacify well-meaning
opposers, and to confute invidious censurers, so as to induce the latter
to repent of their unreasonable contradiction, and the former to be glad
to learn; for they who admonish one in a friendly spirit should be
instructed, they who attack one like enemies should be repelled. But I
observe that the several books which I have lately published
74 have
occasioned much noise and various discourse about them; some people
wondering what the reason has been why I have applied myself so suddenly
to the study of philosophy, and others desirous of knowing what my
opinion is on such subjects. I likewise perceive that many people wonder
at my following that philosophy
75 chiefly which seems to take away the
light, and to bury and envelop things in a kind of artificial night, and
that I should so unexpectedly have taken up the defence of a school that
has been long neglected and forsaken. But it is a mistake to suppose
that this application to philosophical studies has been sudden on my
part. I have applied
212myself to them from my youth, at no small expense
of time and trouble; and I have been in the habit of philosophizing a
great deal when I least seemed to think about it; for the truth of which
I appeal to my orations, which are filled with quotations from
philosophers, and to my intimacy with those very learned men who
frequented my house and conversed daily with me, particularly Diodorus,
Philo, Antiochus, and Posidonius,
76 under whom I was bred; and if all
the precepts of philosophy are to have reference to the conduct of life,
I am inclined to think that I have advanced, both in public and private
affairs, only such principles as may be supported by reason and
authority.
IV. But if any one should ask what has induced me, in the decline of
life, to write on these subjects, nothing is more easily answered; for
when I found myself entirely disengaged from business, and the
commonwealth reduced to the necessity of being governed by the direction
and care of one man,
77 I thought it becoming, for the sake of the
public, to instruct my countrymen in philosophy, and that it would be of
importance, and much to the honor and commendation of our city, to have
such great and excellent subjects introduced in the Latin tongue. I the
less repent of my undertaking, since I plainly see that I have excited
in many a desire, not only of learning, but of writing; for we have had
several Romans well grounded in the learning of the Greeks who were
unable to communicate to their countrymen what they had learned, because
they looked upon it as impossible to express that in Latin which they
had received from the Greeks. In this point I think I have succeeded so
well that what I have done is not, even in copiousness of expression,
inferior to that language.
Another inducement to it was a melancholy disposition of mind, and the
great and heavy oppression of fortune that was upon me; from which, if I
could have found any surer remedy, I would not have sought relief in
this pursuit. But I could procure ease by no means better than by not
only applying myself to books, but by devoting myself
213to the
examination of the whole body of philosophy. And every part and branch
of this is readily discovered when every question is propounded in
writing; for there is such an admirable continuation and series of
things that each seems connected with the other, and all appear linked
together and united.
V. Now, those men who desire to know my own private opinion on every
particular subject have more curiosity than is necessary. For the force
of reason in disputation is to be sought after rather than authority,
since the authority of the teacher is often a disadvantage to those who
are willing to learn; as they refuse to use their own judgment, and rely
implicitly on him whom they make choice of for a preceptor. Nor could I
ever approve this custom of the Pythagoreans, who, when they affirmed
anything in disputation, and were asked why it was so, used to give this
answer: “He himself has said it;” and this “he himself,” it seems, was
Pythagoras. Such was the force of prejudice and opinion that his
authority was to prevail even without argument or reason.
They who wonder at my being a follower of this sect in particular may
find a satisfactory answer in my four books of Academical Questions. But
I deny that I have undertaken the protection of what is neglected and
forsaken; for the opinions of men do not die with them, though they may
perhaps want the author’s explanation. This manner of philosophizing, of
disputing all things and assuming nothing certainly, was begun by
Socrates, revived by Arcesilaus, confirmed by Carneades, and has
descended, with all its power, even to the present age; but I am
informed that it is now almost exploded even in Greece. However, I do
not impute that to any fault in the institution of the Academy, but to
the negligence of mankind. If it is difficult to know all the doctrines
of any one sect, how much more is it to know those of every sect! which,
however, must necessarily be known to those who resolve, for the sake of
discovering truth, to dispute for or against all philosophers without
partiality.
I do not profess myself to be master of this difficult and noble
faculty; but I do assert that I have endeavored to make myself so; and
it is impossible that they who choose
214this manner of philosophizing
should not meet at least with something worthy their pursuit. I have
spoken more fully on this head in another place. But as some are too
slow of apprehension, and some too careless, men stand in perpetual need
of caution. For we are not people who believe that there is nothing
whatever which is true; but we say that some falsehoods are so blended
with all truths, and have so great a resemblance to them, that there is
no certain rule for judging of or assenting to propositions; from which
this maxim also follows, that many things are probable, which, though
they are not evident to the senses, have still so persuasive and
beautiful an aspect that a wise man chooses to direct his conduct by
them.
VI. Now, to free myself from the reproach of partiality, I propose to
lay before you the opinions of various philosophers concerning the
nature of the Gods, by which means all men may judge which of them are
consistent with truth; and if all agree together, or if any one shall be
found to have discovered what may be absolutely called truth, I will
then give up the Academy as vain and arrogant. So I may cry out, in the
words of Statius, in the Synephebi,
Ye Gods, I call upon, require, pray, beseech, entreat, and implore
the attention of my countrymen all, both young and old;
yet not on so trifling an occasion as when the person in the play
complains that,
In this city we have discovered a most flagrant iniquity: here is a
professed courtesan, who refuses money from her lover;
but that they may attend, know, and consider what sentiments they ought
to preserve concerning religion, piety, sanctity, ceremonies, faith,
oaths, temples, shrines, and solemn sacrifices; what they ought to think
of the auspices over which I preside;78 for all these have relation to
the present question. The manifest disagreement among the most learned
on this subject creates doubts in those who imagine they have some
certain knowledge of the subject.
Which fact I have often taken notice of elsewhere, and 215I did so more
especially at the discussion that was held at my friend C. Cotta’s
concerning the immortal Gods, and which was carried on with the greatest
care, accuracy, and precision; for coming to him at the time of the
Latin holidays,79 according to his own invitation and message from
him, I found him sitting in his study,80 and in a discourse with C.
Velleius, the senator, who was then reputed by the Epicureans the ablest
of our countrymen. Q. Lucilius Balbus was likewise there, a great
proficient in the doctrine of the Stoics, and esteemed equal to the most
eminent of the Greeks in that part of knowledge. As soon as Cotta saw
me, You are come, says he, very seasonably; for I am having a dispute
with Velleius on an important subject, which, considering the nature of
your studies, is not improper for you to join in.
VII. Indeed, says I, I think I am come very seasonably, as you say; for
here are three chiefs of three principal sects met together. If M.
Piso81 was present, no sect of philosophy that is in any esteem would
want an advocate. If Antiochus’s book, replies Cotta, which he lately
sent to Balbus, says true, you have no occasion to wish for your friend
Piso; for Antiochus is of the opinion that the Stoics do not differ from
the Peripatetics in fact, though they do in words; and I should be glad
to know what you think of that book, Balbus. I? says he. I wonder that
Antiochus, a man of the clearest apprehension, should not see what a
vast difference there is between the Stoics, who distinguish the honest
and the profitable, not only in name, but absolutely in kind, and the
Peripatetics, who blend the honest with the profitable in such a manner
that they differ only in degrees and proportion, and not in kind. This
is not a little difference in words, but a great one in things; 216but of
this hereafter. Now, if you think fit, let us return to what we began
with.
With all my heart, says Cotta. But that this visitor (looking at me),
who is just come in, may not be ignorant of what we are upon, I will
inform him that we were discoursing on the nature of the Gods;
concerning which, as it is a subject that always appeared very obscure
to me, I prevailed on Velleius to give us the sentiments of Epicurus.
Therefore, continues he, if it is not troublesome, Velleius, repeat what
you have already stated to us. I will, says he, though this new-comer
will be no advocate for me, but for you; for you have both, adds he,
with a smile, learned from the same Philo to be certain of nothing.82
What we have learned from him, replied I, Cotta will discover; but I
would not have you think I am come as an assistant to him, but as an
auditor, with an impartial and unbiassed mind, and not bound by any
obligation to defend any particular principle, whether I like or dislike
it.
VIII. After this, Velleius, with the confidence peculiar to his sect,
dreading nothing so much as to seem to doubt of anything, began as if he
had just then descended from the council of the Gods, and Epicurus’s
intervals of worlds. Do not attend, says he, to these idle and imaginary
tales; nor to the operator and builder of the World, the God of Plato’s
Timæus; nor to the old prophetic dame, the Πρόνοια of the Stoics, which
the Latins call Providence; nor to that round, that burning, revolving
deity, the World, endowed with sense and understanding; the prodigies
and wonders, not of inquisitive philosophers, but of dreamers!
For with what eyes of the mind was your Plato able to see that workhouse
of such stupendous toil, in which he makes the world to be modelled and
built by God? What materials, what tools, what bars, what machines, what
servants, were employed in so vast a work? How could the air, fire,
water, and earth pay obedience and submit to the will of the architect?
>From whence arose those five forms,83 of which the rest were composed,
so aptly contributing to frame the mind and produce the senses? It 217is
tedious to go through all, as they are of such a sort that they look
more like things to be desired than to be discovered.
But, what is more remarkable, he gives us a world which has been not
only created, but, if I may so say, in a manner formed with hands, and
yet he says it is eternal. Do you conceive him to have the least skill
in natural philosophy who is capable of thinking anything to be
everlasting that had a beginning? For what can possibly ever have been
put together which cannot be dissolved again? Or what is there that had
a beginning which will not have an end? If your Providence, Lucilius, is
the same as Plato’s God, I ask you, as before, who were the assistants,
what were the engines, what was the plan and preparation of the whole
work? If it is not the same, then why did she make the world mortal, and
not everlasting, like Plato’s God?
IX. But I would demand of you both, why these world-builders started up
so suddenly, and lay dormant for so many ages? For we are not to
conclude that, if there was no world, there were therefore no ages. I do
not now speak of such ages as are finished by a certain number of days
and nights in annual courses; for I acknowledge that those could not be
without the revolution of the world; but there was a certain eternity
from infinite time, not measured by any circumscription of seasons; but
how that was in space we cannot understand, because we cannot possibly
have even the slightest idea of time before time was. I desire,
therefore, to know, Balbus, why this Providence of yours was idle for
such an immense space of time? Did she avoid labor? But that could have
no effect on the Deity; nor could there be any labor, since all nature,
air, fire, earth, and water would obey the divine essence. What was it
that incited the Deity to act the part of an Г¦dile, to illuminate and
decorate the world? If it was in order that God might be the better
accommodated in his habitation, then he must have been dwelling an
infinite length of time before in darkness as in a dungeon. But do we
imagine that he was afterward delighted with that variety with which we
see the heaven and earth adorned? What entertainment could that be to
the Deity? If it was any, he would not have been without it so long.
218Or were these things made, as you almost assert, by God for the sake of
men? Was it for the wise? If so, then this great design was adopted for
the sake of a very small number. Or for the sake of fools? First of all,
there was no reason why God should consult the advantage of the wicked;
and, further, what could be his object in doing so, since all fools are,
without doubt, the most miserable of men, chiefly because they are
fools? For what can we pronounce more deplorable than folly? Besides,
there are many inconveniences in life which the wise can learn to think
lightly of by dwelling rather on the advantages which they receive; but
which fools are unable to avoid when they are coming, or to bear when
they are come.
X. They who affirm the world to be an animated and intelligent being
have by no means discovered the nature of the mind, nor are able to
conceive in what form that essence can exist; but of that I shall speak
more hereafter. At present I must express my surprise at the weakness of
those who endeavor to make it out to be not only animated and immortal,
but likewise happy, and round, because Plato says that is the most
beautiful form; whereas I think a cylinder, a square, a cone, or a
pyramid more beautiful. But what life do they attribute to that round
Deity? Truly it is a being whirled about with a celerity to which
nothing can be even conceived by the imagination as equal; nor can I
imagine how a settled mind and happy life can consist in such motion,
the least degree of which would be troublesome to us. Why, therefore,
should it not be considered troublesome also to the Deity? For the earth
itself, as it is part of the world, is part also of the Deity. We see
vast tracts of land barren and uninhabitable; some, because they are
scorched by the too near approach of the sun; others, because they are
bound up with frost and snow, through the great distance which the sun
is from them. Therefore, if the world is a Deity, as these are parts of
the world, some of the Deity’s limbs must be said to be scorched, and
some frozen.
These are your doctrines, Lucilius; but what those of others are I will
endeavor to ascertain by tracing them back from the earliest of ancient
philosophers. Thales 219the Milesian, who first inquired after such
subjects, asserted water to be the origin of things, and that God was
that mind which formed all things from water. If the Gods can exist
without corporeal sense, and if there can be a mind without a body, why
did he annex a mind to water?
It was Anaximander’s opinion that the Gods were born; that after a great
length of time they died; and that they are innumerable worlds. But what
conception can we possibly have of a Deity who is not eternal?
Anaximenes, after him, taught that the air is God, and that he was
generated, and that he is immense, infinite, and always in motion; as if
air, which has no form, could possibly be God; for the Deity must
necessarily be not only of some form or other, but of the most beautiful
form. Besides, is not everything that had a beginning subject to
mortality?
XI. Anaxagoras, who received his learning from Anaximenes, was the first
who affirmed the system and disposition of all things to be contrived
and perfected by the power and reason of an infinite mind; in which
infinity he did not perceive that there could be no conjunction of sense
and motion, nor any sense in the least degree, where nature herself
could feel no impulse. If he would have this mind to be a sort of
animal, then there must be some more internal principle from whence that
animal should receive its appellation. But what can be more internal
than the mind? Let it, therefore, be clothed with an external body. But
this is not agreeable to his doctrine; but we are utterly unable to
conceive how a pure simple mind can exist without any substance annexed
to it.
Alcmæon of Crotona, in attributing a divinity to the sun, the moon, and
the rest of the stars, and also to the mind, did not perceive that he
was ascribing immortality to mortal beings.
Pythagoras, who supposed the Deity to be one soul, mixing with and
pervading all nature, from which our souls are taken, did not consider
that the Deity himself must, in consequence of this doctrine, be maimed
and torn with the rending every human soul from it; nor that, when the
human mind is afflicted (as is the case in many instances), that part of
the Deity must likewise be afflicted, 220which cannot be. If the human
mind were a Deity, how could it be ignorant of any thing? Besides, how
could that Deity, if it is nothing but soul, be mixed with, or infused
into, the world?
Then Xenophanes, who said that everything in the world which had any
existence, with the addition of intellect, was God, is as liable to
exception as the rest, especially in relation to the infinity of it, in
which there can be nothing sentient, nothing composite.
Parmenides formed a conceit to himself of something circular like a
crown. (He names it Stephane.) It is an orb of constant light and heat
around the heavens; this he calls God; in which there is no room to
imagine any divine form or sense. And he uttered many other absurdities
on the same subject; for he ascribed a divinity to war, to discord, to
lust, and other passions of the same kind, which are destroyed by
disease, or sleep, or oblivion, or age. The same honor he gives to the
stars; but I shall forbear making any objections to his system here,
having already done it in another place.
XII. Empedocles, who erred in many things, is most grossly mistaken in
his notion of the Gods. He lays down four natures84 as divine, from
which he thinks that all things were made. Yet it is evident that they
have a beginning, that they decay, and that they are void of all sense.
Protagoras did not seem to have any idea of the real nature of the Gods;
for he acknowledged that he was altogether ignorant whether there are or
are not any, or what they are.
What shall I say of Democritus, who classes our images of objects, and
their orbs, in the number of the Gods; as he does that principle through
which those images appear and have their influence? He deifies likewise
our knowledge and understanding. Is he not involved in a very great
error? And because nothing continues always in the same state, he denies
that anything is everlasting, does he not thereby entirely destroy the
Deity, and make it impossible to form any opinion of him?
221Diogenes of Apollonia looks upon the air to be a Deity. But what sense
can the air have? or what divine form can be attributed to it?
It would be tedious to show the uncertainty of Plato’s opinion; for, in
his Timæus, he denies the propriety of asserting that there is one great
father or creator of the world; and, in his book of Laws, he thinks we
ought not to make too strict an inquiry into the nature of the Deity.
And as for his statement when he asserts that God is a being without any
body—what the Greeks call ἀσώματος—it is certainly quite
unintelligible how that theory can possibly be true; for such a God must
then necessarily be destitute of sense, prudence, and pleasure; all
which things are comprehended in our notion of the Gods. He likewise
asserts in his Timæus, and in his Laws, that the world, the heavens, the
stars, the mind, and those Gods which are delivered down to us from our
ancestors, constitute the Deity. These opinions, taken separately, are
apparently false; and, together, are directly inconsistent with each
other.
Xenophon has committed almost the same mistakes, but in fewer words. In
those sayings which he has related of Socrates, he introduces him
disputing the lawfulness of inquiring into the form of the Deity, and
makes him assert the sun and the mind to be Deities: he represents him
likewise as affirming the being of one God only, and at another time of
many; which are errors of almost the same kind which I before took
notice of in Plato.
XIII. Antisthenes, in his book called the Natural Philosopher, says that
there are many national and one natural Deity; but by this saying he
destroys the power and nature of the Gods. Speusippus is not much less
in the wrong; who, following his uncle Plato, says that a certain
incorporeal power governs everything; by which he endeavors to root out
of our minds the knowledge of the Gods.
Aristotle, in his third book of Philosophy, confounds many things
together, as the rest have done; but he does not differ from his master
Plato. At one time he attributes all divinity to the mind, at another he
asserts that the world is God. Soon afterward he makes some other
essence 222preside over the world, and gives it those faculties by which,
with certain revolutions, he may govern and preserve the motion of it.
Then he asserts the heat of the firmament to be God; not perceiving the
firmament to be part of the world, which in another place he had
described as God. How can that divine sense of the firmament be
preserved in so rapid a motion? And where do the multitude of Gods
dwell, if heaven itself is a Deity? But when this philosopher says that
God is without a body, he makes him an irrational and insensible being.
Besides, how can the world move itself, if it wants a body? Or how, if
it is in perpetual self-motion, can it be easy and happy?
Xenocrates, his fellow-pupil, does not appear much wiser on this head,
for in his books concerning the nature of the Gods no divine form is
described; but he says the number of them is eight. Five are moving
planets;85 the sixth is contained in all the fixed stars; which,
dispersed, are so many several members, but, considered together, are
one single Deity; the seventh is the sun; and the eighth the moon. But
in what sense they can possibly be happy is not easy to be understood.
From the same school of Plato, Heraclides of Pontus stuffed his books
with puerile tales. Sometimes he thinks the world a Deity, at other
times the mind. He attributes divinity likewise to the wandering stars.
He deprives the Deity of sense, and makes his form mutable; and, in the
same book again, he makes earth and heaven Deities.
The unsteadiness of Theophrastus is equally intolerable. At one time he
attributes a divine prerogative to the mind; at another, to the
firmament; at another, to the stars and celestial constellations.
Nor is his disciple Strato, who is called the naturalist, any more
worthy to be regarded; for he thinks that the divine power is diffused
through nature, which is the cause of birth, increase, and diminution,
but that it has no sense nor form.
XIV. Zeno (to come to your sect, Balbus) thinks the law of nature to be
the divinity, and that it has the power 223to force us to what is right,
and to restrain us from what is wrong. How this law can be an animated
being I cannot conceive; but that God is so we would certainly maintain.
The same person says, in another place, that the sky is God; but can we
possibly conceive that God is a being insensible, deaf to our prayers,
our wishes, and our vows, and wholly unconnected with us? In other books
he thinks there is a certain rational essence pervading all nature,
indued with divine efficacy. He attributes the same power to the stars,
to the years, to the months, and to the seasons. In his interpretation
of Hesiod’s Theogony,86 he entirely destroys the established notions
of the Gods; for he excludes Jupiter, Juno, and Vesta, and those
esteemed divine, from the number of them; but his doctrine is that these
are names which by some kind of allusion are given to mute and inanimate
beings. The sentiments of his disciple Aristo are not less erroneous. He
thought it impossible to conceive the form of the Deity, and asserts
that the Gods are destitute of sense; and he is entirely dubious whether
the Deity is an animated being or not.
Cleanthes, who next comes under my notice, a disciple of Zeno at the
same time with Aristo, in one place says that the world is God; in
another, he attributes divinity to the mind and spirit of universal
nature; then he asserts that the most remote, the highest, the
all-surrounding, the all-enclosing and embracing heat, which is called
the sky, is most certainly the Deity. In the books he wrote against
pleasure, in which he seems to be raving, he imagines the Gods to have a
certain form and shape; then he ascribes all divinity to the stars; and,
lastly, he thinks nothing more divine than reason. So that this God,
whom we know mentally and in the speculations of our minds, from which
traces we receive our impression, has at last actually no visible form
at all.
XV. Persæus, another disciple of Zeno, says that they who have made
discoveries advantageous to the life of man should be esteemed as Gods;
and the very things, he says, which are healthful and beneficial have
derived their names from those of the Gods; so that he thinks it not
sufficient to call them the discoveries of Gods, but he urges that they
224themselves should be deemed divine. What can be more absurd than to
ascribe divine honors to sordid and deformed things; or to place among
the Gods men who are dead and mixed with the dust, to whose memory all
the respect that could be paid would be but mourning for their loss?
Chrysippus, who is looked upon as the most subtle interpreter of the
dreams of the Stoics, has mustered up a numerous band of unknown Gods;
and so unknown that we are not able to form any idea about them, though
our mind seems capable of framing any image to itself in its thoughts.
For he says that the divine power is placed in reason, and in the spirit
and mind of universal nature; that the world, with a universal effusion
of its spirit, is God; that the superior part of that spirit, which is
the mind and reason, is the great principle of nature, containing and
preserving the chain of all things; that the divinity is the power of
fate, and the necessity of future events. He deifies fire also, and what
I before called the ethereal spirit, and those elements which naturally
proceed from it—water, earth, and air. He attributes divinity to the
sun, moon, stars, and universal space, the grand container of all
things, and to those men likewise who have obtained immortality. He
maintains the sky to be what men call Jupiter; the air, which pervades
the sea, to be Neptune; and the earth, Ceres. In like manner he goes
through the names of the other Deities. He says that Jupiter is that
immutable and eternal law which guides and directs us in our manners;
and this he calls fatal necessity, the everlasting verity of future
events. But none of these are of such a nature as to seem to carry any
indication of divine virtue in them. These are the doctrines contained
in his first book of the Nature of the Gods. In the second, he endeavors
to accommodate the fables of Orpheus, Musæus, Hesiod, and Homer to what
he has advanced in the first, in order that the most ancient poets, who
never dreamed of these things, may seem to have been Stoics. Diogenes
the Babylonian was a follower of the doctrine of Chrysippus; and in that
book which he wrote, entitled “A Treatise concerning Minerva,” he
separates the account of Jupiter’s bringing-forth, and the birth of that
virgin, from the fabulous, and reduces it to a natural construction.
225XVI. Thus far have I been rather exposing the dreams of dotards than
giving the opinions of philosophers. Not much more absurd than these are
the fables of the poets, who owe all their power of doing harm to the
sweetness of their language; who have represented the Gods as enraged
with anger and inflamed with lust; who have brought before our eyes
their wars, battles, combats, wounds; their hatreds, dissensions,
discords, births, deaths, complaints, and lamentations; their
indulgences in all kinds of intemperance; their adulteries; their
chains; their amours with mortals, and mortals begotten by immortals. To
these idle and ridiculous flights of the poets we may add the prodigious
stories invented by the Magi, and by the Egyptians also, which were of
the same nature, together with the extravagant notions of the multitude
at all times, who, from total ignorance of the truth, are always
fluctuating in uncertainty.
Now, whoever reflects on the rashness and absurdity of these tenets must
inevitably entertain the highest respect and veneration for Epicurus,
and perhaps even rank him in the number of those beings who are the
subject of this dispute; for he alone first founded the idea of the
existence of the Gods on the impression which nature herself hath made
on the minds of all men. For what nation, what people are there, who
have not, without any learning, a natural idea, or prenotion, of a
Deity? Epicurus calls this ПЂПЃбЅ№О»О·П€О№П‚; that is, an antecedent conception
of the fact in the mind, without which nothing can be understood,
inquired after, or discoursed on; the force and advantage of which
reasoning we receive from that celestial volume of Epicurus concerning
the Rule and Judgment of Things.
XVII. Here, then, you see the foundation of this question clearly laid;
for since it is the constant and universal opinion of mankind,
independent of education, custom, or law, that there are Gods, it must
necessarily follow that this knowledge is implanted in our minds, or,
rather, innate in us. That opinion respecting which there is a general
agreement in universal nature must infallibly be true; therefore it must
be allowed that there are Gods; for in this we have the concurrence, not
only of almost all philosophers, but likewise of the ignorant and
illiterate. It 226must be also confessed that the point is established
that we have naturally this idea, as I said before, or prenotion, of the
existence of the Gods. As new things require new names, so that
prenotion was called ПЂПЃбЅ№О»О·П€О№П‚ by Epicurus; an appellation never used
before. On the same principle of reasoning, we think that the Gods are
happy and immortal; for that nature which hath assured us that there are
Gods has likewise imprinted in our minds the knowledge of their
immortality and felicity; and if so, what Epicurus hath declared in
these words is true: “That which is eternally happy cannot be burdened
with any labor itself, nor can it impose any labor on another; nor can
it be influenced by resentment or favor: because things which are liable
to such feelings must be weak and frail.” We have said enough to prove
that we should worship the Gods with piety, and without superstition, if
that were the only question.
For the superior and excellent nature of the Gods requires a pious
adoration from men, because it is possessed of immortality and the most
exalted felicity; for whatever excels has a right to veneration, and all
fear of the power and anger of the Gods should be banished; for we must
understand that anger and affection are inconsistent with the nature of
a happy and immortal being. These apprehensions being removed, no dread
of the superior powers remains. To confirm this opinion, our curiosity
leads us to inquire into the form and life and action of the intellect
and spirit of the Deity.
XVIII. With regard to his form, we are directed partly by nature and
partly by reason. All men are told by nature that none but a human form
can be ascribed to the Gods; for under what other image did it ever
appear to any one either sleeping or waking? and, without having
recourse to our first notions,87 reason itself declares the same; for
as it is easy to conceive that the most excellent nature, either because
of its happiness or immortality, should be the most beautiful, what
composition of limbs, what conformation of lineaments, what form, what
aspect, can be more beautiful than the human? Your sect, Lucilius (not
like my friend Cotta, who sometimes says one 227thing and sometimes
another), when they represent the divine art and workmanship in the
human body, are used to describe how very completely each member is
formed, not only for convenience, but also for beauty. Therefore, if the
human form excels that of all other animal beings, as God himself is an
animated being, he must surely be of that form which is the most
beautiful. Besides, the Gods are granted to be perfectly happy; and
nobody can be happy without virtue, nor can virtue exist where reason is
not; and reason can reside in none but the human form; the Gods,
therefore, must be acknowledged to be of human form; yet that form is
not body, but something like body; nor does it contain any blood, but
something like blood. Though these distinctions were more acutely
devised and more artfully expressed by Epicurus than any common capacity
can comprehend; yet, depending on your understanding, I shall be more
brief on the subject than otherwise I should be. Epicurus, who not only
discovered and understood the occult and almost hidden secrets of
nature, but explained them with ease, teaches that the power and nature
of the Gods is not to be discerned by the senses, but by the mind; nor
are they to be considered as bodies of any solidity, or reducible to
number, like those things which, because of their firmness, he calls
ОЈП„ОµПЃбЅіОјОЅО№О±;88 but as images, perceived by similitude and transition. As
infinite kinds of those images result from innumerable individuals, and
centre in the Gods, our minds and understanding are directed towards and
fixed with the greatest delight on them, in order to comprehend what
that happy and eternal essence is.
XIX. Surely the mighty power of the Infinite Being is most worthy our
great and earnest contemplation; the nature of which we must necessarily
understand to be such that everything in it is made to correspond
completely to some other answering part. This is called by Epicurus
бј°ПѓОїОЅОїОјбЅ·О±; that is to say, an equal distribution or even disposition of
things. From hence he draws this inference, 228that, as there is such a
vast multitude of mortals, there cannot be a less number of immortals;
and if those which perish are innumerable, those which are preserved
ought also to be countless. Your sect, Balbus, frequently ask us how the
Gods live, and how they pass their time? Their life is the most happy,
and the most abounding with all kinds of blessings, which can be
conceived. They do nothing. They are embarrassed with no business; nor
do they perform any work. They rejoice in the possession of their own
wisdom and virtue. They are satisfied that they shall ever enjoy the
fulness of eternal pleasures.
XX. Such a Deity may properly be called happy; but yours is a most
laborious God. For let us suppose the world a Deity—what can be a more
uneasy state than, without the least cessation, to be whirled about the
axle-tree of heaven with a surprising celerity? But nothing can be happy
that is not at ease. Or let us suppose a Deity residing in the world,
who directs and governs it, who preserves the courses of the stars, the
changes of the seasons, and the vicissitudes and orders of things,
surveying the earth and the sea, and accommodating them to the advantage
and necessities of man. Truly this Deity is embarrassed with a very
troublesome and laborious office. We make a happy life to consist in a
tranquillity of mind, a perfect freedom from care, and an exemption from
all employment. The philosopher from whom we received all our knowledge
has taught us that the world was made by nature; that there was no
occasion for a workhouse to frame it in; and that, though you deny the
possibility of such a work without divine skill, it is so easy to her,
that she has made, does make, and will make innumerable worlds. But,
because you do not conceive that nature is able to produce such effects
without some rational aid, you are forced, like the tragic poets, when
you cannot wind up your argument in any other way, to have recourse to a
Deity, whose assistance you would not seek, if you could view that vast
and unbounded magnitude of regions in all parts; where the mind,
extending and spreading itself, travels so far and wide that it can find
no end, no extremity to stop at. In this immensity of breadth, length,
and height, a most boundless company of innumerable atoms 229are
fluttering about, which, notwithstanding the interposition of a void
space, meet and cohere, and continue clinging to one another; and by
this union these modifications and forms of things arise, which, in your
opinions, could not possibly be made without the help of bellows and
anvils. Thus you have imposed on us an eternal master, whom we must
dread day and night. For who can be free from fear of a Deity who
foresees, regards, and takes notice of everything; one who thinks all
things his own; a curious, ever-busy God?
Hence first arose your О•бј±ОјО±ПЃОјбЅіОЅО·, as you call it, your fatal necessity;
so that, whatever happens, you affirm that it flows from an eternal
chain and continuance of causes. Of what value is this philosophy,
which, like old women and illiterate men, attributes everything to fate?
Then follows your ОјО±ОЅП„О№ОєбЅґ, in Latin called divinatio, divination;
which, if we would listen to you, would plunge us into such superstition
that we should fall down and worship your inspectors into sacrifices,
your augurs, your soothsayers, your prophets, and your fortune-tellers.
Epicurus having freed us from these terrors and restored us to liberty,
we have no dread of those beings whom we have reason to think entirely
free from all trouble themselves, and who do not impose any on others.
We pay our adoration, indeed, with piety and reverence to that essence
which is above all excellence and perfection. But I fear my zeal for
this doctrine has made me too prolix. However, I could not easily leave
so eminent and important a subject unfinished, though I must confess I
should rather endeavor to hear than speak so long.
XXI. Cotta, with his usual courtesy, then began. Velleius, says he, were
it not for something which you have advanced, I should have remained
silent; for I have often observed, as I did just now upon hearing you,
that I cannot so easily conceive why a proposition is true as why it is
false. Should you ask me what I take the nature of the Gods to be, I
should perhaps make no answer. But if you should ask whether I think it
to be of that nature which you have described, I should answer that I
was as far as possible from agreeing with you. However, before I enter
on the subject of your discourse and what you 230have advanced upon it, I
will give you my opinion of yourself. Your intimate friend, L. Crassus,
has been often heard by me to say that you were beyond all question
superior to all our learned Romans; and that few Epicureans in Greece
were to be compared to you. But as I knew what a wonderful esteem he had
for you, I imagined that might make him the more lavish in commendation
of you. Now, however, though I do not choose to praise any one when
present, yet I must confess that I think you have delivered your
thoughts clearly on an obscure and very intricate subject; that you are
not only copious in your sentiments, but more elegant in your language
than your sect generally are. When I was at Athens, I went often to hear
Zeno, by the advice of Philo, who used to call him the chief of the
Epicureans; partly, probably, in order to judge more easily how
completely those principles could be refuted after I had heard them
stated by the most learned of the Epicureans. And, indeed, he did not
speak in any ordinary manner; but, like you, with clearness, gravity,
and elegance; yet what frequently gave me great uneasiness when I heard
him, as it did while I attended to you, was to see so excellent a genius
falling into such frivolous (excuse my freedom), not to say foolish,
doctrines. However, I shall not at present offer anything better; for,
as I said before, we can in most subjects, especially in physics, sooner
discover what is not true than what is.
XXII. If you should ask me what God is, or what his character and nature
are, I should follow the example of Simonides, who, when Hiero the
tyrant proposed the same question to him, desired a day to consider of
it. When he required his answer the next day, Simonides begged two days
more; and as he kept constantly desiring double the number which he had
required before instead of giving his answer, Hiero, with surprise,
asked him his meaning in doing so: “Because,” says he, “the longer I
meditate on it, the more obscure it appears to me.” Simonides, who was
not only a delightful poet, but reputed a wise and learned man in other
branches of knowledge, found, I suppose, so many acute and refined
arguments occurring to him, that he was doubtful which was the truest,
and therefore despaired of discovering any truth.
231But does your Epicurus (for I had rather contend with him than with
you) say anything that is worthy the name of philosophy, or even of
common-sense?
In the question concerning the nature of the Gods, his first inquiry is,
whether there are Gods or not. It would be dangerous, I believe, to take
the negative side before a public auditory; but it is very safe in a
discourse of this kind, and in this company. I, who am a priest, and who
think that religions and ceremonies ought sacredly to be maintained, am
certainly desirous to have the existence of the Gods, which is the
principal point in debate, not only fixed in opinion, but proved to a
demonstration; for many notions flow into and disturb the mind which
sometimes seem to convince us that there are none. But see how candidly
I will behave to you: as I shall not touch upon those tenets you hold in
common with other philosophers, consequently I shall not dispute the
existence of the Gods, for that doctrine is agreeable to almost all men,
and to myself in particular; but I am still at liberty to find fault
with the reasons you give for it, which I think are very insufficient.
XXIII. You have said that the general assent of men of all nations and
all degrees is an argument strong enough to induce us to acknowledge the
being of the Gods. This is not only a weak, but a false, argument; for,
first of all, how do you know the opinions of all nations? I really
believe there are many people so savage that they have no thoughts of a
Deity. What think you of Diagoras, who was called the atheist; and of
Theodorus after him? Did not they plainly deny the very essence of a
Deity? Protagoras of Abdera, whom you just now mentioned, the greatest
sophist of his age, was banished by order of the Athenians from their
city and territories, and his books were publicly burned, because these
words were in the beginning of his treatise concerning the Gods: “I am
unable to arrive at any knowledge whether there are, or are not, any
Gods.” This treatment of him, I imagine, restrained many from professing
their disbelief of a Deity, since the doubt of it only could not escape
punishment. What shall we say of the sacrilegious, the impious, and the
perjured? If Tubulus Lucius, Lupus, or Carbo the son of 232Neptune, as
Lucilius says, had believed that there were Gods, would either of them
have carried his perjuries and impieties to such excess? Your reasoning,
therefore, to confirm your assertion is not so conclusive as you think
it is. But as this is the manner in which other philosophers have argued
on the same subject, I will take no further notice of it at present; I
rather choose to proceed to what is properly your own.
I allow that there are Gods. Instruct me, then, concerning their origin;
inform me where they are, what sort of body, what mind, they have, and
what is their course of life; for these I am desirous of knowing. You
attribute the most absolute power and efficacy to atoms. Out of them you
pretend that everything is made. But there are no atoms, for there is
nothing without body; every place is occupied by body, therefore there
can be no such thing as a vacuum or an atom.
XXIV. I advance these principles of the naturalists without knowing
whether they are true or false; yet they are more like truth than those
statements of yours; for they are the absurdities in which Democritus,
or before him Leucippus, used to indulge, saying that there are certain
light corpuscles—some smooth, some rough, some round, some square, some
crooked and bent as bows—which by a fortuitous concourse made heaven
and earth, without the influence of any natural power. This opinion, C.
Velleius, you have brought down to these our times; and you would sooner
be deprived of the greatest advantages of life than of that authority;
for before you were acquainted with those tenets, you thought that you
ought to profess yourself an Epicurean; so that it was necessary that
you should either embrace these absurdities or lose the philosophical
character which you had taken upon you; and what could bribe you to
renounce the Epicurean opinion? Nothing, you say, can prevail on you to
forsake the truth and the sure means of a happy life. But is that the
truth? for I shall not contest your happy life, which you think the
Deity himself does not enjoy unless he languishes in idleness. But where
is truth? Is it in your innumerable worlds, some of which are rising,
some falling, at every moment of time? Or is it in your atomical
corpuscles, 233which form such excellent works without the direction of
any natural power or reason? But I was forgetting my liberality, which I
had promised to exert in your case, and exceeding the bounds which I at
first proposed to myself. Granting, then, everything to be made of
atoms, what advantage is that to your argument? For we are searching
after the nature of the Gods; and allowing them to be made of atoms,
they cannot be eternal, because whatever is made of atoms must have had
a beginning: if so, there were no Gods till there was this beginning;
and if the Gods have had a beginning, they must necessarily have an end,
as you have before contended when you were discussing Plato’s world.
Where, then, is your beatitude and immortality, in which two words you
say that God is expressed, the endeavor to prove which reduces you to
the greatest perplexities? For you said that God had no body, but
something like body; and no blood, but something like blood.
XXV. It is a frequent practice among you, when you assert anything that
has no resemblance to truth, and wish to avoid reprehension, to advance
something else which is absolutely and utterly impossible, in order that
it may seem to your adversaries better to grant that point which has
been a matter of doubt than to keep on pertinaciously contradicting you
on every point: like Epicurus, who, when he found that if his atoms were
allowed to descend by their own weight, our actions could not be in our
own power, because their motions would be certain and necessary,
invented an expedient, which escaped Democritus, to avoid necessity. He
says that when the atoms descend by their own weight and gravity, they
move a little obliquely. Surely, to make such an assertion as this is
what one ought more to be ashamed of than the acknowledging ourselves
unable to defend the proposition. His practice is the same against the
logicians, who say that in all propositions in which yes or no is
required, one of them must be true; he was afraid that if this were
granted, then, in such a proposition as “Epicurus will be alive or dead
to-morrow,” either one or the other must necessarily be admitted;
therefore he absolutely denied the necessity of yes or no. Can anything
234show stupidity in a greater degree? Zeno,89 being pressed by
Arcesilas, who pronounced all things to be false which are perceived by
the senses, said that some things were false, but not all. Epicurus was
afraid that if any one thing seen should be false, nothing could be
true; and therefore he asserted all the senses to be infallible
directors of truth. Nothing can be more rash than this; for by
endeavoring to repel a light stroke, he receives a heavy blow. On the
subject of the nature of the Gods, he falls into the same errors. While
he would avoid the concretion of individual bodies, lest death and
dissolution should be the consequence, he denies that the Gods have
body, but says they have something like body; and says they have no
blood, but something like blood.
XXVI. It seems an unaccountable thing how one soothsayer can refrain
from laughing when he sees another. It is yet a greater wonder that you
can refrain from laughing among yourselves. It is no body, but something
like body! I could understand this if it were applied to statues made of
wax or clay; but in regard to the Deity, I am not able to discover what
is meant by a quasi-body or quasi-blood. Nor indeed are you, Velleius,
though you will not confess so much. For those precepts are delivered to
you as dictates which Epicurus carelessly blundered out; for he boasted,
as we see in his writings, that he had no instructor, which I could
easily believe without his public declaration of it, for the same reason
that I could believe the master of a very bad edifice if he were to
boast that he had no architect but himself: for there is nothing of the
Academy, nothing of the Lyceum, in his doctrine; nothing but
puerilities. He might have been a pupil of Xenocrates. O ye immortal
Gods, what a teacher was he! And there are those who believe that he
actually was his pupil; but he says otherwise, and I shall give more
credit to his word than to another’s. He confesses that he was a pupil
of a certain disciple of Plato, one Pamphilus, at Samos; for he lived
there when he was young, with his father and his brothers. His father,
Neocles, was a farmer in those parts; 235but as the farm, I suppose, was
not sufficient to maintain him, he turned school-master; yet Epicurus
treats this Platonic philosopher with wonderful contempt, so fearful was
he that it should be thought he had ever had any instruction. But it is
well known he had been a pupil of Nausiphanes, the follower of
Democritus; and since he could not deny it, he loaded him with insults
in abundance. If he never heard a lecture on these Democritean
principles, what lectures did he ever hear? What is there in Epicurus’s
physics that is not taken from Democritus? For though he altered some
things, as what I mentioned before of the oblique motions of the atoms,
yet most of his doctrines are the same; his atoms—his vacuum—his
images—infinity of space—innumerable worlds, their rise and decay—and
almost every part of natural learning that he treats of.
Now, do you understand what is meant by quasi-body and quasi-blood? For
I not only acknowledge that you are a better judge of it than I am, but
I can bear it without envy. If any sentiments, indeed, are communicated
without obscurity, what is there that Velleius can understand and Cotta
not? I know what body is, and what blood is; but I cannot possibly find
out the meaning of quasi-body and quasi-blood. Not that you
intentionally conceal your principles from me, as Pythagoras did his
from those who were not his disciples; or that you are intentionally
obscure, like Heraclitus. But the truth is (which I may venture to say
in this company), you do not understand them yourself.
XXVII. This, I perceive, is what you contend for, that the Gods have a
certain figure that has nothing concrete, nothing solid, nothing of
express substance, nothing prominent in it; but that it is pure, smooth,
and transparent. Let us suppose the same with the Venus of Cos, which is
not a body, but the representation of a body; nor is the red, which is
drawn there and mixed with the white, real blood, but a certain
resemblance of blood; so in Epicurus’s Deity there is no real substance,
but the resemblance of substance.
Let me take for granted that which is perfectly unintelligible; then
tell me what are the lineaments and figures 236of these sketched-out
Deities. Here you have plenty of arguments by which you would show the
Gods to be in human form. The first is, that our minds are so
anticipated and prepossessed, that whenever we think of a Deity the
human shape occurs to us. The next is, that as the divine nature excels
all things, so it ought to be of the most beautiful form, and there is
no form more beautiful than the human; and the third is, that reason
cannot reside in any other shape.
First, let us consider each argument separately. You seem to me to
assume a principle, despotically I may say, that has no manner of
probability in it. Who was ever so blind, in contemplating these
subjects, as not to see that the Gods were represented in human form,
either by the particular advice of wise men, who thought by those means
the more easily to turn the minds of the ignorant from a depravity of
manners to the worship of the Gods; or through superstition, which was
the cause of their believing that when they were paying adoration to
these images they were approaching the Gods themselves. These conceits
were not a little improved by the poets, painters, and artificers; for
it would not have been very easy to represent the Gods planning and
executing any work in another form, and perhaps this opinion arose from
the idea which mankind have of their own beauty. But do not you, who are
so great an adept in physics, see what a soothing flatterer, what a sort
of procuress, nature is to herself? Do you think there is any creature
on the land or in the sea that is not highly delighted with its own
form? If it were not so, why would not a bull become enamored of a mare,
or a horse of a cow? Do you believe an eagle, a lion, or a dolphin
prefers any shape to its own? If nature, therefore, has instructed us in
the same manner, that nothing is more beautiful than man, what wonder is
it that we, for that reason, should imagine the Gods are of the human
form? Do you suppose if beasts were endowed with reason that every one
would not give the prize of beauty to his own species?
XXVIII. Yet, by Hercules (I speak as I think)! though I am fond enough
of myself, I dare not say that I excel in beauty that bull which carried
Europa. For the question 237here is not concerning our genius and
elocution, but our species and figure. If we could make and assume to
ourselves any form, would you be unwilling to resemble the sea-triton as
he is painted supported swimming on sea-monsters whose bodies are partly
human? Here I touch on a difficult point; for so great is the force of
nature that there is no man who would not choose to be like a man, nor,
indeed, any ant that would not be like an ant. But like what man? For
how few can pretend to beauty! When I was at Athens, the whole flock of
youths afforded scarcely one. You laugh, I see; but what I tell you is
the truth. Nay, to us who, after the examples of ancient philosophers,
delight in boys, defects are often pleasing. Alcæus was charmed with a
wart on a boy’s knuckle; but a wart is a blemish on the body; yet it
seemed a beauty to him. Q. Catulus, my friend and colleague’s father,
was enamored with your fellow-citizen Roscius, on whom he wrote these
verses:
As once I stood to hail the rising day,
Roscius appearing on the left I spied:
Forgive me, Gods, if I presume to say
The mortal’s beauty with th’ immortal vied.
Roscius more beautiful than a God! yet he was then, as he now is,
squint-eyed. But what signifies that, if his defects were beauties to
Catulus?
XXIX. I return to the Gods. Can we suppose any of them to be
squint-eyed, or even to have a cast in the eye? Have they any warts? Are
any of them hook-nosed, flap-eared, beetle-browed, or jolt-headed, as
some of us are? Or are they free from imperfections? Let us grant you
that. Are they all alike in the face? For if they are many, then one
must necessarily be more beautiful than another, and then there must be
some Deity not absolutely most beautiful. Or if their faces are all
alike, there would be an Academy90 in heaven; for if one God does not
differ from another, there is no possibility of knowing or
distinguishing them.
What if your assertion, Velleius, proves absolutely false, that no form
occurs to us, in our contemplations on the 238Deity, but the human? Will
you, notwithstanding that, persist in the defence of such an absurdity?
Supposing that form occurs to us, as you say it does, and we know
Jupiter, Juno, Minerva, Neptune, Vulcan, Apollo, and the other Deities,
by the countenance which painters and statuaries have given them, and
not only by their countenances, but by their decorations, their age, and
attire; yet the Egyptians, the Syrians, and almost all barbarous
nations,91 are without such distinctions. You may see a greater regard
paid by them to certain beasts than by us to the most sacred temples and
images of the Gods; for many shrines have been rifled, and images of the
Deities have been carried from their most sacred places by us; but we
never heard that an Egyptian offered any violence to a crocodile, an
ibis, or a cat. What do you think, then? Do not the Egyptians esteem
their sacred bull, their Apis, as a Deity? Yes, by Hercules! as
certainly as you do our protectress Juno, whom you never behold, even in
your dreams, without a goat-skin, a spear, a shield, and broad sandals.
But the Grecian Juno of Argos and the Roman Juno are not represented in
this manner; so that the Grecians, the Lanuvinians, and we, ascribe
different forms to Juno; and our Capitoline Jupiter is not the same with
the Jupiter Ammon of the Africans.
XXX. Therefore, ought not a natural philosopher—that is, an inquirer
into the secrets of nature—to be ashamed of seeking a testimony to
truth from minds prepossessed by custom? According to the rule you have
laid down, it may be said that Jupiter is always bearded, Apollo always
beardless; that Minerva has gray and Neptune azure eyes; and, indeed, we
must then honor that Vulcan at Athens, made by Alcamenes, whose lameness
through his thin robes appears to be no deformity. Shall we, therefore,
receive a lame Deity because we have such an account of him?
Consider, likewise, that the Gods go by what names we give them. Now, in
the first place, they have as many names as men have languages; for
Vulcan is not called Vulcan in Italy, Africa, or Spain, as you are
called Velleius in all countries. Besides, the Gods are innumerable,
though the list of their names is of no great length even 239in the
records of our priests. Have they no names? You must necessarily
confess, indeed, they have none; for what occasion is there for
different names if their persons are alike?
How much more laudable would it be, Velleius, to acknowledge that you do
not know what you do not know than to follow a man whom you must
despise! Do you think the Deity is like either me or you? You do not
really think he is like either of us. What is to be done, then? Shall I
call the sun, the moon, or the sky a Deity? If so, they are consequently
happy. But what pleasures can they enjoy? And they are wise too. But how
can wisdom reside in such shapes? These are your own principles.
Therefore, if they are not of human form, as I have proved, and if you
cannot persuade yourself that they are of any other, why are you
cautious of denying absolutely the being of any Gods? You dare not deny
it—which is very prudent in you, though here you are not afraid of the
people, but of the Gods themselves. I have known Epicureans who
reverence92 even the least images of the Gods, though I perceive it to
be the opinion of some that Epicurus, through fear of offending against
the Athenian laws, has allowed a Deity in words and destroyed him in
fact; so in those his select and short sentences, which are called by
you κυρίαι δόξαι,93 this, I think, is the first: “That being which is
happy and immortal is not burdened with any labor, and does not impose
any on any one else.”
XXXI. In his statement of this sentence, some think that he avoided
speaking clearly on purpose, though it was manifestly without design.
But they judge ill of a man who had not the least art. It is doubtful
whether he means that there is any being happy and immortal, or that if
there is any being happy, he must likewise be immortal. They do not
consider that he speaks here, indeed, ambiguously; but in many other
places both he and Metrodorus explain themselves as clearly as you have
done. But he believed there are Gods; nor have I ever seen any one 240who
was more exceedingly afraid of what he declared ought to be no objects
of fear, namely, death and the Gods, with the apprehensions of which the
common rank of people are very little affected; but he says that the
minds of all mortals are terrified by them. Many thousands of men commit
robberies in the face of death; others rifle all the temples they can
get into: such as these, no doubt, must be greatly terrified, the one by
the fears of death, and the others by the fear of the Gods.
But since you dare not (for I am now addressing my discourse to Epicurus
himself) absolutely deny the existence of the Gods, what hinders you
from ascribing a divine nature to the sun, the world, or some eternal
mind? I never, says he, saw wisdom and a rational soul in any but a
human form. What! did you ever observe anything like the sun, the moon,
or the five moving planets? The sun, terminating his course in two
extreme parts of one circle,94 finishes his annual revolutions. The
moon, receiving her light from the sun, completes the same course in
the space of a month.95 The five planets in the same circle, some
nearer, others more remote from the earth, begin the same courses
together, and finish them in different spaces of time. Did you ever
observe anything like this, Epicurus? So that, according to you, there
can be neither sun, moon, nor stars, because nothing can exist but what
we have touched or seen.96 What! have you ever seen the Deity himself?
Why else do you believe there is any? If this doctrine prevails, we must
reject all that history relates or reason discovers; and the people who
inhabit inland countries must not believe there is such a thing as the
sea. This is so narrow a way of thinking that if you had been born in
Seriphus, and never had been from out of that island, where you had
frequently been in the habit of seeing little hares and foxes, you would
not, therefore, believe that there are such beasts as lions and
panthers; 241and if any one should describe an elephant to you, you would
think that he designed to laugh at you.
XXXII. You indeed, Velleius, have concluded your argument, not after the
manner of your own sect, but of the logicians, to which your people are
utter strangers. You have taken it for granted that the Gods are happy.
I allow it. You say that without virtue no one can be happy. I willingly
concur with you in this also. You likewise say that virtue cannot reside
where reason is not. That I must necessarily allow. You add, moreover,
that reason cannot exist but in a human form. Who, do you think, will
admit that? If it were true, what occasion was there to come so
gradually to it? And to what purpose? You might have answered it on your
own authority. I perceive your gradations from happiness to virtue, and
from virtue to reason; but how do you come from reason to human form?
There, indeed, you do not descend by degrees, but precipitately.
Nor can I conceive why Epicurus should rather say the Gods are like men
than that men are like the Gods. You ask what is the difference; for,
say you, if this is like that, that is like this. I grant it; but this I
assert, that the Gods could not take their form from men; for the Gods
always existed, and never had a beginning, if they are to exist
eternally; but men had a beginning: therefore that form, of which the
immortal Gods are, must have had existence before mankind; consequently,
the Gods should not be said to be of human form, but our form should be
called divine. However, let this be as you will. I now inquire how this
extraordinary good fortune came about; for you deny that reason had any
share in the formation of things. But still, what was this extraordinary
fortune? Whence proceeded that happy concourse of atoms which gave so
sudden a rise to men in the form of Gods? Are we to suppose the divine
seed fell from heaven upon earth, and that men sprung up in the likeness
of their celestial sires? I wish you would assert it; for I should not
be unwilling to acknowledge my relation to the Gods. But you say nothing
like it; no, our resemblance to the Gods, it seems, was by chance. Must
I now seek for arguments to refute this doctrine seriously? I wish I
could 242as easily discover what is true as I can overthrow what is false.
XXXIII. You have enumerated with so ready a memory, and so copiously,
the opinions of philosophers, from Thales the Milesian, concerning the
nature of the Gods, that I am surprised to see so much learning in a
Roman. But do you think they were all madmen who thought that a Deity
could by some possibility exist without hands and feet? Does not even
this consideration have weight with you when you consider what is the
use and advantage of limbs in men, and lead you to admit that the Gods
have no need of them? What necessity can there be of feet, without
walking; or of hands, if there is nothing to be grasped? The same may be
asked of the other parts of the body, in which nothing is vain, nothing
useless, nothing superfluous; therefore we may infer that no art can
imitate the skill of nature. Shall the Deity, then, have a tongue, and
not speak—teeth, palate, and jaws, though he will have no use for them?
Shall the members which nature has given to the body for the sake of
generation be useless to the Deity? Nor would the internal parts be less
superfluous than the external. What comeliness is there in the heart,
the lungs, the liver, and the rest of them, abstracted from their use? I
mention these because you place them in the Deity on account of the
beauty of the human form.
Depending on these dreams, not only Epicurus, Metrodorus, and Hermachus
declaimed against Pythagoras, Plato, and Empedocles, but that little
harlot Leontium presumed to write against Theophrastus: indeed, she had
a neat Attic style; but yet, to think of her arguing against
Theophrastus! So much did the garden of Epicurus97 abound with these
liberties, and, indeed, you are always complaining against them. Zeno
wrangled. Why need I mention Albutius? Nothing could be more elegant or
humane than Phædrus; yet a sharp expression would disgust the old man.
Epicurus treated Aristotle with great contumely. He foully slandered
Phædo, the disciple of Socrates. He pelted Timocrates, the brother of
his companion Metrodorus, with whole volumes, because he disagreed with
him in some trifling point of philosophy. He 243was ungrateful even to
Democritus, whose follower he was; and his master Nausiphanes, from whom
he learned nothing, had no better treatment from him.
XXXIV. Zeno gave abusive language not only to those who were then
living, as Apollodorus, Syllus, and the rest, but he called Socrates,
who was the father of philosophy, the Attic buffoon, using the Latin
word Scurra. He never called Chrysippus by any name but Chesippus. And
you yourself a little before, when you were numbering up a senate, as we
may call them, of philosophers, scrupled not to say that the most
eminent men talked like foolish, visionary dotards. Certainly,
therefore, if they have all erred in regard to the nature of the Gods,
it is to be feared there are no such beings. What you deliver on that
head are all whimsical notions, and not worthy the consideration even of
old women. For you do not seem to be in the least aware what a task you
draw on yourselves, if you should prevail on us to grant that the same
form is common to Gods and men. The Deity would then require the same
trouble in dressing, and the same care of the body, that mankind does.
He must walk, run, lie down, lean, sit, hold, speak, and discourse. You
need not be told the consequence of making the Gods male and female.
Therefore I cannot sufficiently wonder how this chief of yours came to
entertain these strange opinions. But you constantly insist on the
certainty of this tenet, that the Deity is both happy and immortal.
Supposing he is so, would his happiness be less perfect if he had not
two feet? Or cannot that blessedness or beatitude—call it which you
will (they are both harsh terms, but we must mollify them by use)—can
it not, I say, exist in that sun, or in this world, or in some eternal
mind that has not human shape or limbs? All you say against it is, that
you never saw any happiness in the sun or the world. What, then? Did you
ever see any world but this? No, you will say. Why, therefore, do you
presume to assert that there are not only six hundred thousand worlds,
but that they are innumerable? Reason tells you so. Will not reason tell
you likewise that as, in our inquiries into the most excellent nature,
we find none but the divine nature can be happy and eternal, so the same
divine nature surpasses us in
244excellence of mind; and as in mind, so in body? Why,
therefore, as we are inferior in all other respects, should
we be equal in form? For human virtue approaches
nearer to the divinity than human form.
XXXV. To return to the subject I was upon. What
can be more childish than to assert that there are no such
creatures as are generated in the Red Sea or in India?
The most curious inquirer cannot arrive at the knowledge
of all those creatures which inhabit the earth, sea, fens, and
rivers; and shall we deny the existence of them because
we never saw them? That similitude which you are so
very fond of is nothing to the purpose. Is not a dog like
a wolf? And, as Ennius says,
The monkey, filthiest beast, how like to man!
Yet they differ in nature. No beast has more sagacity
than an elephant; yet where can you find any of a larger
size? I am speaking here of beasts. But among men, do
we not see a disparity of manners in persons very much
alike, and a similitude of manners in persons unlike? If
this sort of argument were once to prevail, Velleius, observe
what it would lead to. You have laid it down as
certain that reason cannot possibly reside in any but the
human form. Another may affirm that it can exist in none
but a terrestrial being; in none but a being that is born,
that grows up, and receives instruction, and that consists
of a soul, and an infirm and perishable body; in short, in
none but a mortal man. But if you decline those opinions,
why should a single form disturb you? You perceive
that man is possessed of reason and understanding, with
all the infirmities which I have mentioned interwoven
with his being; abstracted from which, you nevertheless
know God, you say, if the lineaments do but remain.
This is not talking considerately, but at a venture; for
surely you did not think what an encumbrance anything
superfluous or useless is, not only in a man, but a tree.
How troublesome it is to have a finger too much! And
why so? Because neither use nor ornament requires
more than five; but your Deity has not only a finger more
than he wants, but a head, a neck, shoulders, sides, a
paunch, back, hams, hands, feet, thighs, and legs. Are
245these parts necessary to immortality? Are they conducive
to the existence of the Deity? Is the face itself of
use? One would rather say so of the brain, the heart,
the lights, and the liver; for these are the seats of life.
The features of the face contribute nothing to the preservation
of it.
XXXVI. You censured those who, beholding those excellent
and stupendous works, the world, and its respective
parts—the heaven, the earth, the seas—and the splendor
with which they are adorned; who, contemplating the
sun, moon, and stars; and who, observing the maturity
and changes of the seasons, and vicissitudes of times, inferred
from thence that there must be some excellent and
eminent essence that originally made, and still moves, directs,
and governs them. Suppose they should mistake in
their conjecture, yet I see what they aim at. But what is
that great and noble work which appears to you to be the
effect of a divine mind, and from which you conclude that
there are Gods? “I have,” say you, “a certain information
of a Deity imprinted in my mind.” Of a bearded
Jupiter, I suppose, and a helmeted Minerva.
But do you really imagine them to be such? How
much better are the notions of the ignorant vulgar, who
not only believe the Deities have members like ours, but
that they make use of them; and therefore they assign
them a bow and arrows, a spear, a shield, a trident, and
lightning; and though they do not behold the actions of
the Gods, yet they cannot entertain a thought of a Deity
doing nothing. The Egyptians (so much ridiculed) held
no beasts to be sacred, except on account of some advantage
which they had received from them. The ibis, a very
large bird, with strong legs and a horny long beak, destroys
a great number of serpents. These birds keep
Egypt from pestilential diseases by killing and devouring
the flying serpents brought from the deserts of Lybia by
the south-west wind, which prevents the mischief that
may attend their biting while alive, or any infection when
dead. I could speak of the advantage of the ichneumon,
the crocodile, and the cat; but I am unwilling to be tedious;
yet I will conclude with observing that the barbarians
paid divine honors to beasts because of the benefits
246they received from them; whereas your
Gods not only confer no benefit, but are idle, and do no single act of
any description whatever.
XXXVII. “They have nothing to do,” your teacher says. Epicurus truly,
like indolent boys, thinks nothing preferable to idleness; yet those
very boys, when they have a holiday, entertain themselves in some
sportive exercise. But we are to suppose the Deity in such an inactive
state that if he should move we may justly fear he would be no longer
happy. This doctrine divests the Gods of motion and operation; besides,
it encourages men to be lazy, as they are by this taught to believe that
the least labor is incompatible even with divine felicity.
But let it be as you would have it, that the Deity is in the form and
image of a man. Where is his abode? Where is his habitation? Where is
the place where he is to be found? What is his course of life? And what
is it that constitutes the happiness which you assert that he enjoys?
For it seems necessary that a being who is to be happy must use and
enjoy what belongs to him. And with regard to place, even those natures
which are inanimate have each their proper stations assigned to them: so
that the earth is the lowest; then water is next above the earth; the
air is above the water; and fire has the highest situation of all
allotted to it. Some creatures inhabit the earth, some the water, and
some, of an amphibious nature, live in both. There are some, also, which
are thought to be born in fire, and which often appear fluttering in
burning furnaces.
In the first place, therefore, I ask you, Where is the habitation of
your Deity? Secondly, What motive is it that stirs him from his place,
supposing he ever moves? And, lastly, since it is peculiar to animated
beings to have an inclination to something that is agreeable to their
several natures, what is it that the Deity affects, and to what purpose
does he exert the motion of his mind and reason? In short, how is he
happy? how eternal? Whichever of these points you touch upon, I am
afraid you will come lamely off. For there is never a proper end to
reasoning which proceeds on a false foundation; for you asserted
likewise that the form of the Deity is perceptible by the mind, but 247not
by sense; that it is neither solid, nor invariable in number; that it is
to be discerned by similitude and transition, and that a constant supply
of images is perpetually flowing on from innumerable atoms, on which our
minds are intent; so that we from that conclude that divine nature to be
happy and everlasting.
XXXVIII. What, in the name of those Deities concerning whom we are now
disputing, is the meaning of all this? For if they exist only in
thought, and have no solidity nor substance, what difference can there
be between thinking of a Hippocentaur and thinking of a Deity? Other
philosophers call every such conformation of the mind a vain motion; but
you term it “the approach and entrance of images into the mind.” Thus,
when I imagine that I behold T. Gracchus haranguing the people in the
Capitol, and collecting their suffrages concerning M. Octavius, I call
that a vain motion of the mind: but you affirm that the images of
Gracchus and Octavius are present, which are only conveyed to my mind
when they have arrived at the Capitol. The case is the same, you say, in
regard to the Deity, with the frequent representation of which the mind
is so affected that from thence it may be clearly understood that the
Gods98 are happy and eternal.
Let it be granted that there are images by which the mind is affected,
yet it is only a certain form that occurs; and why must that form be
pronounced happy? why eternal? But what are those images you talk of,
or whence do they proceed? This loose manner of arguing is taken from
Democritus; but he is reproved by many people for it; nor can you derive
any conclusions from it: the whole system is weak and imperfect. For
what can be more improbable than that the images of Homer, Archilochus,
Romulus, Numa, Pythagoras, and Plato should come into my mind, and yet
not in the form in which they existed? How, therefore, can they be those
persons? And whose images are they? Aristotle tells us that there never
was such a person as Orpheus the poet;99 and it is said that the verse
248called Orphic verse was the invention of Cercops, a Pythagorean; yet
Orpheus, that is to say, the image of him, as you will have it, often
runs in my head. What is the reason that I entertain one idea of the
figure of the same person, and you another? Why do we image to ourselves
such things as never had any existence, and which never can have, such
as Scyllas and Chimæras? Why do we frame ideas of men, countries, and
cities which we never saw? How is it that the very first moment that I
choose I can form representations of them in my mind? How is it that
they come to me, even in my sleep, without being called or sought after?
XXXIX. The whole affair, Velleius, is ridiculous. You do not impose
images on our eyes only, but on our minds. Such is the privilege which
you have assumed of talking nonsense with impunity. But there is, you
say, a transition of images flowing on in great crowds in such a way
that out of many some one at least must be perceived! I should be
ashamed of my incapacity to understand this if you, who assert it, could
comprehend it yourselves; for how do you prove that these images are
continued in uninterrupted motion? Or, if uninterrupted, still how do
you prove them to be eternal? There is a constant supply, you say, of
innumerable atoms. But must they, for that reason, be all eternal? To
elude this, you have recourse to equilibration (for so, with your leave,
I will call your бјёПѓОїОЅОїОјбЅ·О±),100 and say that as there is a sort of
nature mortal, so there must also be a sort which is immortal. By the
same rule, as there are men mortal, there are men immortal; and as some
arise from the earth, some must arise from the water also; and as there
are causes which destroy, there must likewise be causes which preserve.
Be it as you say; but let those causes preserve which have existence
themselves. I cannot conceive these your Gods to have any. But how does
all this face of things arise from atomic corpuscles? Were there any
such atoms (as there 249are not), they might perhaps impel one another,
and be jumbled together in their motion; but they could never be able to
impart form, or figure, or color, or animation, so that you by no means
demonstrate the immortality of your Deity.
XL. Let us now inquire into his happiness. It is certain that without
virtue there can be no happiness; but virtue consists in action: now
your Deity does nothing; therefore he is void of virtue, and
consequently cannot be happy. What sort of life does he lead? He has a
constant supply, you say, of good things, without any intermixture of
bad. What are those good things? Sensual pleasures, no doubt; for you
know no delight of the mind but what arises from the body, and returns
to it. I do not suppose, Velleius, that you are like some of the
Epicureans, who are ashamed of those expressions of Epicurus,101 in
which he openly avows that he has no idea of any good separate from
wanton and obscene pleasures, which, without a blush, he names
distinctly. What food, therefore, what drink, what variety of music or
flowers, what kind of pleasures of touch, what odors, will you offer to
the Gods to fill them with pleasures? The poets indeed provide them with
banquets of nectar and ambrosia, and a Hebe or a Ganymede to serve up
the cup. But what is it, Epicurus, that you do for them? For I do not
see from whence your Deity should have those things, nor how he could
use them. Therefore the nature of man is better constituted for a happy
life than the nature of the Gods, because men enjoy various kinds of
pleasures; but you look on all those pleasures as superficial which
delight the senses only by a titillation, as Epicurus calls it. Where is
to be the end of this trifling? Even Philo, who followed the Academy,
could not bear to hear the soft and luscious delights of the Epicureans
despised; for with his admirable memory he perfectly remembered and used
to repeat many sentences of Epicurus in the very words in which they
were written. He likewise used to quote many, 250which were more gross,
from Metrodorus, the sage colleague of Epicurus, who blamed his brother
Timocrates because he would not allow that everything which had any
reference to a happy life was to be measured by the belly; nor has he
said this once only, but often. You grant what I say, I perceive; for
you know it to be true. I can produce the books, if you should deny it;
but I am not now reproving you for referring all things to the standard
of pleasure: that is another question. What I am now showing is, that
your Gods are destitute of pleasure; and therefore, according to your
own manner of reasoning, they are not happy.
XLI. But they are free from pain. Is that sufficient for beings who are
supposed to enjoy all good things and the most supreme felicity? The
Deity, they say, is constantly meditating on his own happiness, for he
has no other idea which can possibly occupy his mind. Consider a little;
reflect what a figure the Deity would make if he were to be idly
thinking of nothing through all eternity but “It is very well with me,
and I am happy;” nor do I see why this happy Deity should not fear being
destroyed, since, without any intermission, he is driven and agitated by
an everlasting incursion of atoms, and since images are constantly
floating off from him. Your Deity, therefore, is neither happy nor
eternal.
Epicurus, it seems, has written books concerning sanctity and piety
towards the Gods. But how does he speak on these subjects? You would say
that you were listening to Coruncanius or Scævola, the high-priests, and
not to a man who tore up all religion by the roots, and who overthrew
the temples and altars of the immortal Gods; not, indeed, with hands,
like Xerxes, but with arguments; for what reason is there for your
saying that men ought to worship the Gods, when the Gods not only do not
regard men, but are entirely careless of everything, and absolutely do
nothing at all?
But they are, you say, of so glorious and excellent a nature that a wise
man is induced by their excellence to adore them. Can there be any glory
or excellence in that nature which only contemplates its own happiness,
and neither will do, nor does, nor ever did anything? Besides, 251what
piety is due to a being from whom you receive nothing? Or how can you,
or any one else, be indebted to him who bestows no benefits? For piety
is only justice towards the Gods; but what right have they to it, when
there is no communication whatever between the Gods and men? And
sanctity is the knowledge of how we ought to worship them; but I do not
understand why they are to be worshipped, if we are neither to receive
nor expect any good from them.
XLII. And why should we worship them from an admiration only of that
nature in which we can behold nothing excellent? and as for that freedom
from superstition, which you are in the habit of boasting of so much, it
is easy to be free from that feeling when you have renounced all belief
in the power of the Gods; unless, indeed, you imagine that Diagoras or
Theodorus, who absolutely denied the being of the Gods, could possibly
be superstitious. I do not suppose that even Protagoras could, who
doubted whether there were Gods or not. The opinions of these
philosophers are not only destructive of superstition, which arises from
a vain fear of the Gods, but of religion also, which consists in a pious
adoration of them.
What think you of those who have asserted that the whole doctrine
concerning the immortal Gods was the invention of politicians, whose
view was to govern that part of the community by religion which reason
could not influence? Are not their opinions subversive of all religion?
Or what religion did Prodicus the Chian leave to men, who held that
everything beneficial to human life should be numbered among the Gods?
Were not they likewise void of religion who taught that the Deities, at
present the object of our prayers and adoration, were valiant,
illustrious, and mighty men who arose to divinity after death?
Euhemerus, whom our Ennius translated, and followed more than other
authors, has particularly advanced this doctrine, and treated of the
deaths and burials of the Gods; can he, then, be said to have confirmed
religion, or, rather, to have totally subverted it? I shall say nothing
of that sacred and august Eleusina, into whose mysteries the most
distant nations were initiated, 252nor of the solemnities in Samothrace,
or in Lemnos, secretly resorted to by night, and surrounded by thick and
shady groves; which, if they were properly explained, and reduced to
reasonable principles, would rather explain the nature of things than
discover the knowledge of the Gods.
XLIII. Even that great man Democritus, from whose fountains Epicurus
watered his little garden, seems to me to be very inferior to his usual
acuteness when speaking about the nature of the Gods. For at one time he
thinks that there are images endowed with divinity, inherent in the
universality of things; at another, that the principles and minds
contained in the universe are Gods; then he attributes divinity to
animated images, employing themselves in doing us good or harm; and,
lastly, he speaks of certain images of such vast extent that they
encompass the whole outside of the universe; all which opinions are more
worthy of the country102 of Democritus than of Democritus himself; for
who can frame in his mind any ideas of such images? who can admire them?
who can think they merit a religious adoration?
But Epicurus, when he divests the Gods of the power of doing good,
extirpates all religion from the minds of men; for though he says the
divine nature is the best and the most excellent of all natures, he will
not allow it to be susceptible of any benevolence, by which he destroys
the chief and peculiar attribute of the most perfect being. For what is
better and more excellent than goodness and beneficence? To refuse your
Gods that quality is to say that no man is any object of their favor,
and no Gods either; that they neither love nor esteem any one; in short,
that they not only give themselves no trouble about us, but even look on
each other with the greatest indifference.
XLIV. How much more reasonable is the doctrine of the Stoics, whom you
censure? It is one of their maxims that the wise are friends to the
wise, though unknown to each other; for as nothing is more amiable than
virtue, he who possesses it is worthy our love, to whatever country 253he
belongs. But what evils do your principles bring, when you make good
actions and benevolence the marks of imbecility! For, not to mention the
power and nature of the Gods, you hold that even men, if they had no
need of mutual assistance, would be neither courteous nor beneficent. Is
there no natural charity in the dispositions of good men? The very name
of love, from which friendship is derived, is dear to men;103 and if
friendship is to centre in our own advantage only, without regard to him
whom we esteem a friend, it cannot be called friendship, but a sort of
traffic for our own profit. Pastures, lands, and herds of cattle are
valued in the same manner on account of the profit we gather from them;
but charity and friendship expect no return. How much more reason have
we to think that the Gods, who want nothing, should love each other, and
employ themselves about us! If it were not so, why should we pray to or
adore them? Why do the priests preside over the altars, and the augurs
over the auspices? What have we to ask of the Gods, and why do we prefer
our vows to them?
But Epicurus, you say, has written a book concerning sanctity. A
trifling performance by a man whose wit is not so remarkable in it, as
the unrestrained license of writing which he has permitted himself; for
what sanctity can there be if the Gods take no care of human affairs? Or
how can that nature be called animated which neither regards nor
performs anything? Therefore our friend Posidonius has well observed, in
his fifth book of the Nature of the Gods, that Epicurus believed there
were no Gods, and that what he had said about the immortal Gods was only
said from a desire to avoid unpopularity. He could not be so weak as to
imagine that the Deity has only the outward features of a simple mortal,
without any real solidity; that he has all the members of a man, without
the least power to use them—a certain unsubstantial pellucid being,
neither favorable nor beneficial to any one, neither regarding nor doing
anything. There can be no such being in nature; and as Epicurus said
this plainly, he allows 254the Gods in words, and destroys them in fact;
and if the Deity is truly such a being that he shows no favor, no
benevolence to mankind, away with him! For why should I entreat him to
be propitious? He can be propitious to none, since, as you say, all his
favor and benevolence are the effects of imbecility.
BOOK II.
I.
When Cotta had thus concluded, Velleius replied: I certainly was
inconsiderate to engage in argument with an Academician who is likewise
a rhetorician. I should not have feared an Academician without
eloquence, nor a rhetorician without that philosophy, however eloquent
he might be; for I am never puzzled by an empty flow of words, nor by
the most subtle reasonings delivered without any grace of oratory. But
you, Cotta, have excelled in both. You only wanted the assembly and the
judges. However, enough of this at present. Now, let us hear what
Lucilius has to say, if it is agreeable to him.
I had much rather, says Balbus, hear Cotta resume his discourse, and
demonstrate the true Gods with the same eloquence which he made use of
to explode the false; for, on such a subject, the loose, unsettled
doctrine of the Academy does not become a philosopher, a priest, a
Cotta, whose opinions should be, like those we hold, firm and certain.
Epicurus has been more than sufficiently refuted; but I would willingly
hear your own sentiments, Cotta.
Do you forget, replies Cotta, what I at first said—that it is easier
for me, especially on this point, to explain what opinions those are
which I do not hold, rather than what those are which I do? Nay, even if
I did feel some certainty on any particular point, yet, after having
been so diffuse myself already, I would prefer now hearing you speak in
your turn. I submit, says Balbus, and will be as brief as I possibly
can; for as you have confuted the errors of Epicurus, my part in the
dispute will be the shorter.
255Our sect divide the whole question
concerning the immortal Gods into four parts. First, they prove that
there are Gods; secondly, of what character and nature they are;
thirdly, that the universe is governed by them; and, lastly, that they
exercise a superintendence over human affairs. But in this present
discussion let us confine ourselves to the first two articles, and defer
the third and fourth till another opportunity, as they require more time
to discuss. By no means, says Cotta, for we have time enough on our
hands; besides that, we are now discussing a subject which should be
preferred even to serious business.
II. The first point, then, says Lucilius, I think needs no discourse to
prove it; for what can be so plain and evident, when we behold the
heavens and contemplate the celestial bodies, as the existence of some
supreme, divine intelligence, by which all these things are governed?
Were it otherwise, Ennius would not, with a universal approbation, have
said,
Look up to the refulgent heaven above,
Which all men call, unanimously, Jove.
This is Jupiter, the governor of the world, who rules all things with
his nod, and is, as the same Ennius adds,
——of Gods and men the sire,
104
an omnipresent and omnipotent God. And if any one doubts this, I really
do not understand why the same man may not also doubt whether there is a
sun or not. For what can possibly be more evident than this? And if it
were not a truth universally impressed on the minds of men, the belief
in it would never have been so firm; nor would it have been, as it is,
increased by length of years, nor would it have gathered strength and
stability through every age. And, in truth, we see that other opinions,
being false and groundless, have already fallen into oblivion by lapse
of time. Who now believes in Hippocentaurs and 256Chimæras? Or what old
woman is now to be found so weak and ignorant as to stand in fear of
those infernal monsters which once so terrified mankind? For time
destroys the fictions of error and opinion, while it confirms the
determinations of nature and of truth. And therefore it is that, both
among us and among other nations, sacred institutions and the divine
worship of the Gods have been strengthened and improved from time to
time. And this is not to be imputed to chance or folly, but to the
frequent appearance of the Gods themselves. In the war with the Latins,
when A. Posthumius, the dictator, attacked Octavius Mamilius, the
Tusculan, at Regillus, Castor and Pollux were seen fighting in our army
on horseback; and since that the same offspring of Tyndarus gave notice
of the defeat of Perses; for as P. Vatienus, the grandfather of the
present young man of that name, was coming in the night to Rome from his
government of Reate, two young men on white horses appeared to him, and
told him that King105 Perses was that day taken prisoner. This news he
carried to the senate, who immediately threw him into prison for
speaking inconsiderately on a state affair; but when it was confirmed by
letters from Paullus, he was recompensed by the senate with land and
immunities.106 Nor do we forget when the Locrians defeated the people
of Crotone, in a great battle on the banks of the river Sagra, that it
was known the same day at the Olympic Games. The voices of the Fauns
have been often heard, and Deities have appeared in forms so visible
that they have compelled every one who is not senseless, or hardened in
impiety, to confess the presence of the Gods.
III. What do predictions and foreknowledge of future events indicate,
but that such future events are shown, pointed out, portended, and
foretold to men? From whence they are called omens, signs, portents,
prodigies. But though we should esteem fabulous what is said of
257Mopsus,107 Tiresias,108 Amphiaraus,109 Calchas,110 and
Helenus111 (who would not have been delivered down to us as augurs
even in fable if their art had been despised), may we not be
sufficiently apprised of the power of the Gods by domestic examples?
Will not the temerity of P. Claudius, in the first Punic war, affect us?
who, when the poultry were let out of the coop and would not feed,
ordered them to be thrown into the water, and, joking even upon the
Gods, said, with a sneer, “Let them drink, since they will not eat;”
which piece of ridicule, being followed by a victory over his fleet,
cost him many tears, and brought great calamity on the Roman people. Did
not his colleague Junius, in the same war, lose his fleet in a tempest
by disregarding the auspices? Claudius, therefore, was condemned by the
people, and Junius killed himself. CЕ“lius says that P. Flaminius, from
his neglect of religion, fell at Thrasimenus; a loss which the public
severely felt. By these instances of calamity we may be assured that
Rome owes her grandeur and success to the conduct of those who were
tenacious of their religious duties; and if we compare ourselves to our
neighbors, we shall find that we are infinitely distinguished above
foreign nations by our zeal for religious ceremonies, though in other
things we may be only equal to them, and in other respects even inferior
to them.
Ought we to contemn Attius Navius’s staff, with which 258he divided the
regions of the vine to find his sow?112 I should despise it, if I were
not aware that King Hostilius had carried on most important wars in
deference to his auguries; but by the negligence of our nobility the
discipline of the augury is now omitted, the truth of the auspices
despised, and only a mere form observed; so that the most important
affairs of the commonwealth, even the wars, on which the public safety
depends, are conducted without any auspices; the Peremnia113 are
discussed; no part of the Acumina114 performed; no select men are
called to witness to the military testaments;115 our generals now
begin their wars as soon as they have arranged the Auspicia. The force
of religion was so great among our ancestors that some of their
commanders have, with their faces veiled, and with the solemn, formal
expressions of religion, sacrificed themselves to the immortal Gods to
save their country.116 I could mention many of the Sibylline
prophecies, and many answers of the haruspices, to confirm those things,
which ought not to be doubted.
IV. For example: our augurs and the Etrurian haruspices saw the truth of
their art established when P. Scipio and C. Figulus were consuls; for as
Tiberius Gracchus, who was a second time consul, wished to proceed to a
259fresh election, the first Rogator,117 as he was collecting the
suffrages, fell down dead on the spot. Gracchus nevertheless went on
with the assembly, but perceiving that this accident had a religious
influence on the people, he brought the affair before the senate. The
senate thought fit to refer it to those who usually took cognizance of
such things. The haruspices were called, and declared that the man who
had acted as Rogator of the assembly had no right to do so; to which, as
I have heard my father say, he replied with great warmth, Have I no
right, who am consul, and augur, and favored by the Auspicia? And shall
you, who are Tuscans and Barbarians, pretend that you have authority
over the Roman Auspicia, and a right to give judgment in matters
respecting the formality of our assemblies? Therefore, he then commanded
them to withdraw; but not long afterward he wrote from his province118
to the college of augurs, acknowledging that in reading the books119
he remembered that he had illegally chosen a place for his tent in the
gardens of Scipio, and had afterward entered the PomЕ“rium, in order to
hold a senate, but that in repassing the same PomЕ“rium he had forgotten
to take the auspices; and that, therefore, the consuls had been created
informally. The augurs laid the case before the senate. The senate
decreed that they should resign their charge, and so they accordingly
abdicated. What greater example need we seek for? The wisest, perhaps
the most excellent of men, chose to confess his fault, which he might
have concealed, rather than leave the public the least atom of religious
guilt; and the consuls chose to quit the highest office in the State,
rather than fill it for a moment in defiance of religion. How great is
the reputation of the augurs!
And is not the art of the soothsayers divine? And must not every one who
sees what innumerable instances of the same kind there are confess the
existence of the 260Gods? For they who have interpreters must certainly
exist themselves; now, there are interpreters of the Gods; therefore we
must allow there are Gods. But it may be said, perhaps, that all
predictions are not accomplished. We may as well conclude there is no
art of physic, because all sick persons do not recover. The Gods show us
signs of future events; if we are occasionally deceived in the results,
it is not to be imputed to the nature of the Gods, but to the
conjectures of men. All nations agree that there are Gods; the opinion
is innate, and, as it were, engraved in the minds of all men. The only
point in dispute among us is, what they are.
V. Their existence no one denies. Cleanthes, one of our sect, imputes
the way in which the idea of the Gods is implanted in the minds of men
to four causes. The first is that which I just now mentioned—the
foreknowledge of future things. The second is the great advantages which
we enjoy from the temperature of the air, the fertility of the earth,
and the abundance of various benefits of other kinds. The third cause is
deduced from the terror with which the mind is affected by thunder,
tempests, storms, snow, hail, devastation, pestilence, earthquakes often
attended with hideous noises, showers of stones, and rain like drops of
blood; by rocks and sudden openings of the earth; by monstrous births of
men and beasts; by meteors in the air, and blazing stars, by the Greeks
called cometæ, by us crinitæ, the appearance of which, in the late
Octavian war,120 were foreboders of great calamities; by two suns,
which, as I have heard my father say, happened in the consulate of
Tuditanus and Aquillius, and in which year also another sun (P.
Africanus) was extinguished. These things terrified mankind, and raised
in them a firm belief of the existence of some celestial and divine
power.
His fourth cause, and that the strongest, is drawn from the regularity
of the motion and revolution of the heavens, the distinctness, variety,
beauty, and order of the sun, moon, and all the stars, the appearance
only of which is sufficient to convince us they are not the effects of
chance; as when we enter into a house, or school, or court, and observe
the exact order, discipline, and method of it, we cannot suppose 261that
it is so regulated without a cause, but must conclude that there is some
one who commands, and to whom obedience is paid. It is quite impossible
for us to avoid thinking that the wonderful motions, revolutions, and
order of those many and great bodies, no part of which is impaired by
the countless and infinite succession of ages, must be governed and
directed by some supreme intelligent being.
VI. Chrysippus, indeed, had a very penetrating genius; yet such is the
doctrine which he delivers, that he seems rather to have been instructed
by nature than to owe it to any discovery of his own. “If,” says he,
“there is anything in the universe which no human reason, ability, or
power can make, the being who produced it must certainly be preferable
to man. Now, celestial bodies, and all those things which proceed in any
eternal order, cannot be made by man; the being who made them is
therefore preferable to man. What, then, is that being but a God? If
there be no such thing as a Deity, what is there better than man, since
he only is possessed of reason, the most excellent of all things? But it
is a foolish piece of vanity in man to think there is nothing preferable
to him. There is, therefore, something preferable; consequently, there
is certainly a God.”
When you behold a large and beautiful house, surely no one can persuade
you it was built for mice and weasels, though you do not see the master;
and would it not, therefore, be most manifest folly to imagine that a
world so magnificently adorned, with such an immense variety of
celestial bodies of such exquisite beauty, and that the vast sizes and
magnitude of the sea and land were intended as the abode of man, and not
as the mansion of the immortal Gods? Do we not also plainly see this,
that all the most elevated regions are the best, and that the earth is
the lowest region, and is surrounded with the grossest air? so that as
we perceive that in some cities and countries the capacities of men are
naturally duller, from the thickness of the climate, so mankind in
general are affected by the heaviness of the air which surrounds the
earth, the grossest region of the world.
Yet even from this inferior intelligence of man we may 262discover the
existence of some intelligent agent that is divine, and wiser than
ourselves; for, as Socrates says in Xenophon, from whence had man his
portion of understanding? And, indeed, if any one were to push his
inquiries about the moisture and heat which is diffused through the
human body, and the earthy kind of solidity existing in our entrails,
and that soul by which we breathe, and to ask whence we derived them, it
would be plain that we have received one thing from the earth, another
from liquid, another from fire, and another from that air which we
inhale every time that we breathe.
VII. But where did we find that which excels all these things—I mean
reason, or (if you please, in other terms) the mind, understanding,
thought, prudence; and from whence did we receive it? Shall the world be
possessed of every other perfection, and be destitute of this one, which
is the most important and valuable of all? But certainly there is
nothing better, or more excellent, or more beautiful than the world; and
not only there is nothing better, but we cannot even conceive anything
superior to it; and if reason and wisdom are the greatest of all
perfections, they must necessarily be a part of what we all allow to be
the most excellent.
Who is not compelled to admit the truth of what I assert by that
agreeable, uniform, and continued agreement of things in the universe?
Could the earth at one season be adorned with flowers, at another be
covered with snow? Or, if such a number of things regulated their own
changes, could the approach and retreat of the sun in the summer and
winter solstices be so regularly known and calculated? Could the flux
and reflux of the sea and the height of the tides be affected by the
increase or wane of the moon? Could the different courses of the stars
be preserved by the uniform movement of the whole heaven? Could these
things subsist, I say, in such a harmony of all the parts of the
universe without the continued influence of a divine spirit?
If these points are handled in a free and copious manner, as I purpose
to do, they will be less liable to the cavils of the Academics; but the
narrow, confined way in which Zeno reasoned upon them laid them more
open to 263objection; for as running streams are seldom or never tainted,
while standing waters easily grow corrupt, so a fluency of expression
washes away the censures of the caviller, while the narrow limits of a
discourse which is too concise is almost defenceless; for the arguments
which I am enlarging upon are thus briefly laid down by Zeno:
VIII. “That which reasons is superior to that which does not; nothing is
superior to the world; the world, therefore, reasons.” By the same rule
the world may be proved to be wise, happy, and eternal; for the
possession of all these qualities is superior to the want of them; and
nothing is superior to the world; the inevitable consequence of which
argument is, that the world, therefore, is a Deity. He goes on: “No part
of anything void of sense is capable of perception; some parts of the
world have perception; the world, therefore, has sense.” He proceeds,
and pursues the argument closely. “Nothing,” says he, “that is destitute
itself of life and reason can generate a being possessed of life and
reason; but the world does generate beings possessed of life and reason;
the world, therefore, is not itself destitute of life and reason.”
He concludes his argument in his usual manner with a simile: “If
well-tuned pipes should spring out of the olive, would you have the
slightest doubt that there was in the olive-tree itself some kind of
skill and knowledge? Or if the plane-tree could produce harmonious
lutes, surely you would infer, on the same principle, that music was
contained in the plane-tree. Why, then, should we not believe the world
is a living and wise being, since it produces living and wise beings out
of itself?”
IX. But as I have been insensibly led into a length of discourse beyond
my first design (for I said that, as the existence of the Gods was
evident to all, there was no need of any long oration to prove it), I
will demonstrate it by reasons deduced from the nature of things. For it
is a fact that all beings which take nourishment and increase contain in
themselves a power of natural heat, without which they could neither be
nourished nor increase. For everything which is of a warm and fiery
character is agitated and stirred up by its own motion. But that which
is nourished and grows is influenced by a certain regular 264and equable
motion. And as long as this motion remains in us, so long does sense and
life remain; but the moment that it abates and is extinguished, we
ourselves decay and perish.
By arguments like these, Cleanthes shows how great is the power of heat
in all bodies. He observes that there is no food so gross as not to be
digested in a night and a day; and that even in the excrementitious
parts, which nature rejects, there remains a heat. The veins and
arteries seem, by their continual quivering, to resemble the agitation
of fire; and it has often been observed when the heart of an animal is
just plucked from the body that it palpitates with such visible motion
as to resemble the rapidity of fire. Everything, therefore, that has
life, whether it be animal or vegetable, owes that life to the heat
inherent in it; it is this nature of heat which contains in itself the
vital power which extends throughout the whole world. This will appear
more clearly on a more close explanation of this fiery quality, which
pervades all things.
Every division, then, of the world (and I shall touch upon the most
considerable) is sustained by heat; and first it may be observed in
earthly substances that fire is produced from stones by striking or
rubbing one against another; that “the warm earth smokes”121 when just
turned up, and that water is drawn warm from well-springs; and this is
most especially the case in the winter season, because there is a great
quantity of heat contained in the caverns of the earth; and this becomes
more dense in the winter, and on that account confines more closely the
innate heat which is discoverable in the earth.
X. It would require a long dissertation, and many reasons would require
to be adduced, to show that all the seeds which the earth conceives, and
all those which it contains having been generated from itself, and fixed
in roots and trunks, derive all their origin and increase from the
temperature and regulation of heat. And that even every liquor has a
mixture of heat in it is plainly demonstrated by the effusion of water;
for it would not congeal by cold, nor become solid, as ice or snow, and
return again 265to its natural state, if it were not that, when heat is
applied to it, it again becomes liquefied and dissolved, and so diffuses
itself. Therefore, by northern and other cold winds it is frozen and
hardened, and in turn it dissolves and melts again by heat. The seas
likewise, we find, when agitated by winds, grow warm, so that from this
fact we may understand that there is heat included in that vast body of
water; for we cannot imagine it to be external and adventitious heat,
but such as is stirred up by agitation from the deep recesses of the
seas; and the same thing takes place with respect to our bodies, which
grow warm with motion and exercise.
And the very air itself, which indeed is the coldest element, is by no
means void of heat; for there is a great quantity, arising from the
exhalations of water, which appears to be a sort of steam occasioned by
its internal heat, like that of boiling liquors. The fourth part of the
universe is entirely fire, and is the source of the salutary and vital
heat which is found in the rest. From hence we may conclude that, as all
parts of the world are sustained by heat, the world itself also has such
a great length of time subsisted from the same cause; and so much the
more, because we ought to understand that that hot and fiery principle
is so diffused over universal nature that there is contained in it a
power and cause of generation and procreation, from which all animate
beings, and all those creatures of the vegetable world, the roots of
which are contained in the earth, must inevitably derive their origin
and their increase.
XI. It is nature, consequently, that continues and preserves the world,
and that, too, a nature which is not destitute of sense and reason; for
in every essence that is not simple, but composed of several parts,
there must be some predominant quality—as, for instance, the mind in
man, and in beasts something resembling it, from which arise all the
appetites and desires for anything. As for trees, and all the vegetable
produce of the earth, it is thought to be in their roots. I call that
the predominant quality,122 which 266the Greeks call бјЎОіОµОјОїОЅО№ОєбЅ№ОЅ; which
must and ought to be the most excellent quality, wherever it is found.
That, therefore, in which the prevailing quality of all nature resides
must be the most excellent of all things, and most worthy of the power
and pre-eminence over all things.
Now, we see that there is nothing in being that is not a part of the
universe; and as there are sense and reason in the parts of it, there
must therefore be these qualities, and these, too, in a more energetic
and powerful degree, in that part in which the predominant quality of
the world is found. The world, therefore, must necessarily be possessed
of wisdom; and that element, which embraces all things, must excel in
perfection of reason. The world, therefore, is a God, and the whole
power of the world is contained in that divine element.
The heat also of the world is more pure, clear, and lively, and,
consequently, better adapted to move the senses than the heat allotted
to us; and it vivifies and preserves all things within the compass of
our knowledge.
It is absurd, therefore, to say that the world, which is endued with a
perfect, free, pure, spirituous, and active heat, is not sensitive,
since by this heat men and beasts are preserved, and move, and think;
more especially since this heat of the world is itself the sole
principle of agitation, and has no external impulse, but is moved
spontaneously; for what can be more powerful than the world, which moves
and raises that heat by which it subsists?
XII. For let us listen to Plato, who is regarded as a God among
philosophers. He says that there are two sorts of motion, one innate and
the other external; and that that which is moved spontaneously is more
divine than that which is moved by another power. This self-motion he
places in the mind alone, and concludes that the first principle of
motion is derived from the mind. Therefore, since all motion arises from
the heat of the world, and that heat is not moved by the effect of any
external impulse, but of its own accord, it must necessarily be a mind;
from whence it follows that the world is animated.
On such reasoning is founded this opinion, that the world is possessed
of understanding, because it certainly has more perfections in itself
than any other nature; for 267as there is no part of our bodies so
considerable as the whole of us, so it is clear that there is no
particular portion of the universe equal in magnitude to the whole of
it; from whence it follows that wisdom must be an attribute of the
world; otherwise man, who is a part of it, and possessed of reason,
would be superior to the entire world.
And thus, if we proceed from the first rude, unfinished natures to the
most superior and perfect ones, we shall inevitably come at last to the
nature of the Gods. For, in the first place, we observe that those
vegetables which are produced out of the earth are supported by nature,
and she gives them no further supply than is sufficient to preserve them
by nourishing them and making them grow. To beasts she has given sense
and motion, and a faculty which directs them to what is wholesome, and
prompts them to shun what is noxious to them. On man she has conferred a
greater portion of her favor; inasmuch as she has added reason, by which
he is enabled to command his passions, to moderate some, and to subdue
others.
XIII. In the fourth and highest degree are those beings which are
naturally wise and good, who from the first moment of their existence
are possessed of right and consistent reason, which we must consider
superior to man and deserving to be attributed to a God; that is to say,
to the world, in which it is inevitable that that perfect and complete
reason should be inherent. Nor is it possible that it should be said
with justice that there is any arrangement of things in which there
cannot be something entire and perfect. For as in a vine or in beasts we
see that nature, if not prevented by some superior violence, proceeds by
her own appropriate path to her destined end; and as in painting,
architecture, and the other arts there is a point of perfection which is
attainable, and occasionally attained, so it is even much more necessary
that in universal nature there must be some complete and perfect result
arrived at. Many external accidents may happen to all other natures
which may impede their progress to perfection, but nothing can hinder
universal nature, because she is herself the ruler and governor of all
other natures. That, therefore, must be the fourth and most elevated
degree to which no other power can approach.
268But this degree is that on which the nature of all things is placed;
and since she is possessed of this, and she presides over all things,
and is subject to no possible impediment, the world must necessarily be
an intelligent and even a wise being. But how marvellously great is the
ignorance of those men who dispute the perfection of that nature which
encircles all things; or who, allowing it to be infinitely perfect, yet
deny it to be, in the first place, animated, then reasonable, and,
lastly, prudent and wise! For how without these qualities could it be
infinitely perfect? If it were like vegetables, or even like beasts,
there would be no more reason for thinking it extremely good than
extremely bad; and if it were possessed of reason, and had not wisdom
from the beginning, the world would be in a worse condition than man;
for man may grow wise, but the world, if it were destitute of wisdom
through an infinite space of time past, could never acquire it. Thus it
would be worse than man. But as that is absurd to imagine, the world
must be esteemed wise from all eternity, and consequently a Deity: since
there is nothing existing that is not defective, except the universe,
which is well provided, and fully complete and perfect in all its
numbers and parts.
XIV. For Chrysippus says, very acutely, that as the case is made for the
buckler, and the scabbard for the sword, so all things, except the
universe, were made for the sake of something else. As, for instance,
all those crops and fruits which the earth produces were made for the
sake of animals, and animals for man; as, the horse for carrying, the ox
for the plough, the dog for hunting and for a guard. But man himself was
born to contemplate and imitate the world, being in no wise perfect,
but, if I may so express myself, a particle of perfection; but the
world, as it comprehends all, and as nothing exists that is not
contained in it, is entirely perfect. In what, therefore, can it be
defective, since it is perfect? It cannot want understanding and reason,
for they are the most desirable of all qualities. The same Chrysippus
observes also, by the use of similitudes, that everything in its kind,
when arrived at maturity and perfection, is superior to that which is
not—as, a horse to a colt, a dog to a puppy, and a man to a boy—so
whatever 269is best in the whole universe must exist in some complete and
perfect being. But nothing is more perfect than the world, and nothing
better than virtue. Virtue, therefore, is an attribute of the world. But
human nature is not perfect, and nevertheless virtue is produced in it:
with how much greater reason, then, do we conceive it to be inherent in
the world! Therefore the world has virtue, and it is also wise, and
consequently a Deity.
XV. The divinity of the world being now clearly perceived, we must
acknowledge the same divinity to be likewise in the stars, which are
formed from the lightest and purest part of the ether, without a mixture
of any other matter; and, being altogether hot and transparent, we may
justly say they have life, sense, and understanding. And Cleanthes
thinks that it may be established by the evidence of two of our
senses—feeling and seeing—that they are entirely fiery bodies; for the
heat and brightness of the sun far exceed any other fire, inasmuch as it
enlightens the whole universe, covering such a vast extent of space, and
its power is such that we perceive that it not only warms, but often
even burns: neither of which it could do if it were not of a fiery
quality. Since, then, says he, the sun is a fiery body, and is nourished
by the vapors of the ocean (for no fire can continue without some
sustenance), it must be either like that fire which we use to warm us
and dress our food, or like that which is contained in the bodies of
animals.
And this fire, which the convenience of life requires, is the devourer
and consumer of everything, and throws into confusion and destroys
whatever it reaches. On the contrary, the corporeal heat is full of
life, and salutary; and vivifies, preserves, cherishes, increases, and
sustains all things, and is productive of sense; therefore, says he,
there can be no doubt which of these fires the sun is like, since it
causes all things in their respective kinds to flourish and arrive to
maturity; and as the fire of the sun is like that which is contained in
the bodies of animated beings, the sun itself must likewise be animated,
and so must the other stars also, which arise out of the celestial ardor
that we call the sky, or firmament.
As, then, some animals are generated in the earth, some 270in the water,
and some in the air, Aristotle123 thinks it ridiculous to imagine that
no animal is formed in that part of the universe which is the most
capable to produce them. But the stars are situated in the ethereal
space; and as this is an element the most subtle, whose motion is
continual, and whose force does not decay, it follows, of necessity,
that every animated being which is produced in it must be endowed with
the quickest sense and the swiftest motion. The stars, therefore, being
there generated, it is a natural inference to suppose them endued with
such a degree of sense and understanding as places them in the rank of
Gods.
XVI. For it may be observed that they who inhabit countries of a pure,
clear air have a quicker apprehension and a readier genius than those
who live in a thick, foggy climate. It is thought likewise that the
nature of a man’s diet has an effect on the mind; therefore it is
probable that the stars are possessed of an excellent understanding,
inasmuch as they are situated in the ethereal part of the universe, and
are nourished by the vapors of the earth and sea, which are purified by
their long passage to the heavens. But the invariable order and regular
motion of the stars plainly manifest their sense and understanding; for
all motion which seems to be conducted with reason and harmony supposes
an intelligent principle, that does not act blindly, or inconsistently,
or at random. And this regularity and consistent course of the stars
from all eternity indicates not any natural order, for it is pregnant
with sound reason, not fortune (for fortune, being a friend to change,
despises consistency). It follows, therefore, that they move
spontaneously by their own sense and divinity.
Aristotle also deserves high commendation for his observation that
everything that moves is either put in motion by natural impulse, or by
some external force, or of its own accord; and that the sun, and moon,
and all the stars move; but that those things which are moved by natural
impulse are either borne downward by their weight, or upward by their
lightness; neither of which things could be the case with the stars,
because they move in a regular circle and orbit. Nor can it be said that
271there is some superior force which causes the stars to be moved in a
manner contrary to nature. For what superior force can there be? It
follows, therefore, that their motion must be voluntary. And whoever is
convinced of this must discover not only great ignorance, but great
impiety likewise, if he denies the existence of the Gods; nor is the
difference great whether a man denies their existence, or deprives them
of all design and action; for whatever is wholly inactive seems to me
not to exist at all. Their existence, therefore, appears so plain that I
can scarcely think that man in his senses who denies it.
XVII. It now remains that we consider what is the character of the Gods.
Nothing is more difficult than to divert our thoughts and judgment from
the information of our corporeal sight, and the view of objects which
our eyes are accustomed to; and it is this difficulty which has had such
an influence on the unlearned, and on philosophers124 also who
resembled the unlearned multitude, that they have been unable to form
any idea of the immortal Gods except under the clothing of the human
figure; the weakness of which opinion Cotta has so well confuted that I
need not add my thoughts upon it. But as the previous idea which we have
of the Deity comprehends two things—first of all, that he is an
animated being; secondly, that there is nothing in all nature superior
to him—I do not see what can be more consistent with this idea and
preconception than to attribute a mind and divinity to the world,125
the most excellent of all beings.
Epicurus may be as merry with this notion as he pleases; a man not the
best qualified for a joker, as not having the wit and sense of his
country.126 Let him say that a voluble round Deity is to him
incomprehensible; yet he shall never dissuade me from a principle which
he himself approves, for he is of opinion there are Gods when he allows
that there must be a nature excellently perfect. But it is certain 272that
the world is most excellently perfect: nor is it to be doubted that
whatever has life, sense, reason, and understanding must excel that
which is destitute of these things. It follows, then, that the world has
life, sense, reason, and understanding, and is consequently a Deity. But
this shall soon be made more manifest by the operation of these very
things which the world causes.
XVIII. In the mean while, Velleius, let me entreat you not to be always
saying that we are utterly destitute of every sort of learning. The
cone, you say, the cylinder, and the pyramid, are more beautiful to you
than the sphere. This is to have different eyes from other men. But
suppose they are more beautiful to the sight only, which does not appear
to me, for I can see nothing more beautiful than that figure which
contains all others, and which has nothing rough in it, nothing
offensive, nothing cut into angles, nothing broken, nothing swelling,
and nothing hollow; yet as there are two forms most esteemed,127 the
globe in solids (for so the Greek word ПѓП†О±бї–ПЃО±, I think, should be
construed), and the circle, or orb, in planes (in Greek, ОєбЅ»ОєО»ОїП‚); and as
they only have an exact similitude of parts in which every extreme is
equally distant from the centre, what can we imagine in nature to be
more just and proper? But if you have never raked into this learned
dust128 to find out these things, surely, at all events, you natural
philosophers must know that equality of motion and invariable order
could not be preserved in any other figure. Nothing, therefore, can be
more illiterate than to assert, as you are in the habit of doing, that
it is doubtful whether the world is round or not, because it may
possibly be of another shape, and that there are innumerable worlds of
different forms; which Epicurus, if he ever had learned that two and two
are equal to four, would not have said. But while he judges of what is
best by his palate, he does not look up to the “palace of heaven,” as
Ennius calls it.
XIX. For as there are two sorts of stars,129 one kind of 273which
measure their journey from east to west by immutable stages, never in
the least varying from their usual course, while the other completes a
double revolution with an equally constant regularity; from each of
these facts we demonstrate the volubility of the world (which could not
possibly take place in any but a globular form) and the circular orbits
of the stars. And first of all the sun, which has the chief rank among
all the stars, is moved in such a manner that it fills the whole earth
with its light, and illuminates alternately one part of the earth, while
it leaves the other in darkness. The shadow of the earth interposing
causes night; and the intervals of night are equal to those of day. And
it is the regular approaches and retreats of the sun from which arise
the regulated degrees of cold and heat. His annual circuit is in three
hundred and sixty-five days, and nearly six hours more.130 At one time
he bends his course to the north, at another to the south, and thus
produces summer and winter, with the other two seasons, one of which
succeeds the decline of winter, and the other that of summer. And so to
these four changes of the seasons we attribute the origin and cause of
all the productions both of sea and land.
The moon completes the same course every month which the sun does in a
year. The nearer she approaches to the sun, the dimmer light does she
yield, and when most remote from it she shines with the fullest
brilliancy; nor are her figure and form only changed in her wane, but
her situation likewise, which is sometimes in the north and sometimes in
the south. By this course she has a sort of summer and winter solstices;
and by her influence she contributes to the nourishment and increase of
animated 274beings, and to the ripeness and maturity of all vegetables.
XX. But most worthy our admiration is the motion of those five stars
which are falsely called wandering stars; for they cannot be said to
wander which keep from all eternity their approaches and retreats, and
have all the rest of their motions, in one regular constant and
established order. What is yet more wonderful in these stars which we
are speaking of is that sometimes they appear, and sometimes they
disappear; sometimes they advance towards the sun, and sometimes they
retreat; sometimes they precede him, and sometimes follow him; sometimes
they move faster, sometimes slower, and sometimes they do not stir in
the least, but for a while stand still. From these unequal motions of
the planets, mathematicians have called that the “great year”131 in
which the sun, moon, and five wandering stars, having finished their
revolutions, are found in their original situation. In how long a time
this is effected is much disputed, but it must be a certain and definite
period. For the planet Saturn (called by the Greeks О¦О±бЅ·ОЅОїОЅ), which is
farthest from the earth, finishes his course in about thirty years; and
in his course there is something very singular, for sometimes he moves
before the sun, sometimes he keeps behind it; at one time lying hidden
in the night, at another again appearing in the morning; and ever
performing the same motions in the same space of time without any
alteration, so as to be for infinite ages regular in these courses.
Beneath this planet, and nearer the earth, is Jupiter, called О¦О±бЅіОёП‰ОЅ,
which passes the same orbit of the twelve signs132 in twelve years,
and goes through exactly the same variety in its course that the star of
Saturn does. Next to Jupiter is the planet Mars (in Greek, О П…ПЃбЅ№ОµО№П‚),
which finishes its revolution through the same orbit as the two
previously mentioned,133 in twenty-four months, wanting six days, as I
275imagine. Below this is Mercury (called by the Greeks ОЈП„бЅ·О»ОІП‰ОЅ), which
performs the same course in little less than a year, and is never
farther distant from the sun than the space of one sign, whether it
precedes or follows it. The lowest of the five planets, and nearest the
earth, is that of Venus (called in Greek О¦П‰ПѓП†бЅ№ПЃОїП‚). Before the rising of
the sun, it is called the morning-star, and after the setting, the
evening-star. It has the same revolution through the zodiac, both as to
latitude and longitude, with the other planets, in a year, and never is
more than two134 signs from the sun, whether it precedes or follows
it.
XXI. I cannot, therefore, conceive that this constant course of the
planets, this just agreement in such various motions through all
eternity, can be preserved without a mind, reason, and consideration;
and since we may perceive these qualities in the stars, we cannot but
place them in the rank of Gods. Those which are called the fixed stars
have the same indications of reason and prudence. Their motion is daily,
regular, and constant. They do not move with the sky, nor have they an
adhesion to the firmament, as they who are ignorant of natural
philosophy affirm. For the sky, which is thin, transparent, and suffused
with an equal heat, does not seem by its nature to have power to whirl
about the stars, or to be proper to contain them. The fixed stars,
therefore, have their own sphere, separate and free from any conjunction
with the sky. Their perpetual courses, with that admirable and
incredible regularity of theirs, so plainly declare a divine power and
mind to be in them, that he who cannot perceive that they are also
endowed with divine power must be incapable of all perception whatever.
In the heavens, therefore, there is nothing fortuitous, unadvised,
inconstant, or variable: all there is order, truth, reason, and
constancy; and all the things which are destitute of these qualities are
counterfeit, deceitful, and erroneous, and have their residence about
the earth135 beneath the moon, the lowest of all the planets. He,
therefore, 276who believes that this admirable order and almost incredible
regularity of the heavenly bodies, by which the preservation and entire
safety of all things is secured, is destitute of intelligence, must be
considered to be himself wholly destitute of all intellect whatever.
I think, then, I shall not deceive myself in maintaining this dispute
upon the principle of Zeno, who went the farthest in his search after
truth.
XXII. Zeno, then, defines nature to be “an artificial fire, proceeding
in a regular way to generation;” for he thinks that to create and beget
are especial properties of art, and that whatever may be wrought by the
hands of our artificers is much more skilfully performed by nature, that
is, by this artificial fire, which is the master of all other arts.
According to this manner of reasoning, every particular nature is
artificial, as it operates agreeably to a certain method peculiar to
itself; but that universal nature which embraces all things is said by
Zeno to be not only artificial, but absolutely the artificer, ever
thinking and providing all things useful and proper; and as every
particular nature owes its rise and increase to its own proper seed, so
universal nature has all her motions voluntary, has affections and
desires (by the Greeks called бЅЃПЃОјбЅ°П‚) productive of actions agreeable to
them, like us, who have sense and understanding to direct us. Such,
then, is the intelligence of the universe; for which reason it may be
properly termed prudence or providence (in Greek, ПЂПЃбЅ№ОЅОїО№О±), since her
chiefest care and employment is to provide all things fit for its
duration, that it may want nothing, and, above all, that it may be
adorned with all perfection of beauty and ornament.
XXIII. Thus far have I spoken concerning the universe, and also of the
stars; from whence it is apparent that there is almost an infinite
number of Gods, always in action, but without labor or fatigue; for they
are not composed of veins, nerves, and bones; their food and drink are
not such as cause humors too gross or too subtle; nor are their bodies
such as to be subject to the fear of falls or blows, or in danger of
diseases from a weariness of limbs. Epicurus, to secure his Gods from
such accidents, 277has made them only outlines of Deities, void of action;
but our Gods being of the most beautiful form, and situated in the
purest region of the heavens, dispose and rule their course in such a
manner that they seem to contribute to the support and preservation of
all things.
Besides these, there are many other natures which have with reason been
deified by the wisest Grecians, and by our ancestors, in consideration
of the benefits derived from them; for they were persuaded that whatever
was of great utility to human kind must proceed from divine goodness,
and the name of the Deity was applied to that which the Deity produced,
as when we call corn Ceres, and wine Bacchus; whence that saying of
Terence,136
Without Ceres and Bacchus, Venus starves.
And any quality, also, in which there was any singular virtue was
nominated a Deity, such as Faith and Wisdom, which are placed among the
divinities in the Capitol; the last by Г†milius Scaurus, but Faith was
consecrated before by Atilius Calatinus. You see the temple of Virtue
and that of Honor repaired by M. Marcellus, erected formerly, in the
Ligurian war, by Q. Maximus. Need I mention those dedicated to Help,
Safety, Concord, Liberty, and Victory, which have been called Deities,
because their efficacy has been so great that it could not have
proceeded from any but from some divine power? In like manner are the
names of Cupid, Voluptas, and of Lubentine Venus consecrated, though
they were things vicious and not natural, whatever Velleius may think
to the contrary, for they frequently stimulate nature in too violent a
manner. Everything, then, from which any great utility proceeded was
deified; and, indeed, the names I have just now mentioned are
declaratory of the particular virtue of each Deity.
XXIV. It has been a general custom likewise, that men who have done
important service to the public should be exalted to heaven by fame and
universal consent. Thus Hercules, Castor and Pollux, Г†sculapius, and
Liber became Gods (I mean Liber137 the son of Semele, and not him138
whom our ancestors consecrated in such state and 278solemnity with Ceres
and Libera; the difference in which may be seen in our Mysteries.139
But because the offsprings of our bodies are called “Liberi” (children),
therefore the offsprings of Ceres are called Liber and Libera
(Libera140 is the feminine, and Liber the masculine); thus likewise
Romulus, or Quirinus—for they are thought to be the same—became a God.
They are justly esteemed as Deities, since their souls subsist and enjoy
eternity, from whence they are perfect and immortal beings.
There is another reason, too, and that founded on natural philosophy,
which has greatly contributed to the number of Deities; namely, the
custom of representing in human form a crowd of Gods who have supplied
the poets with fables, and filled mankind with all sorts of
superstition. Zeno has treated of this subject, but it has been
discussed more at length by Cleanthes and Chrysippus. All Greece was of
opinion that CЕ“lum was castrated by his son Saturn,141 and that Saturn
was chained by his son Jupiter. In these impious fables, a physical and
not inelegant meaning is contained; for they would denote that the
celestial, most exalted, and ethereal nature—that is, the fiery nature,
which produces all things by itself—is destitute of that part of the
body which is necessary for the act of generation by conjunction with
another.
XXV. By Saturn they mean that which comprehends the course and
revolution of times and seasons; the Greek name for which Deity implies
as much, for he is called 279ОљПЃбЅ№ОЅОїП‚, which is the same with О§ПЃбЅ№ОЅОїП‚, that
is, a “space of time.” But he is called Saturn, because he is filled
(saturatur) with years; and he is usually feigned to have devoured his
children, because time, ever insatiable, consumes the rolling years; but
to restrain him from immoderate haste, Jupiter has confined him to the
course of the stars, which are as chains to him. Jupiter (that is,
juvans pater) signifies a “helping father,” whom, by changing the
cases, we call Jove,142 a juvando. The poets call him “father of
Gods and men;”143 and our ancestors “the most good, the most great;”
and as there is something more glorious in itself, and more agreeable to
others, to be good (that is, beneficent) than to be great, the title of
“most good” precedes that of “most great.” This, then, is he whom Ennius
means in the following passage, before quoted—
Look up to the refulgent heaven above,
Which all men call, unanimously, Jove:
which is more plainly expressed than in this other passage144 of the
same poet—
On whose account I’ll curse that flood of light,
Whate’er it is above that shines so bright.
Our augurs also mean the same, when, for the “thundering and lightning
heaven,” they say the “thundering and lightning Jove.” Euripides, among
many excellent things, has this:
The vast, expanded, boundless sky behold,
See it with soft embrace the earth enfold;
This own the chief of Deities above,
And this acknowledge by the name of Jove.
XXVI. The air, according to the Stoics, which is between the sea and the
heaven, is consecrated by the name of Juno, and is called the sister and
wife of Jove, because
280it resembles the sky, and is in close conjunction
with it. They have made it feminine, because there is nothing softer.
But I believe it is called Juno,
a juvando (from helping).
To make three separate kingdoms, by fable, there remained yet the water
and the earth. The dominion of the sea is given, therefore, to Neptune,
a brother, as he is called, of Jove; whose name, Neptunus—as
Portunus,
a portu, from a port—is derived
a nando (from swimming), the first
letters being a little changed. The sovereignty and power over the earth
is the portion of a God, to whom we, as well as the Greeks, have given a
name that denotes riches (in Latin,
Dis; in Greek,
О О»ОїбЅ»П„П‰ОЅ), because
all things arise from the earth and return to it. He forced away
Proserpine (in Greek called
О ОµПЃПѓОµП†бЅ№ОЅО·), by which the poets mean the
“seed of corn,” from whence comes their fiction of Ceres, the mother of
Proserpine, seeking for her daughter, who was hidden from her. She is
called Ceres, which is the same as Geres—
a gerendis
frugibus145—“from bearing fruit,” the first letter of the word being
altered after the manner of the Greeks, for by them she is called
О”О·ОјбЅµП„О·ПЃ, the same as
О“О·ОјбЅµП„О·ПЃ.
146 Again, he (
qui magna vorteret) “who
brings about mighty changes” is called Mavors; and Minerva is so called
because (
minueret, or
minaretur) she diminishes or menaces.
XXVII. And as the beginnings and endings of all things are of the
greatest importance, therefore they would have their sacrifices to begin
with Janus.
147 His name is derived
ab eundo, from passing; from
whence thorough passages are called
jani, and the outward doors of
common houses are called
januæ. The name of Vesta is, from the Greeks,
the same with their
бј™ПѓП„бЅ·О±. Her province is over altars and hearths; and
in the name of this Goddess, who is the keeper of all things within,
prayers and sacrifices are concluded. The
Dii Penates, “household Gods,”
have some affinity with this power, and are so called either from
penus,
281“all kind of human provisions,” or because
penitus insident
(they reside within), from which, by the poets, they are called
penetrales also. Apollo, a Greek name, is called
Sol, the sun; and
Diana,
Luna, the moon. The sun (
sol) is so named either because he
is
solus (alone), so eminent above all the stars; or because he
obscures all the stars, and appears alone as soon as he rises.
Luna,
the moon, is so called
a lucendo (from shining); she bears the name
also of Lucina: and as in Greece the women in labor invoke Diana
Lucifera, so here they invoke Juno Lucina. She is likewise called Diana
omnivaga, not
a venando (from hunting), but because she is reckoned
one of the seven stars that seem to wander.
148 She is called Diana
because she makes a kind of day of the night;
149 and presides over
births, because the delivery is effected sometimes in seven, or at most
in nine, courses of the moon; which, because they make
mensa spatia
(measured spaces), are called
menses (months). This occasioned a
pleasant observation of Timæus (as he has many). Having said in his
history that “the same night in which Alexander was born, the temple of
Diana at Ephesus was burned down,” he adds, “It is not in the least to
be wondered at, because Diana, being willing to assist at the labor of
Olympias,
150 was absent from home.” But to this Goddess, because
ad
res omnes veniret—“she has an influence upon all things”—we have
given the appellation of Venus,
151 from whom the word
venustas
(beauty) is rather derived than Venus from
venustas.
XXVIII. Do you not see, therefore, how, from the productions of nature
and the useful inventions of men, have arisen fictitious and imaginary
Deities, which have been the foundation of false opinions, pernicious
errors, and wretched superstitions? For we know how the different forms
of the Gods—their ages, apparel, ornaments; their
282pedigrees,
marriages, relations, and everything belonging to them—are adapted to
human weakness and represented with our passions; with lust, sorrow, and
anger, according to fabulous history: they have had wars and combats,
not only, as Homer relates, when they have interested themselves in two
different armies, but when they have fought battles in their own defence
against the Titans and giants. These stories, of the greatest weakness
and levity, are related and believed with the most implicit folly.
But, rejecting these fables with contempt, a Deity is diffused in every
part of nature; in earth under the name of Ceres, in the sea under the
name of Neptune, in other parts under other names. Yet whatever they
are, and whatever characters and dispositions they have, and whatever
name custom has given them, we are bound to worship and adore them. The
best, the chastest, the most sacred and pious worship of the Gods is to
reverence them always with a pure, perfect, and unpolluted mind and
voice; for our ancestors, as well as the philosophers, have separated
superstition from religion. They who prayed whole days and sacrificed,
that their children might survive them (
ut superstites essent), were
called superstitious, which word became afterward more general; but they
who diligently perused, and, as we may say, read or practised over
again, all the duties relating to the worship of the Gods, were called
religiosi—religious, from
relegendo—“reading over again, or
practising;” as
elegantes, elegant,
ex eligendo, “from choosing,
making a good choice;”
diligentes, diligent,
ex diligendo, “from
attending on what we love;”
intelligentes, intelligent, from
understanding—for the signification is derived in the same manner. Thus
are the words superstitious and religious understood; the one being a
term of reproach, the other of commendation. I think I have now
sufficiently demonstrated that there are Gods, and what they are.
XXIX. I am now to show that the world is governed by the providence of
the Gods. This is an important point, which you Academics endeavor to
confound; and, indeed, the whole contest is with you, Cotta; for your
sect, Velleius, know very little of what is said on different subjects
by other schools. You read and have a taste only for
283your own books,
and condemn all others without examination. For instance, when you
mentioned yesterday
152 that prophetic old dame
О ПЃбЅ№ОЅОїО№О±, Providence,
invented by the Stoics, you were led into that error by imagining that
Providence was made by them to be a particular Deity that governs the
whole universe, whereas it is only spoken in a short manner; as when it
is said “The commonwealth of Athens is governed by the council,” it is
meant “of the Areopagus;”
153 so when we say “The world is governed by
providence,” we mean “by the providence of the Gods.” To express
ourselves, therefore, more fully and clearly, we say, “The world is
governed by the providence of the Gods.” Be not, therefore, lavish of
your railleries, of which your sect has little to spare: if I may advise
you, do not attempt it. It does not become you, it is not your talent,
nor is it in your power. This is not applied to you in particular who
have the education and politeness of a Roman, but to all your sect in
general, and especially to your leader
154—a man unpolished,
illiterate, insulting, without wit, without reputation, without
elegance.
XXX. I assert, then, that the universe, with all its parts, was
originally constituted, and has, without any cessation, been ever
governed by the providence of the Gods. This argument we Stoics commonly
divide into three parts; the first of which is, that the existence of
the Gods being once known, it must follow that the world is governed by
their wisdom; the second, that as everything is under the direction of
an intelligent nature, which has produced that beautiful order in the
world, it is evident that it is formed from animating principles; the
third is deduced from those glorious works which we behold in the
heavens and the earth.
First, then, we must either deny the existence of the Gods (as
Democritus and Epicurus by their doctrine of images in some sort do),
or, if we acknowledge that there
284are Gods, we must believe they are
employed, and that, too, in something excellent. Now, nothing is so
excellent as the administration of the universe. The universe,
therefore, is governed by the wisdom of the Gods. Otherwise, we must
imagine that there is some cause superior to the Deity, whether it be a
nature inanimate, or a necessity agitated by a mighty force, that
produces those beautiful works which we behold. The nature of the Gods
would then be neither supreme nor excellent, if you subject it to that
necessity or to that nature, by which you would make the heaven, the
earth, and the seas to be governed. But there is nothing superior to the
Deity; the world, therefore, must be governed by him: consequently, the
Deity is under no obedience or subjection to nature, but does himself
rule over all nature. In effect, if we allow the Gods have
understanding, we allow also their providence, which regards the most
important things; for, can they be ignorant of those important things,
and how they are to be conducted and preserved, or do they want power to
sustain and direct them? Ignorance is inconsistent with the nature of
the Gods, and imbecility is repugnant to their majesty. From whence it
follows, as we assert, that the world is governed by the providence of
the Gods.
XXXI. But supposing, which is incontestable, that there are Gods, they
must be animated, and not only animated, but endowed with
reason—united, as we may say, in a civil agreement and society, and
governing together one universe, as a republic or city. Thus the same
reason, the same verity, the same law, which ordains good and prohibits
evil, exists in the Gods as it does in men. From them, consequently, we
have prudence and understanding, for which reason our ancestors erected
temples to the Mind, Faith, Virtue, and Concord. Shall we not then allow
the Gods to have these perfections, since we worship the sacred and
august images of them? But if understanding, faith, virtue, and concord
reside in human kind, how could they come on earth, unless from heaven?
And if we are possessed of wisdom, reason, and prudence, the Gods must
have the same qualities in a greater degree; and not only have them, but
employ them in the best and greatest works. The universe is the best and
greatest
285work; therefore it must be governed by the wisdom and
providence of the Gods.
Lastly, as we have sufficiently shown that those glorious and luminous
bodies which we behold are Deities—I mean the sun, the moon, the fixed
and wandering stars, the firmament, and the world itself, and those
other things also which have any singular virtue, and are of any great
utility to human kind—it follows that all things are governed by
providence and a divine mind. But enough has been said on the first
part.
XXXII. It is now incumbent on me to prove that all things are subjected
to nature, and most beautifully directed by her. But, first of all, it
is proper to explain precisely what that nature is, in order to come to
the more easy understanding of what I would demonstrate. Some think that
nature is a certain irrational power exciting in bodies the necessary
motions. Others, that it is an intelligent power, acting by order and
method, designing some end in every cause, and always aiming at that
end, whose works express such skill as no art, no hand, can imitate;
for, they say, such is the virtue of its seed, that, however small it
is, if it falls into a place proper for its reception, and meets with
matter conducive to its nourishment and increase, it forms and produces
everything in its respective kind; either vegetables, which receive
their nourishment from their roots; or animals, endowed with motion,
sense, appetite, and abilities to beget their likeness.
Some apply the word nature to everything; as Epicurus does, who
acknowledges no cause, but atoms, a vacuum, and their accidents. But
when we
155 say that nature forms and governs the world, we do not
apply it to a clod of earth, or piece of stone, or anything of that
sort, whose parts have not the necessary cohesion,
156 but to a tree,
in
286which there is not the appearance of chance, but of order and a
resemblance of art.
XXXIII. But if the art of nature gives life and increase to vegetables,
without doubt it supports the earth itself; for, being impregnated with
seeds, she produces every kind of vegetable, and embracing their roots,
she nourishes and increases them; while, in her turn, she receives her
nourishment from the other elements, and by her exhalations gives proper
sustenance to the air, the sky, and all the superior bodies. If nature
gives vigor and support to the earth, by the same reason she has an
influence over the rest of the world; for as the earth gives nourishment
to vegetables, so the air is the preservation of animals. The air sees
with us, hears with us, and utters sounds with us; without it, there
would be no seeing, hearing, or sounding. It even moves with us; for
wherever we go, whatever motion we make, it seems to retire and give
place to us.
That which inclines to the centre, that which rises from it to the
surface, and that which rolls about the centre, constitute the universal
world, and make one entire nature; and as there are four sorts of
bodies, the continuance of nature is caused by their reciprocal changes;
for the water arises from the earth, the air from the water, and the
fire from the air; and, reversing this order, the air arises from fire,
the water from the air, and from the water the earth, the lowest of the
four elements, of which all beings are formed. Thus by their continual
motions backward and forward, upward and downward, the conjunction of
the several parts of the universe is preserved; a union which, in the
beauty we now behold it, must be eternal, or at least of a very long
duration, and almost for an infinite space of time; and, whichever it
is, the universe must of consequence be governed by nature. For what art
of navigating fleets, or of marshalling an army, and—to instance the
produce of nature—what vine, what tree, what animated form and
conformation of their members, give us so great an indication of skill
as appears in the universe? Therefore we must either deny that there is
the least trace of an intelligent nature, or acknowledge that the world
is governed by it. But since the universe
287contains all particular
beings, as well as their seeds, can we say that it is not itself
governed by nature? That would be the same as saying that the teeth and
the beard of man are the work of nature, but that the man himself is
not. Thus the effect would be understood to be greater than the cause.
XXXIV. Now, the universe sows, as I may say, plants, produces, raises,
nourishes, and preserves what nature administers, as members and parts
of itself. If nature, therefore, governs them, she must also govern the
universe. And, lastly, in nature’s administration there is nothing
faulty. She produced the best possible effect out of those elements
which existed. Let any one show how it could have been better. But that
can never be; and whoever attempts to mend it will either make it worse,
or aim at impossibilities.
But if all the parts of the universe are so constituted that nothing
could be better for use or beauty, let us consider whether this is the
effect of chance, or whether, in such a state they could possibly
cohere, but by the direction of wisdom and divine providence. Nature,
therefore, cannot be void of reason, if art can bring nothing to
perfection without it, and if the works of nature exceed those of art.
How is it consistent with common-sense that when you view an image or a
picture, you imagine it is wrought by art; when you behold afar off a
ship under sail, you judge it is steered by reason and art; when you see
a dial or water-clock,
157 you believe the hours are shown by art, and
not by chance; and yet that you should imagine that the universe, which
contains all arts and the artificers, can be void of reason and
understanding?
But if that sphere which was lately made by our friend Posidonius, the
regular revolutions of which show the course of the sun, moon, and five
wandering stars, as it is every day and night performed, were carried
into Scythia or Britain, who, in those barbarous countries, would doubt
that that sphere had been made so perfect by the exertion of reason?
XXXV. Yet these people
158 doubt whether the universe,
288from whence all
things arise and are made, is not the effect of chance, or some
necessity, rather than the work of reason and a divine mind. According
to them, Archimedes shows more knowledge in representing the motions of
the celestial globe than nature does in causing them, though the copy is
so infinitely beneath the original. The shepherd in Attius,
159 who had
never seen a ship, when he perceived from a mountain afar off the divine
vessel of the Argonauts, surprised and frighted at this new object,
expressed himself in this manner:
What horrid bulk is that before my eyes,
Which o’er the deep with noise and vigor flies?
It turns the whirlpools up, its force so strong,
And drives the billows as it rolls along.
The ocean’s violence it fiercely braves;
Runs furious on, and throws about the waves.
Swiftly impetuous in its course, and loud,
Like the dire bursting of a show’ry cloud;
Or, like a rock, forced by the winds and rain,
Now whirl’d aloft, then plunged into the main.
But hold! perhaps the Earth and Neptune jar,
And fiercely wage an elemental war;
Or Triton with his trident has o’erthrown
His den, and loosen’d from the roots the stone;
The rocky fragment, from the bottom torn,
Is lifted up, and on the surface borne.
At first he is in suspense at the sight of this unknown object; but on
seeing the young mariners, and hearing their singing, he says,
Like sportive dolphins, with their snouts they roar;
160
and afterward goes on,
Loud in my ears methinks their voices ring,
As if I heard the God Sylvanus sing.
As at first view the shepherd thinks he sees something inanimate and
insensible, but afterward, judging by more
289trustworthy indications, he
begins to figure to himself what it is; so philosophers, if they are
surprised at first at the sight of the universe, ought, when they have
considered the regular, uniform, and immutable motions of it, to
conceive that there is some Being that is not only an inhabitant of this
celestial and divine mansion, but a ruler and a governor, as architect
of this mighty fabric.
XXXVI. Now, in my opinion, they
161 do not seem to have even the least
suspicion that the heavens and earth afford anything marvellous. For, in
the first place, the earth is situated in the middle part of the
universe, and is surrounded on all sides by the air, which we breathe,
and which is called “aer,”
162 which, indeed, is a Greek word; but by
constant use it is well understood by our countrymen, for, indeed, it is
employed as a Latin word. The air is encompassed by the boundless ether
(sky), which consists of the fires above. This word we borrow also, for
we use
Г¦ther in Latin as well as
aer; though Pacuvius thus expresses
it,
—This, of which I speak,
In Latin’s cœlum, æther call’d in Greek.
As though he were not a Greek into whose mouth he puts this sentence;
but he is speaking in Latin, though we listen as if he were speaking
Greek; for, as he says elsewhere,
His speech discovers him a Grecian born.
But to return to more important matters. In the sky innumerable fiery
stars exist, of which the sun is the chief, enlightening all with his
refulgent splendor, and being by many degrees larger than the whole
earth; and this multitude of vast fires are so far from hurting the
earth, and things terrestrial, that they are of benefit to them;
whereas, if they were moved from their stations, we should inevitably be
burned through the want of a proper moderation and temperature of heat.
XXXVII. Is it possible for any man to behold these things, and yet
imagine that certain solid and individual bodies move by their natural
force and gravitation, and that a world so beautifully adorned was made
by their fortuitous concourse? He who believes this may as well
290believe
that if a great quantity of the one-and-twenty letters, composed either
of gold or any other matter, were thrown upon the ground, they would
fall into such order as legibly to form the Annals of Ennius. I doubt
whether fortune could make a single verse of them. How, therefore, can
these people assert that the world was made by the fortuitous concourse
of atoms, which have no color, no quality—which the Greeks call
ПЂОїО№бЅ№П„О·П‚, no sense? or that there are innumerable worlds, some rising and
some perishing, in every moment of time? But if a concourse of atoms can
make a world, why not a porch, a temple, a house, a city, which are
works of less labor and difficulty?
Certainly those men talk so idly and inconsiderately concerning this
lower world that they appear to me never to have contemplated the
wonderful magnificence of the heavens; which is the next topic for our
consideration.
Well, then, did Aristotle
163 observe: “If there were men whose
habitations had been always underground, in great and commodious houses,
adorned with statues and pictures, furnished with everything which they
who are reputed happy abound with; and if, without stirring from thence,
they should be informed of a certain divine power and majesty, and,
after some time, the earth should open, and they should quit their dark
abode to come to us, where they should immediately behold the earth, the
seas, the heavens; should consider the vast extent of the clouds and
force of the winds; should see the sun, and observe his grandeur and
beauty, and also his generative power, inasmuch as day is occasioned by
the diffusion of his light through the sky; and when night has obscured
the earth, they should contemplate the heavens bespangled and adorned
with stars, the surprising variety of the moon in her increase and wane,
the rising and setting of all the stars, and the inviolable regularity
of their courses; when,” says he, “they should see these things, they
would undoubtedly conclude that there are Gods, and that these are their
mighty works.”
XXXVIII. Thus far Aristotle. Let us imagine, also, as great darkness as
was formerly occasioned by the irruption of the fires of Mount Г†tna,
which are said to have obscured
291the adjacent countries for two days to
such a degree that no man could recognize his fellow; but on the third,
when the sun appeared, they seemed to be risen from the dead. Now, if we
should be suddenly brought from a state of eternal darkness to see the
light, how beautiful would the heavens seem! But our minds have become
used to it from the daily practice and habituation of our eyes, nor do
we take the trouble to search into the principles of what is always in
view; as if the novelty, rather than the importance, of things ought to
excite us to investigate their causes.
Is he worthy to be called a man who attributes to chance, not to an
intelligent cause, the constant motion of the heavens, the regular
courses of the stars, the agreeable proportion and connection of all
things, conducted with so much reason that our intellect itself is
unable to estimate it rightly? When we see machines move artificially,
as a sphere, a clock, or the like, do we doubt whether they are the
productions of reason? And when we behold the heavens moving with a
prodigious celerity, and causing an annual succession of the different
seasons of the year, which vivify and preserve all things, can we doubt
that this world is directed, I will not say only by reason, but by
reason most excellent and divine? For without troubling ourselves with
too refined a subtlety of discussion, we may use our eyes to contemplate
the beauty of those things which we assert have been arranged by divine
providence.
XXXIX. First, let us examine the earth, whose situation is in the middle
of the universe,
164 solid, round, and conglobular by its natural
tendency; clothed with flowers, herbs, trees, and fruits; the whole in
multitudes incredible, and with a variety suitable to every taste: let
us consider the ever-cool and running springs, the clear waters of the
rivers, the verdure of their banks, the hollow depths of caves, the
cragginess of rocks, the heights of impending mountains, and the
boundless extent of plains, the hidden veins of gold and silver, and the
infinite quarries of marble.
292What and how various are the kinds of animals, tame or wild? The
flights and notes of birds? How do the beasts live in the fields and in
the forests? What shall I say of men, who, being appointed, as we may
say, to cultivate the earth, do not suffer its fertility to be choked
with weeds, nor the ferocity of beasts to make it desolate; who, by the
houses and cities which they build, adorn the fields, the isles, and the
shores? If we could view these objects with the naked eye, as we can by
the contemplation of the mind, nobody, at such a sight, would doubt
there was a divine intelligence.
But how beautiful is the sea! How pleasant to see the extent of it! What
a multitude and variety of islands! How delightful are the coasts! What
numbers and what diversity of inhabitants does it contain; some within
the bosom of it, some floating on the surface, and others by their
shells cleaving to the rocks! While the sea itself, approaching to the
land, sports so closely to its shores that those two elements appear to
be but one.
Next above the sea is the air, diversified by day and night: when
rarefied, it possesses the higher region; when condensed, it turns into
clouds, and with the waters which it gathers enriches the earth by the
rain. Its agitation produces the winds. It causes heat and cold
according to the different seasons. It sustains birds in their flight;
and, being inhaled, nourishes and preserves all animated beings.
XL. Add to these, which alone remaineth to be mentioned, the firmament
of heaven, a region the farthest from our abodes, which surrounds and
contains all things. It is likewise called ether, or sky, the extreme
bounds and limits of the universe, in which the stars perform their
appointed courses in a most wonderful manner; among which, the sun,
whose magnitude far surpasses the earth, makes his revolution round it,
and by his rising and setting causes day and night; sometimes coming
near towards the earth, and sometimes going from it, he every year makes
two contrary reversions
165 from the extreme
293point of its course. In
his retreat the earth seems locked up in sadness; in his return it
appears exhilarated with the heavens. The moon, which, as mathematicians
demonstrate, is bigger than half the earth, makes her revolutions
through the same spaces
166 as the sun; but at one time approaching,
and at another receding from, the sun, she diffuses the light which she
has borrowed from him over the whole earth, and has herself also many
various changes in her appearance. When she is found under the sun, and
opposite to it, the brightness of her rays is lost; but when the earth
directly interposes between the moon and sun, the moon is totally
eclipsed. The other wandering stars have their courses round the earth
in the same spaces,
167 and rise and set in the same manner; their
motions are sometimes quick, sometimes slow, and often they stand still.
There is nothing more wonderful, nothing more beautiful. There is a vast
number of fixed stars, distinguished by the names of certain figures, to
which we find they have some resemblance.
XLI. I will here, says Balbus, looking at me, make use of the verses
which, when you were young, you translated from Aratus,
168 and which,
because they are in Latin, gave me so much delight that I have many of
them still in my memory. As then, we daily see, without any change or
variation,
—the rest169
Swiftly pursue the course to which they’re bound;
And with the heavens the days and nights go round;
the contemplation of which, to a mind desirous of observing the
constancy of nature, is inexhaustible.
The extreme top of either point is call’d
The pole.
170
294About this the two бјЊПЃОєП„ОїО№ are turned, which never set;
Of these, the Greeks one Cynosura call,
The other Helice.
171
The brightest stars,172 indeed, of Helice are discernible all night,
Which are by us Septentriones call’d.
Cynosura moves about the same pole, with a like number of stars, and
ranged in the same order:
This
173 the PhЕ“nicians choose to make their guide
When on the ocean in the night they ride.
Adorned with stars of more refulgent light,
The other
174 shines, and first appears at night.
Though this is small, sailors its use have found;
More inward is its course, and short its round.
XLII. The aspect of those stars is the more admirable, because,
The Dragon grim between them bends his way,
As through the winding banks the currents stray,
And up and down in sinuous bending rolls.
175
His whole form is excellent; but the shape of his head and the ardor of
his eyes are most remarkable.
Various the stars which deck his glittering head;
His temples are with double glory spread;
From his fierce eyes two fervid lights afar
Flash, and his chin shines with one radiant star;
Bow’d is his head; and his round neck he bends,
And to the tail of Helice
176 extends.
The rest of the Dragon’s body we see177 at every hour in the night.
295Here
178 suddenly the head a little hides
Itself, where all its parts, which are in sight,
And those unseen in the same place unite.
Near to this head
Is placed the figure of a man that moves
Weary and sad,
which the Greeks
Engonasis do call, because he’s borne
179
About with bended knee. Near him is placed
The crown with a refulgent lustre graced.
This indeed is at his back; but Anguitenens (the Snake-holder) is near
his head:180
The Greeks him Ophiuchus call, renown’d
The name. He strongly grasps the serpent round
With both his hands; himself the serpent folds
Beneath his breast, and round his middle holds;
Yet gravely he, bright shining in the skies,
Moves on, and treads on Nepa’s
181 breast and eyes.
The Septentriones182 are followed by—
Arctophylax,
183 that’s said to be the same
Which we Boötes call, who has the name,
Because he drives the Greater Bear along
Yoked to a wain.
Besides, in Boötes,
A star of glittering rays about his waist,
Arcturus called, a name renown’d, is placed.
184
296Beneath which is
The Virgin of illustrious form, whose hand
Holds a bright spike.
XLIII. And truly these signs are so regularly disposed that a divine
wisdom evidently appears in them:
Beneath the Bear’s
185 head have the Twins their seat,
Under his chest the Crab, beneath his feet
The mighty Lion darts a trembling flame.
186
The Charioteer
On the left side of Gemini we see,
187
And at his head behold fierce Helice;
On his left shoulder the bright Goat appears.
But to proceed—
This is indeed a great and glorious star,
On th’ other side the Kids, inferior far,
Yield but a slender light to mortal eyes.
Under his feet
The horned bull,
188 with sturdy limbs, is placed:
his head is spangled with a number of stars;
These by the Greeks are called the Hyades,
from raining; for бЅ•ОµО№ОЅ is to rain: therefore they are injudiciously
called Suculæ by our people, as if they had their name from ὗς, a sow,
and not from бЅ•П‰.
Behind the Lesser Bear, Cepheus189 follows with extended hands,
For close behind the Lesser Bear he comes.
297Before him goes
Cassiopea
190 with a faintish light;
But near her moves (fair and illustrious sight!)
Andromeda,
191 who, with an eager pace,
Seems to avoid her parent’s mournful face.
192
With glittering mane the Horse
193 now seems to tread,
So near he comes, on her refulgent head;
With a fair star, that close to him appears,
A double form
194 and but one light he wears;
By which he seems ambitious in the sky
An everlasting knot of stars to tie.
Near him the Ram, with wreathed horns, is placed;
by whom
The Fishes
195 are; of which one seems to haste
Somewhat before the other, to the blast
Of the north wind exposed.
XLIV. Perseus is described as placed at the feet of Andromeda:
And him the sharp blasts of the north wind beat.
Near his left knee, but dim their light, their seat
The small Pleiades
196 maintain. We find,
Not far from them, the Lyre
197 but slightly join’d.
Next is the winged Bird,
198 that seems to fly
Beneath the spacious covering of the sky.
298Near the head of the Horse199 lies the right hand of Aquarius, then
all Aquarius himself.200
Then Capricorn, with half the form of beast,
Breathes chill and piercing colds from his strong breast,
And in a spacious circle takes his round;
When him, while in the winter solstice bound,
The sun has visited with constant light,
He turns his course, and shorter makes the night.
201
Not far from hence is seen
The Scorpion
202 rising lofty from below;
By him the Archer,
203 with his bended bow;
Near him the Bird, with gaudy feathers spread;
And the fierce Eagle
204 hovers o’er his head.
Next comes the Dolphin;205
Then bright Orion,
206 who obliquely moves;
he is followed by
The fervent Dog,
207 bright with refulgent stars:
next the Hare follows208
Unwearied in his course. At the Dog’s tail
Argo
209 moves on, and moving seems to sail;
O’er her the Ram and Fishes have their place;
210
The illustrious vessel touches, in her pace,
The river’s banks;
211
which you may see winding and extending itself to a great length.
299The Fetters
212 at the Fishes’ tails are hung.
By Nepa’s
213 head behold the Altar stand,
214
Which by the breath of southern winds is fann’d;
near which the Centaur215
Hastens his mingled parts to join beneath
The Serpent,
216 there extending his right hand,
To where you see the monstrous Scorpion stand,
Which he at the bright Altar fiercely slays.
Here on her lower parts see Hydra
217 raise
Herself;
whose bulk is very far extended.
Amid the winding of her body’s placed
The shining Goblet;
218 and the glossy Crow
219
Plunges his beak into her parts below.
Antecanis beneath the Twins is seen,
Call’d Procyon by the Greeks.
220
Can any one in his senses imagine that this disposition of the stars,
and this heaven so beautifully adorned, could ever have been formed by a
fortuitous concourse of atoms? Or what other nature, being destitute of
intellect and reason, could possibly have produced these effects, which
not only required reason to bring them about, but the very character of
which could not be understood and appreciated without the most strenuous
exertions of well-directed reason?
XLV. But our admiration is not limited to the objects here described.
What is most wonderful is that the world is so durable, and so perfectly
made for lasting that it is not to be impaired by time; for all its
parts tend equally to the centre, and are bound together by a sort of
chain, which surrounds the elements. This chain is nature, which
300being
diffused through the universe, and performing all things with judgment
and reason, attracts the extremities to the centre.
If, then, the world is round, and if on that account all its parts,
being of equal dimensions and relative proportions, mutually support and
are supported by one another, it must follow that as all the parts
incline to the centre (for that is the lowest place of a globe) there is
nothing whatever which can put a stop to that propensity in the case of
such great weights. For the same reason, though the sea is higher than
the earth, yet because it has the like tendency, it is collected
everywhere, equally concentres, and never overflows, and is never
wasted.
The air, which is contiguous, ascends by its lightness, but diffuses
itself through the whole; therefore it is by nature joined and united to
the sea, and at the same time borne by the same power towards the
heaven, by the thinness and heat of which it is so tempered as to be
made proper to supply life and wholesome air for the support of animated
beings. This is encompassed by the highest region of the heavens, which
is called the sky, which is joined to the extremity of the air, but
retains its own heat pure and unmixed.
XLVI. The stars have their revolutions in the sky, and are continued by
the tendency of all parts towards the centre. Their duration is
perpetuated by their form and figure, for they are round; which form, as
I think has been before observed, is the least liable to injury; and as
they are composed of fire, they are fed by the vapors which are exhaled
by the sun from the earth, the sea, and other waters; but when these
vapors have nourished and refreshed the stars, and the whole sky, they
are sent back to be exhaled again; so that very little is lost or
consumed by the fire of the stars and the flame of the sky. Hence we
Stoics conclude—which Panætius
221 is said to have doubted of—that
the whole world at last would be consumed by a general conflagration,
when, all moisture being exhausted, neither the earth could have any
nourishment, nor the air return again, since water, of which it is
formed, would then be all consumed; so that only fire would subsist; and
301from this fire, which is an animating power and a Deity, a new world
would arise and be re-established in the same beauty.
I should be sorry to appear to you to dwell too long upon this subject
of the stars, and more especially upon that of the planets, whose
motions, though different, make a very just agreement. Saturn, the
highest, chills; Mars, placed in the middle, burns; while Jupiter,
interposing, moderates their excess, both of light and heat. The two
planets beneath Mars
222 obey the sun. The sun himself fills the whole
universe with his own genial light; and the moon, illuminated by him,
influences conception, birth, and maturity. And who is there who is not
moved by this union of things, and by this concurrence of nature
agreeing together, as it were, for the safety of the world? And yet I
feel sure that none of these reflections have ever been made by these
men.
XLVII. Let us proceed from celestial to terrestrial things. What is
there in them which does not prove the principle of an intelligent
nature? First, as to vegetables; they have roots to sustain their stems,
and to draw from the earth a nourishing moisture to support the vital
principle which those roots contain. They are clothed with a rind or
bark, to secure them more thoroughly from heat and cold. The vines we
see take hold on props with their tendrils, as if with hands, and raise
themselves as if they were animated; it is even said that they shun
cabbages and coleworts, as noxious and pestilential to them, and, if
planted by them, will not touch any part.
But what a vast variety is there of animals! and how wonderfully is
every kind adapted to preserve itself! Some are covered with hides, some
clothed with fleeces, and some guarded with bristles; some are sheltered
with feathers, some with scales; some are armed with horns, and some are
furnished with wings to escape from danger. Nature hath also liberally
and plentifully provided for all animals their proper food. I could
expatiate on the judicious and curious formation and disposition of
their bodies for the reception and digestion of it, for all their
interior parts are so framed and disposed that there is
302nothing
superfluous, nothing that is not necessary for the preservation of life.
Besides, nature has also given these beasts appetite and sense; in order
that by the one they may be excited to procure sufficient sustenance,
and by the other they may distinguish what is noxious from what is
salutary. Some animals seek their food walking, some creeping, some
flying, and some swimming; some take it with their mouth and teeth; some
seize it with their claws, and some with their beaks; some suck, some
graze, some bolt it whole, and some chew it. Some are so low that they
can with ease take such food as is to be found on the ground; but the
taller, as geese, swans, cranes, and camels, are assisted by a length of
neck. To the elephant is given a hand,
223 without which, from his
unwieldiness of body, he would scarce have any means of attaining food.
XLVIII. But to those beasts which live by preying on others, nature has
given either strength or swiftness. On some animals she has even
bestowed artifice and cunning; as on spiders, some of which weave a sort
of net to entrap and destroy whatever falls into it, others sit on the
watch unobserved to fall on their prey and devour it. The naker—by the
Greeks called
Pinna—has a kind of confederacy with the prawn for
procuring food. It has two large shells open, into which when the little
fishes swim, the naker, having notice given by the bite of the prawn,
closes them immediately. Thus, these little animals, though of different
kinds, seek their food in common; in which it is matter of wonder
whether they associate by any agreement, or are naturally joined
together from their beginning.
There is some cause to admire also the provision of nature in the case
of those aquatic animals which are generated on land, such as
crocodiles, river-tortoises, and a certain kind of serpents, which seek
the water as soon as they are able to drag themselves along. We
frequently put duck-eggs under hens, by which, as by their true mothers,
the ducklings are at first hatched and nourished; but when they see the
water, they forsake them and run to it, as to
303their natural abode: so
strong is the impression of nature in animals for their own
preservation.
XLIX. I have read that there is a bird called Platalea (the shoveller),
that lives by watching those fowls which dive into the sea for their
prey, and when they return with it, he squeezes their heads with his
beak till they drop it, and then seizes on it himself. It is said
likewise that he is in the habit of filling his stomach with shell-fish,
and when they are digested by the heat which exists in the stomach, they
cast them up, and then pick out what is proper nourishment. The
sea-frogs, they say, are wont to cover themselves with sand, and moving
near the water, the fishes strike at them, as at a bait, and are
themselves taken and devoured by the frogs. Between the kite and the
crow there is a kind of natural war, and wherever the one finds the eggs
of the other, he breaks them.
But who is there who can avoid being struck with wonder at that which
has been noticed by Aristotle, who has enriched us with so many valuable
remarks? When the cranes
224 pass the sea in search of warmer climes,
they fly in the form of a triangle. By the first angle they repel the
resisting air; on each side, their wings serve as oars to facilitate
their flight; and the basis of their triangle is assisted by the wind in
their stern. Those which are behind rest their necks and heads on those
which precede; and as the leader has not the same relief, because he has
none to lean upon, he at length flies behind that he may also rest,
while one of those which have been eased succeeds him, and through the
whole flight each regularly takes his turn.
I could produce many instances of this kind; but these may suffice. Let
us now proceed to things more familiar to us. The care of beasts for
their own preservation, their circumspection while feeding, and their
manner of taking rest in their lairs, are generally known, but still
they are greatly to be admired.
L. Dogs cure themselves by a vomit, the Egyptian ibis by a purge; from
whence physicians have lately—I mean but few ages since—greatly
improved their art. It is reported
304that panthers, which in barbarous
countries are taken with poisoned flesh, have a certain remedy
225 that
preserves them from dying; and that in Crete, the wild goats, when they
are wounded with poisoned arrows, seek for an herb called dittany,
which, when they have tasted, the arrows (they say) drop from their
bodies. It is said also that deer, before they fawn, purge themselves
with a little herb called hartswort.
226 Beasts, when they receive any
hurt, or fear it, have recourse to their natural arms: the bull to his
horns, the boar to his tusks, and the lion to his teeth. Some take to
flight, others hide themselves; the cuttle-fish vomits
227 blood; the
cramp-fish benumbs; and there are many animals that, by their
intolerable stink, oblige their pursuers to retire.
LI. But that the beauty of the world might be eternal, great care has
been taken by the providence of the Gods to perpetuate the different
kinds of animals, and vegetables, and trees, and all those things which
sink deep into the earth, and are contained in it by their roots and
trunks; in order to which every individual has within itself such
fertile seed that many are generated from one; and in vegetables this
seed is enclosed in the heart of their fruit, but in such abundance that
men may plentifully feed on it, and the earth be always replanted.
With regard to animals, do we not see how aptly they are formed for the
propagation of their species? Nature for this end created some males and
some females. Their parts are perfectly framed for generation, and they
have a wonderful propensity to copulation. When the seed has fallen on
the matrix, it draws almost all the nourishment to itself, by which the
fЕ“tus is formed; but as soon as it is discharged from thence, if it is
an animal that is nourished by milk, almost all the food of the mother
turns into milk, and the animal, without any direction but by the pure
instinct of nature, immediately hunts for the
305teat, and is there fed
with plenty. What makes it evidently appear that there is nothing in
this fortuitous, but the work of a wise and foreseeing nature, is, that
those females which bring forth many young, as sows and bitches, have
many teats, and those which bear a small number have but few. What
tenderness do beasts show in preserving and raising up their young till
they are able to defend themselves! They say, indeed, that fish, when
they have spawned, leave their eggs; but the water easily supports them,
and produces the young fry in abundance.
LII. It is said, likewise, that tortoises and crocodiles, when they have
laid their eggs on the land, only cover them with earth, and then leave
them, so that their young are hatched and brought up without assistance;
but fowls and other birds seek for quiet places to lay in, where they
build their nests in the softest manner, for the surest preservation of
their eggs; which, when they have hatched, they defend from the cold by
the warmth of their wings, or screen them from the sultry heat of the
sun. When their young begin to be able to use their wings, they attend
and instruct them; and then their cares are at an end.
Human art and industry are indeed necessary towards the preservation and
improvement of certain animals and vegetables; for there are several of
both kinds which would perish without that assistance. There are
likewise innumerable facilities (being different in different places)
supplied to man to aid him in his civilization, and in procuring
abundantly what he requires. The Nile waters Egypt, and after having
overflowed and covered it the whole summer, it retires, and leaves the
fields softened and manured for the reception of seed. The Euphrates
fertilizes Mesopotamia, into which, as we may say, it carries yearly new
fields.
228 The Indus, which is the largest of all rivers,
229 not
only improves and cultivates the ground,
306but sows it also; for it is
said to carry with it a great quantity of grain. I could mention many
other countries remarkable for something singular, and many fields,
which are, in their own natures, exceedingly fertile.
LIII. But how bountiful is nature that has provided for us such an
abundance of various and delicious food; and this varying with the
different seasons, so that we may be constantly pleased with change, and
satisfied with abundance! How seasonable and useful to man, to beasts,
and even to vegetables, are the Etesian winds
230 she has bestowed,
which moderate intemperate heat, and render navigation more sure and
speedy! Many things must be omitted on a subject so copious—and still a
great deal must be said—for it is impossible to relate the great
utility of rivers, the flux and reflux of the sea, the mountains clothed
with grass and trees, the salt-pits remote from the sea-coasts, the
earth replete with salutary medicines, or, in short, the innumerable
designs of nature necessary for sustenance and the enjoyment of life. We
must not forget the vicissitudes of day and night, ordained for the
health of animated beings, giving them a time to labor and a time to
rest. Thus, if we every way examine the universe, it is apparent, from
the greatest reason, that the whole is admirably governed by a divine
providence for the safety and preservation of all beings.
If it should be asked for whose sake this mighty fabric was raised,
shall we say for trees and other vegetables, which, though destitute of
sense, are supported by nature? That would be absurd. Is it for beasts?
Nothing can be less probable than that the Gods should have taken such
pains for beings void of speech and understanding. For whom, then, will
any one presume to say that the world was made? Undoubtedly for
reasonable beings; these are the Gods and men, who are certainly the
most perfect of all beings, as nothing is equal to reason. It is
therefore credible that the universe, and all things in it, were made
for the Gods and for men.
But we may yet more easily comprehend that the Gods have taken great
care of the interests and welfare of men,
307if we examine thoroughly into
the structure of the body, and the form and perfection of human nature.
There are three things absolutely necessary for the support of life—to
eat, to drink, and to breathe. For these operations the mouth is most
aptly framed, which, by the assistance of the nostrils, draws in the
more air.
LIV. The teeth are there placed to divide and grind the food.
231 The
fore-teeth, being sharp and opposite to each other, cut it asunder, and
the hind-teeth (called the grinders) chew it, in which office the tongue
seems to assist. At the root of the tongue is the gullet, which receives
whatever is swallowed: it touches the tonsils on each side, and
terminates at the interior extremity of the palate. When, by the motions
of the tongue, the food is forced into this passage, it descends, and
those parts of the gullet which are below it are dilated, and those
above are contracted. There is another passage, called by physicians the
rough artery,
232 which reaches to the lungs, for the entrance and
return of the air we breathe; and as its orifice is joined to the roots
of the tongue a little above the part to which the gullet is annexed, it
is furnished with a sort of coverlid,
233 lest, by the accidental
falling of any food into it, the respiration should be stopped.
As the stomach, which is beneath the gullet, receives the meat and
drink, so the lungs and the heart draw in the air from without. The
stomach is wonderfully composed, consisting almost wholly of nerves; it
abounds with membranes and fibres, and detains what it receives, whether
solid or liquid, till it is altered and digested. It sometimes
contracts, sometimes dilates. It blends and mixes the food together, so
that it is easily concocted and digested by its force of heat, and by
the animal spirits is distributed into the other parts of the body.
LV. As to the lungs, they are of a soft and spongy substance, which
renders them the most commodious for respiration;
308they alternately
dilate and contract to receive and return the air, that what is the
chief animal sustenance may be always fresh. The juice,
234 by which we
are nourished, being separated from the rest of the food, passes the
stomach and intestines to the liver, through open and direct passages,
which lead from the mesentery to the gates of the liver (for so they
call those vessels at the entrance of it). There are other passages from
thence, through which the food has its course when it has passed the
liver. When the bile, and those humors which proceed from the kidneys,
are separated from the food, the remaining part turns to blood, and
flows to those vessels at the entrance of the liver to which all the
passages adjoin. The chyle, being conveyed from this place through them
into the vessel called the hollow vein, is mixed together, and, being
already digested and distilled, passes into the heart; and from the
heart it is communicated through a great number of veins to every part
of the body.
It is not difficult to describe how the gross remains are detruded by
the motion of the intestines, which contract and dilate; but that must
be declined, as too indelicate for discourse. Let us rather explain that
other wonder of nature, the air, which is drawn into the lungs, receives
heat both by that already in and by the coagitation of the lungs; one
part is turned back by respiration, and the other is received into a
place called the ventricle of the heart.
235 There is another ventricle
like it annexed to the heart, into which the blood flows from the liver
through the hollow vein. Thus by one ventricle the blood is diffused to
the extremities through the veins, and by the other the breath is
communicated through the arteries; and there are such numbers of both
dispersed through the whole body that they manifest a divine art.
Why need I speak of the bones, those supports of the body, whose joints
are so wonderfully contrived for stability, and to render the limbs
complete with regard to motion and to every action of the body? Or need
I mention
309the nerves, by which the limbs are governed—their many
interweavings, and their proceeding from the heart,
236 from whence,
like the veins and arteries, they have their origin, and are distributed
through the whole corporeal frame?
LVI. To this skill of nature, and this care of providence, so diligent
and so ingenious, many reflections may be added, which show what
valuable things the Deity has bestowed on man. He has made us of a
stature tall and upright, in order that we might behold the heavens, and
so arrive at the knowledge of the Gods; for men are not simply to dwell
here as inhabitants of the earth, but to be, as it were, spectators of
the heavens and the stars, which is a privilege not granted to any other
kind of animated beings. The senses, which are the interpreters and
messengers of things, are placed in the head, as in a tower, and
wonderfully situated for their proper uses; for the eyes, being in the
highest part, have the office of sentinels, in discovering to us
objects; and the ears are conveniently placed in a high part of the
person, being appointed to receive sound, which naturally ascends. The
nostrils have the like situation, because all scent likewise ascends;
and they have, with great reason, a near vicinity to the mouth, because
they assist us in judging of meat and drink. The taste, which is to
distinguish the quality of what we take; is in that part of the mouth
where nature has laid open a passage for what we eat and drink. But the
touch is equally diffused through the whole body, that we may not
receive any blows, or the too rigid attacks of cold and heat, without
feeling them. And as in building the architect averts from the eyes and
nose of the master those things which must necessarily be offensive, so
has nature removed far from our senses what is of the same kind in the
human body.
LVII. What artificer but nature, whose direction is incomparable, could
have exhibited so much ingenuity in the formation of the senses? In the
first place, she has covered and invested the eyes with the finest
membranes, which she hath made transparent, that we may see through
310them, and firm in their texture, to preserve the eyes. She has made
them slippery and movable, that they might avoid what would offend them,
and easily direct the sight wherever they will. The actual organ of
sight, which is called the pupil, is so small that it can easily shun
whatever might be hurtful to it. The eyelids, which are their coverings,
are soft and smooth, that they may not injure the eyes; and are made to
shut at the apprehension of any accident, or to open at pleasure; and
these movements nature has ordained to be made in an instant: they are
fortified with a sort of palisade of hairs, to keep off what may be
noxious to them when open, and to be a fence to their repose when sleep
closes them, and allows them to rest as if they were wrapped up in a
case. Besides, they are commodiously hidden and defended by eminences on
every side; for on the upper part the eyebrows turn aside the
perspiration which falls from the head and forehead; the cheeks beneath
rise a little, so as to protect them on the lower side; and the nose is
placed between them as a wall of separation.
The hearing is always open, for that is a sense of which we are in need
even while we are sleeping; and the moment that any sound is admitted by
it we are awakened even from sleep. It has a winding passage, lest
anything should slip into it, as it might if it were straight and
simple. Nature also hath taken the same precaution in making there a
viscous humor, that if any little creatures should endeavor to creep in,
they might stick in it as in bird-lime. The ears (by which we mean the
outward part) are made prominent, to cover and preserve the hearing,
lest the sound should be dissipated and escape before the sense is
affected. Their entrances are hard and horny, and their form winding,
because bodies of this kind better return and increase the sound. This
appears in the harp, lute, or horn;
237 and from all tortuous and
enclosed places sounds are returned stronger.
The nostrils, in like manner, are ever open, because we have a continual
use for them; and their entrances also are rather narrow, lest anything
noxious should enter
311them; and they have always a humidity necessary
for the repelling dust and many other extraneous bodies. The taste,
having the mouth for an enclosure, is admirably situated, both in regard
to the use we make of it and to its security.
LVIII. Besides, every human sense is much more exquisite than those of
brutes; for our eyes, in those arts which come under their judgment,
distinguish with great nicety; as in painting, sculpture, engraving, and
in the gesture and motion of bodies. They understand the beauty,
proportion, and, as I may so term it, the becomingness of colors and
figures; they distinguish things of greater importance, even virtues and
vices; they know whether a man is angry or calm, cheerful or sad,
courageous or cowardly, bold or timorous.
The judgment of the ears is not less admirably and scientifically
contrived with regard to vocal and instrumental music. They distinguish
the variety of sounds, the measure, the stops, the different sorts of
voices, the treble and the base, the soft and the harsh, the sharp and
the flat, of which human ears only are capable to judge. There is
likewise great judgment in the smell, the taste, and the touch; to
indulge and gratify which senses more arts have been invented than I
could wish: it is apparent to what excess we have arrived in the
composition of our perfumes, the preparation of our food, and the
enjoyment of corporeal pleasures.
LIX. Again, he who does not perceive the soul and mind of man, his
reason, prudence, and discernment, to be the work of a divine
providence, seems himself to be destitute of those faculties. While I am
on this subject, Cotta, I wish I had your eloquence: how would you
illustrate so fine a subject! You would show the great extent of the
understanding; how we collect our ideas, and join those which follow to
those which precede; establish principles, draw consequences, define
things separately, and comprehend them with accuracy; from whence you
demonstrate how great is the power of intelligence and knowledge, which
is such that even God himself has no qualities more admirable. How
valuable (though you Academics despise and even deny that we have it) is
our
312knowledge of exterior objects, from the perception of the senses
joined to the application of the mind; by which we see in what relation
one thing stands to another, and by the aid of which we have invented
those arts which are necessary for the support and pleasure of life. How
charming is eloquence! How divine that mistress of the universe, as you
call it! It teaches us what we were ignorant of, and makes us capable of
teaching what we have learned. By this we exhort others; by this we
persuade them; by this we comfort the afflicted; by this we deliver the
affrighted from their fear; by this we moderate excessive joy; by this
we assuage the passions of lust and anger. This it is which bound men by
the chains of right and law, formed the bonds of civil society, and made
us quit a wild and savage life.
And it will appear incredible, unless you carefully observe the facts,
how complete the work of nature is in giving us the use of speech; for,
first of all, there is an artery from the lungs to the bottom of the
mouth, through which the voice, having its original principle in the
mind, is transmitted. Then the tongue is placed in the mouth, bounded by
the teeth. It softens and modulates the voice, which would otherwise be
confusedly uttered; and, by pushing it to the teeth and other parts of
the mouth, makes the sound distinct and articulate. We Stoics,
therefore, compare the tongue to the bow of an instrument, the teeth to
the strings, and the nostrils to the sounding-board.
LX. But how commodious are the hands which nature has given to man, and
how beautifully do they minister to many arts! For, such is the
flexibility of the joints, that our fingers are closed and opened
without any difficulty. With their help, the hand is formed for
painting, carving, and engraving; for playing on stringed instruments,
and on the pipe. These are matters of pleasure. There are also works of
necessity, such as tilling the ground, building houses, making cloth and
habits, and working in brass and iron. It is the business of the mind to
invent, the senses to perceive, and the hands to execute; so that if we
have buildings, if we are clothed, if we live in safety, if we have
cities, walls, habitations, and temples, it is to the hands we owe them.
313By our labor, that is, by our hands, variety and plenty of food are
provided; for, without culture, many fruits, which serve either for
present or future consumption, would not be produced; besides, we feed
on flesh, fish, and fowl, catching some, and bringing up others. We
subdue four-footed beasts for our carriage, whose speed and strength
supply our slowness and inability. On some we put burdens, on others
yokes. We convert the sagacity of the elephant and the quick scent of
the dog to our own advantage. Out of the caverns of the earth we dig
iron, a thing entirely necessary for the cultivation of the ground. We
discover the hidden veins of copper, silver, and gold, advantageous for
our use and beautiful as ornaments. We cut down trees, and use every
kind of wild and cultivated timber, not only to make fire to warm us and
dress our meat, but also for building, that we may have houses to defend
us from the heat and cold. With timber likewise we build ships, which
bring us from all parts every commodity of life. We are the only animals
who, from our knowledge of navigation, can manage what nature has made
the most violent—the sea and the winds. Thus we obtain from the ocean
great numbers of profitable things. We are the absolute masters of what
the earth produces. We enjoy the mountains and the plains. The rivers
and the lakes are ours. We sow the seed, and plant the trees. We
fertilize the earth by overflowing it. We stop, direct, and turn the
rivers: in short, by our hands we endeavor, by our various operations in
this world, to make, as it were, another nature.
LXI. But what shall I say of human reason? Has it not even entered the
heavens? Man alone of all animals has observed the courses of the stars,
their risings and settings. By man the day, the month, the year, is
determined. He foresees the eclipses of the sun and moon, and foretells
them to futurity, marking their greatness, duration, and precise time.
>From the contemplation of these things the mind extracts the knowledge
of the Gods—a knowledge which produces piety, with which is connected
justice, and all the other virtues; from which arises a life of
felicity, inferior to that of the Gods in no single particular, except
in immortality, which is not absolutely necessary
314to happy living. In
explaining these things, I think that I have sufficiently demonstrated
the superiority of man to other animated beings; from whence we should
infer that neither the form and position of his limbs nor that strength
of mind and understanding could possibly be the effect of chance.
LXII. I am now to prove, by way of conclusion, that every thing in this
world of use to us was made designedly for us.
First of all, the universe was made for the Gods and men, and all things
therein were prepared and provided for our service. For the world is the
common habitation or city of the Gods and men; for they are the only
reasonable beings: they alone live by justice and law. As, therefore, it
must be presumed the cities of Athens and Lacedæmon were built for the
Athenians and Lacedæmonians, and as everything there is said to belong
to those people, so everything in the universe may with propriety be
said to belong to the Gods and men, and to them alone.
In the next place, though the revolutions of the sun, moon, and all the
stars are necessary for the cohesion of the universe, yet may they be
considered also as objects designed for the view and contemplation of
man. There is no sight less apt to satiate the eye, none more beautiful,
or more worthy to employ our reason and penetration. By measuring their
courses we find the different seasons, their durations and vicissitudes,
which, if they are known to men alone, we must believe were made only
for their sake.
Does the earth bring forth fruit and grain in such excessive abundance
and variety for men or for brutes? The plentiful and exhilarating fruit
of the vine and the olive-tree are entirely useless to beasts. They know
not the time for sowing, tilling, or for reaping in season and gathering
in the fruits of the earth, or for laying up and preserving their
stores. Man alone has the care and advantage of these things.
LXIII. Thus, as the lute and the pipe were made for those, and those
only, who are capable of playing on them, so it must be allowed that the
produce of the earth was designed for those only who make use of them;
and
315though some beasts may rob us of a small part, it does not follow
that the earth produced it also for them. Men do not store up corn for
mice and ants, but for their wives, their children, and their families.
Beasts, therefore, as I said before, possess it by stealth, but their
masters openly and freely. It is for us, therefore, that nature hath
provided this abundance. Can there be any doubt that this plenty and
variety of fruit, which delight not only the taste, but the smell and
sight, was by nature intended for men only? Beasts are so far from being
partakers of this design, that we see that even they themselves were
made for man; for of what utility would sheep be, unless for their wool,
which, when dressed and woven, serves us for clothing? For they are not
capable of anything, not even of procuring their own food, without the
care and assistance of man. The fidelity of the dog, his affectionate
fawning on his master, his aversion to strangers, his sagacity in
finding game, and his vivacity in pursuit of it, what do these qualities
denote but that he was created for our use? Why need I mention oxen? We
perceive that their backs were not formed for carrying burdens, but
their necks were naturally made for the yoke, and their strong broad
shoulders to draw the plough. In the Golden Age, which poets speak of,
they were so greatly beneficial to the husbandman in tilling the fallow
ground that no violence was ever offered them, and it was even thought a
crime to eat them:
The Iron Age began the fatal trade
Of blood, and hammer’d the destructive blade;
Then men began to make the ox to bleed,
And on the tamed and docile beast to feed
238.
LXIV. It would take a long time to relate the advantages which we
receive from mules and asses, which undoubtedly were designed for our
use. What is the swine good for but to eat? whose life, Chrysippus says,
was given it but as salt
239 to keep it from putrefying; and as it
316is
proper food for man, nature hath made no animal more fruitful. What a
multitude of birds and fishes are taken by the art and contrivance of
man only, and which are so delicious to our taste that one would be
tempted sometimes to believe that this Providence which watches over us
was an Epicurean! Though we think there are some birds—the alites and
oscines
240, as our augurs call them—which were made merely to
foretell events.
The large savage beasts we take by hunting, partly for food, partly to
exercise ourselves in imitation of martial discipline, and to use those
we can tame and instruct, as elephants, or to extract remedies for our
diseases and wounds, as we do from certain roots and herbs, the virtues
of which are known by long use and experience. Represent to yourself the
whole earth and seas as if before your eyes. You will see the vast and
fertile plains, the thick, shady mountains, the immense pasturage for
cattle, and ships sailing over the deep with incredible celerity; nor
are our discoveries only on the face of the earth, but in its secret
recesses there are many useful things, which being made for man, by man
alone are discovered.
LXV. Another, and in my opinion the strongest, proof that the providence
of the Gods takes care of us is divination, which both of you, perhaps,
will attack; you, Cotta, because Carneades took pleasure in inveighing
against the Stoics; and you, Velleius, because there is nothing Epicurus
ridicules so much as the prediction of events. Yet the truth of
divination appears in many places, on many occasions, often in private,
but particularly in public concerns. We receive many intimations from
the foresight and presages of augurs and auspices; from oracles,
prophecies, dreams, and prodigies; and it often happens that by these
means events have proved happy to men, and imminent dangers have been
avoided. This knowledge, therefore—call it either a kind of transport,
or an art, or a natural faculty—is certainly found only in men, and is
a gift from the immortal Gods. If these proofs, when taken
317separately,
should make no impression upon your mind, yet, when collected together,
they must certainly affect you.
Besides, the Gods not only provide for mankind universally, but for
particular men. You may bring this universality to gradually a smaller
number, and again you may reduce that smaller number to individuals.
LXVI. For if the reasons which I have given prove to all of us that the
Gods take care of all men, in every country, in every part of the world
separate from our continent, they take care of those who dwell on the
same land with us, from east to west; and if they regard those who
inhabit this kind of great island, which we call the globe of the earth,
they have the like regard for those who possess the parts of this
island—Europe, Asia, and Africa; and therefore they favor the parts of
these parts, as Rome, Athens, Sparta, and Rhodes; and particular men of
these cities, separate from the whole; as Curius, Fabricius,
Coruncanius, in the war with Pyrrhus; in the first Punic war, Calatinus,
Duillius, Metellus, Lutatius; in the second, Maximus, Marcellus,
Africanus; after these, Paullus, Gracchus, Cato; and in our fathers’
times, Scipio, Lælius. Rome also and Greece have produced many
illustrious men, who we cannot believe were so without the assistance of
the Deity; which is the reason that the poets, Homer in particular,
joined their chief heroes—Ulysses, Agamemnon, Diomedes, Achilles—to
certain Deities, as companions in their adventures and dangers. Besides,
the frequent appearances of the Gods, as I have before mentioned,
demonstrate their regard for cities and particular men. This is also
apparent indeed from the foreknowledge of events, which we receive
either sleeping or waking. We are likewise forewarned of many things by
the entrails of victims, by presages, and many other means, which have
been long observed with such exactness as to produce an art of
divination.
There never, therefore, was a great man without divine inspiration. If a
storm should damage the corn or vineyard of a person, or any accident
should deprive him of some conveniences of life, we should not judge
from thence that the Deity hates or neglects him. The Gods take care
318of
great things, and disregard the small. But to truly great men all things
ever happen prosperously; as has been sufficiently asserted and proved
by us Stoics, as well as by Socrates, the prince of philosophers, in his
discourses on the infinite advantages arising from virtue.
LXVII. This is almost the whole that hath occurred to my mind on the
nature of the Gods, and what I thought proper to advance. Do you, Cotta,
if I may advise, defend the same cause. Remember that in Rome you keep
the first rank; remember that you are Pontifex; and as your school is at
liberty to argue on which side you please
241, do you rather take mine,
and reason on it with that eloquence which you acquired by your
rhetorical exercises, and which the Academy improved; for it is a
pernicious and impious custom to argue against the Gods, whether it be
done seriously, or only in pretence and out of sport.
BOOK III.
I.
When Balbus had ended this discourse, then Cotta, with a smile,
rejoined, You direct me too late which side to defend; for during the
course of your argument I was revolving in my mind what objections to
make to what you were saying, not so much for the sake of opposition, as
of obliging you to explain what I did not perfectly comprehend; and as
every one may use his own judgment, it is scarcely possible for me to
think in every instance exactly what you wish.
You have no idea, O Cotta, said Velleius, how impatient I am to hear
what you have to say. For since our friend Balbus was highly delighted
with your discourse against Epicurus, I ought in my turn to be
solicitous to hear what you can say against the Stoics; and I therefore
will give you my best attention, for I believe you are, as usual, well
prepared for the engagement.
I wish, by Hercules! I were, replies Cotta; for it is more difficult to
dispute with Lucilius than it was with you.
319Why so? says Velleius.
Because, replies Cotta, your Epicurus, in my opinion, does not contend
strongly for the Gods: he only, for the sake of avoiding any
unpopularity or punishment, is afraid to deny their existence; for when
he asserts that the Gods are wholly inactive and regardless of
everything, and that they have limbs like ours, but make no use of them,
he seems to jest with us, and to think it sufficient if he allows that
there are beings of any kind happy and eternal. But with regard to
Balbus, I suppose you observed how many things were said by him, which,
however false they may be, yet have a perfect coherence and connection;
therefore, my design, as I said, in opposing him, is not so much to
confute his principles as to induce him to explain what I do not clearly
understand: for which reason, Balbus, I will give you the choice, either
to answer me every particular as I go on, or permit me to proceed
without interruption. If you want any explanation, replies Balbus, I
would rather you would propose your doubts singly; but if your intention
is rather to confute me than to seek instruction for yourself, it shall
be as you please; I will either answer you immediately on every point,
or stay till you have finished your discourse.
II. Very well, says Cotta; then let us proceed as our conversation shall
direct. But before I enter on the subject, I have a word to say
concerning myself; for I am greatly influenced by your authority, and
your exhortation at the conclusion of your discourse, when you desired
me to remember that I was Cotta and Pontifex; by which I presume you
intimated that I should defend the sacred rites and religion and
ceremonies which we received from our ancestors. Most undoubtedly I
always have, and always shall defend them, nor shall the arguments
either of the learned or unlearned ever remove the opinions which I have
imbibed from them concerning the worship of the immortal Gods. In
matters of religion I submit to the rules of the high-priests, T.
Coruncanius, P. Scipio, and P. Scævola; not to the sentiments of Zeno,
Cleanthes, or Chrysippus; and I pay a greater regard to what C. Lælius,
one of our augurs and wise men, has written concerning religion, in that
noble oration of his, than to the most eminent of the Stoics: and as the
whole religion of the Romans at
320first consisted in sacrifices and
divination by birds, to which have since been added predictions, if the
interpreters
242 of the Sibylline oracle or the aruspices have foretold
any event from portents and prodigies, I have ever thought that there
was no point of all these holy things which deserved to be despised. I
have been even persuaded that Romulus, by instituting divination, and
Numa, by establishing sacrifices, laid the foundation of Rome, which
undoubtedly would never have risen to such a height of grandeur if the
Gods had not been made propitious by this worship. These, Balbus, are my
sentiments both as a priest and as Cotta. But you must bring me to your
opinion by the force of your reason: for I have a right to demand from
you, as a philosopher, a reason for the religion which you would have me
embrace. But I must believe the religion of our ancestors without any
proof.
III. What proof, says Balbus, do you require of me? You have proposed,
says Cotta, four articles. First of all, you undertook to prove that
there “are Gods;” secondly, “of what kind and character they are;”
thirdly, that “the universe is governed by them;” lastly, that “they
provide for the welfare of mankind in particular.” Thus, if I remember
rightly, you divided your discourse. Exactly so, replies Balbus; but let
us see what you require.
Let us examine, says Cotta, every proposition. The first one—that there
are Gods—is never contested but by the most impious of men; nay, though
it can never be rooted out of my mind, yet I believe it on the authority
of our ancestors, and not on the proofs which you have brought. Why do
you expect a proof from me, says Balbus, if you thoroughly believe it?
Because, says Cotta, I come to this discussion as if I had never thought
of the Gods, or heard anything concerning them. Take me as a disciple
wholly ignorant and unbiassed, and prove to me all the points which I
ask.
Begin, then, replies Balbus. I would first know, says Cotta, why you
have been so long in proving the existence of the Gods, which you said
was a point so very evident to all, that there was no need of any proof?
In that, answers
321Balbus, I have followed your example, whom I have
often observed, when pleading in the Forum, to load the judge with all
the arguments which the nature of your cause would permit. This also is
the practice of philosophers, and I have a right to follow it. Besides,
you may as well ask me why I look upon you with two eyes, since I can
see you with one.
IV. You shall judge, then, yourself, says Cotta, if this is a very just
comparison; for, when I plead, I do not dwell upon any point agreed to
be self-evident, because long reasoning only serves to confound the
clearest matters; besides, though I might take this method in pleading,
yet I should not make use of it in such a discourse as this, which
requires the nicest distinction. And with regard to your making use of
one eye only when you look on me, there is no reason for it, since
together they have the same view; and since nature, to which you
attribute wisdom, has been pleased to give us two passages by which we
receive light. But the truth is, that it was because you did not think
that the existence of the Gods was so evident as you could wish that you
therefore brought so many proofs. It was sufficient for me to believe it
on the tradition of our ancestors; and since you disregard authorities,
and appeal to reason, permit my reason to defend them against yours. The
proofs on which you found the existence of the Gods tend only to render
a proposition doubtful that, in my opinion, is not so; I have not only
retained in my memory the whole of these proofs, but even the order in
which you proposed them. The first was, that when we lift up our eyes
towards the heavens, we immediately conceive that there is some divinity
that governs those celestial bodies; on which you quoted this passage—
Look up to the refulgent heaven above,
Which all men call, unanimously, Jove;
intimating that we should invoke that as Jupiter, rather than our
Capitoline Jove243, or that it is evident to the whole world that
those bodies are Gods which Velleius and many others do not place even
in the rank of animated beings.
322Another strong proof, in your opinion, was that the belief of the
existence of the Gods was universal, and that mankind was daily more and
more convinced of it. What! should an affair of such importance be left
to the decision of fools, who, by your sect especially, are called
madmen?
V. But the Gods have appeared to us, as to Posthumius at the Lake
Regillus, and to Vatienus in the Salarian Way: something you mentioned,
too, I know not what, of a battle of the Locrians at Sagra. Do you
believe that the Tyndaridæ, as you called them; that is, men sprung from
men, and who were buried in Lacedæmon, as we learn from Homer, who lived
in the next age—do you believe, I say, that they appeared to Vatienus
on the road mounted on white horses, without any servant to attend them,
to tell the victory of the Romans to a country fellow rather than to M.
Cato, who was at that time the chief person of the senate? Do you take
that print of a horse’s hoof which is now to be seen on a stone at
Regillus to be made by Castor’s horse? Should you not believe, what is
probable, that the souls of eminent men, such as the Tyndaridæ, are
divine and immortal, rather than that those bodies which had been
reduced to ashes should mount on horses, and fight in an army? If you
say that was possible, you ought to show how it is so, and not amuse us
with fabulous old women’s stories.
Do you take these for fabulous stories? says Balbus. Is not the temple,
built by Posthumius in honor of Castor and Pollux, to be seen in the
Forum? Is not the decree of the senate concerning Vatienus still
subsisting? As to the affair of Sagra, it is a common proverb among the
Greeks; when they would affirm anything strongly, they say “It is as
certain as what passed at Sagra.” Ought not such authorities to move
you? You oppose me, replies Cotta, with stories, but I ask reasons of
you244. *В *В *
VI. We are now to speak of predictions. No one can avoid what is to
come, and, indeed, it is commonly useless to know it; for it is a
miserable case to be afflicted to no purpose, and not to have even the
last, the common comfort, 323hope, which, according to your principles,
none can have; for you say that fate governs all things, and call that
fate which has been true from all eternity. What advantage, then, is the
knowledge of futurity to us, or how does it assist us to guard against
impending evils, since it will come inevitably?
But whence comes that divination? To whom is owing that knowledge from
the entrails of beasts? Who first made observations from the voice of
the crow? Who invented the Lots?245 Not that I give no credit to these
things, or that I despise Attius Navius’s staff, which you mentioned;
but I ought to be informed how these things are understood by
philosophers, especially as the diviners are often wrong in their
conjectures. But physicians, you say, are likewise often mistaken. What
comparison can there be between divination, of the origin of which we
are ignorant, and physic, which proceeds on principles intelligible to
every one? You believe that the Decii,246 in devoting themselves to
death, appeased the Gods. How great, then, was the iniquity of the Gods
that they could not be appeased but at the price of such noble blood!
That was the stratagem of generals such as the Greeks call ПѓП„ПЃО±П„бЅµОіО·ОјО±,
and it was a stratagem worthy such illustrious leaders, who consulted
the public good even at the expense of their lives: they conceived
rightly, what indeed happened, that if the general rode furiously upon
the enemy, the whole army would follow his example. As to the voice of
the Fauns, I never heard it. If you assure me that you have, I shall
believe you, though I really know not what a Faun is.
VII. I do not, then, O Balbus, from anything that you have said,
perceive as yet that it is proved that there are Gods. I believe it,
indeed, but not from any arguments of the Stoics. Cleanthes, you have
said, attributes the idea that men have of the Gods to four causes. In
the first place (as I have already sufficiently mentioned), to a
foreknowledge 324of future events; secondly, to tempests, and other shocks
of nature; thirdly, to the utility and plenty of things we enjoy;
fourthly, to the invariable order of the stars and the heavens. The
arguments drawn from foreknowledge I have already answered. With regard
to tempests in the air, the sea, and the earth, I own that many people
are affrighted by them, and imagine that the immortal Gods are the
authors of them.
But the question is, not whether there are people who believe that there
are Gods, but whether there are Gods or not. As to the two other causes
of Cleanthes, one of which is derived from the great abundance of
desirable things which we enjoy, the other from the invariable order of
the seasons and the heavens, I shall treat on them when I answer your
discourse concerning the providence of the Gods—a point, Balbus, upon
which you have spoken at great length. I shall likewise defer till then
examining the argument which you attribute to Chrysippus, that “if there
is in nature anything which surpasses the power of man to produce, there
must consequently be some being better than man.” I shall also postpone,
till we come to that part of my argument, your comparison of the world
to a fine house, your observations on the proportion and harmony of the
universe, and those smart, short reasons of Zeno which you quote; and I
shall examine at the same time your reasons drawn from natural
philosophy, concerning that fiery force and that vital heat which you
regard as the principle of all things; and I will investigate, in its
proper place, all that you advanced the other day on the existence of
the Gods, and on the sense and understanding which you attributed to the
sun, the moon, and all the stars; and I shall ask you this question over
and over again, By what proofs are you convinced yourself there are
Gods?
VIII. I thought, says Balbus, that I had brought ample proofs to
establish this point. But such is your manner of opposing, that, when
you seem on the point of interrogating me, and when I am preparing to
answer, you suddenly divert the discourse, and give me no opportunity to
reply to you; and thus those most important points concerning divination
and fate are neglected which we Stoics 325have thoroughly examined, but
which your school has only slightly touched upon. But they are not
thought essential to the question in hand; therefore, if you think
proper, do not confuse them together, that we in this discussion may
come to a clear explanation of the subject of our present inquiry.
Very well, says Cotta. Since, then, you have divided the whole question
into four parts, and I have said all that I had to say on the first, I
will take the second into consideration; in which, when you attempted to
show what the character of the Gods was, you seemed to me rather to
prove that there are none; for you said that it was the greatest
difficulty to draw our minds from the prepossessions of the eyes; but
that as nothing is more excellent than the Deity, you did not doubt that
the world was God, because there is nothing better in nature than the
world, and so we may reasonably think it animated, or, rather, perceive
it in our minds as clearly as if it were obvious to our eyes.
Now, in what sense do you say there is nothing better than the world? If
you mean that there is nothing more beautiful, I agree with you; that
there is nothing more adapted to our wants, I likewise agree with you:
but if you mean that nothing is wiser than the world, I am by no means
of your opinion. Not that I find it difficult to conceive anything in my
mind independent of my eyes; on the contrary, the more I separate my
mind from my eyes, the less I am able to comprehend your opinion.
IX. Nothing is better than the world, you say. Nor is there, indeed,
anything on earth better than the city of Rome; do you think, therefore,
that our city has a mind; that it thinks and reasons; or that this most
beautiful city, being void of sense, is not preferable to an ant,
because an ant has sense, understanding, reason, and memory? You should
consider, Balbus, what ought to be allowed you, and not advance things
because they please you.
For that old, concise, and, as it seemed to you, acute syllogism of Zeno
has been all which you have so much enlarged upon in handling this
topic: “That which reasons is superior to that which does not; nothing
is superior to the world; therefore the world reasons.” If you would
326prove also that the world can very well read a book, follow the example
of Zeno, and say, “That which can read is better than that which cannot;
nothing is better than the world; the world therefore can read.” After
the same manner you may prove the world to be an orator, a
mathematician, a musician—that it possesses all sciences, and, in
short, is a philosopher. You have often said that God made all things,
and that no cause can produce an effect unlike itself. From hence it
will follow, not only that the world is animated, and is wise, but also
plays upon the fiddle and the flute, because it produces men who play on
those instruments. Zeno, therefore, the chief of your sect, advances no
argument sufficient to induce us to think that the world reasons, or,
indeed, that it is animated at all, and consequently none to think it a
Deity; though it may be said that there is nothing superior to it, as
there is nothing more beautiful, nothing more useful to us, nothing more
adorned, and nothing more regular in its motions. But if the world,
considered as one great whole, is not God, you should not surely deify,
as you have done, that infinite multitude of stars which only form a
part of it, and which so delight you with the regularity of their
eternal courses; not but that there is something truly wonderful and
incredible in their regularity; but this regularity of motion, Balbus,
may as well be ascribed to a natural as to a divine cause.
X. What can be more regular than the flux and reflux of the Euripus at
Chalcis, the Sicilian sea, and the violence of the ocean in those
parts247
where the rapid tide
Does Europe from the Libyan coast divide?
The same appears on the Spanish and British coasts. Must we conclude
that some Deity appoints and directs these ebbings and flowings to
certain fixed times? Consider, I pray, if everything which is regular in
its motion is deemed divine, whether it will not follow that tertian and
quartan agues must likewise be so, as their returns have the greatest
regularity. These effects are to be explained by reason; but, because
you are unable to assign any, you have recourse to a Deity as your last
refuge.
327The arguments of Chrysippus appeared to you of great weight; a
man undoubtedly of great quickness and subtlety (I call those quick who
have a sprightly turn of thought, and those subtle whose minds are
seasoned by use as their hands are by labor): “If,” says he, “there is
anything which is beyond the power of man to produce, the being who
produces it is better than man. Man is unable to make what is in the
world; the being, therefore, that could do it is superior to man. What
being is there but a God superior to man? Therefore there is a God.”
These arguments are founded on the same erroneous principles as Zeno’s,
for he does not define what is meant by being better or more excellent,
or distinguish between an intelligent cause and a natural cause.
Chrysippus adds, “If there are no Gods, there is nothing better than
man; but we cannot, without the highest arrogance, have this idea of
ourselves.” Let us grant that it is arrogance in man to think himself
better than the world; but to comprehend that he has understanding and
reason, and that in Orion and Canicula there is neither, is no
arrogance, but an indication of good sense. “Since we suppose,”
continues he, “when we see a beautiful house, that it was built for the
master, and not for mice, we should likewise judge that the world is the
mansion of the Gods.” Yes, if I believed that the Gods built the world;
but not if, as I believe, and intend to prove, it is the work of nature.
XI. Socrates, in Xenophon, asks, “Whence had man his understanding, if
there was none in the world?” And I ask, Whence had we speech, harmony,
singing; unless we think it is the sun conversing with the moon when she
approaches near it, or that the world forms an harmonious concert, as
Pythagoras imagines? This, Balbus, is the effect of nature; not of that
nature which proceeds artificially, as Zeno says, and the character of
which I shall presently examine into, but a nature which, by its own
proper motions and mutations, modifies everything.
For I readily agree to what you said about the harmony and general
agreement of nature, which you pronounced to be firmly bound and united
together, as it were, by ties of blood; but I do not approve of what you
added, that “it could not possibly be so, unless it were so united by
328one divine spirit.” On the contrary, the whole subsists by the power of
nature, independently of the Gods, and there is a kind of sympathy (as
the Greeks call it) which joins together all the parts of the universe;
and the greater that is in its own power, the less is it necessary to
have recourse to a divine intelligence.
XII. But how will you get rid of the objections which Carneades made?
“If,” says he, “there is no body immortal, there is none eternal; but
there is no body immortal, nor even indivisible, or that cannot be
separated and disunited; and as every animal is in its nature passive,
so there is not one which is not subject to the impressions of
extraneous bodies; none, that is to say, which can avoid the necessity
of enduring and suffering: and if every animal is mortal, there is none
immortal; so, likewise, if every animal may be cut up and divided, there
is none indivisible, none eternal, but all are liable to be affected by,
and compelled to submit to, external power. Every animal, therefore, is
necessarily mortal, dissoluble, and divisible.”
For as there is no wax, no silver, no brass which cannot be converted
into something else, whatever is composed of wax, or silver, or brass
may cease to be what it is. By the same reason, if all the elements are
mutable, every body is mutable.
Now, according to your doctrine, all the elements are mutable; all
bodies, therefore, are mutable. But if there were any body immortal,
then all bodies would not be mutable. Every body, then, is mortal; for
every body is either water, air, fire, or earth, or composed of the four
elements together, or of some of them. Now, there is not one of all
these elements that does not perish; for earthly bodies are fragile:
water is so soft that the least shock will separate its parts, and fire
and air yield to the least impulse, and are subject to dissolution;
besides, any of these elements perish when converted into another
nature, as when water is formed from earth, the air from water, and the
sky from air, and when they change in the same manner back again.
Therefore, if there is nothing but what is perishable in the composition
of all animals, there is no animal eternal.
XIII. But, not to insist on these arguments, there is no 329animal to be
found that had not a beginning, and will not have an end; for every
animal being sensitive, they are consequently all sensible of cold and
heat, sweet and bitter; nor can they have pleasing sensations without
being subject to the contrary. As, therefore, they receive pleasure,
they likewise receive pain; and whatever being is subject to pain must
necessarily be subject to death. It must be allowed, therefore, that
every animal is mortal.
Besides, a being that is not sensible of pleasure or pain cannot have
the essence of an animal; if, then, on the one hand, every animal must
be sensible of pleasure and pain, and if, on the other, every being that
has these sensations cannot be immortal, we may conclude that as there
is no animal insensible, there is none immortal. Besides, there is no
animal without inclination and aversion—an inclination to that which is
agreeable to nature, and an aversion to the contrary: there are in the
case of every animal some things which they covet, and others they
reject. What they reject are repugnant to their nature, and consequently
would destroy them. Every animal, therefore, is inevitably subject to be
destroyed. There are innumerable arguments to prove that whatever is
sensitive is perishable; for cold, heat, pleasure, pain, and all that
affects the sense, when they become excessive, cause destruction. Since,
then, there is no animal that is not sensitive, there is none immortal.
XIV. The substance of an animal is either simple or compound; simple, if
it is composed only of earth, of fire, of air, or of water (and of such
a sort of being we can form no idea); compound, if it is formed of
different elements, which have each their proper situation, and have a
natural tendency to it—this element tending towards the highest parts,
that towards the lowest, and another towards the middle. This
conjunction may for some time subsist, but not forever; for every
element must return to its first situation. No animal, therefore, is
eternal.
But your school, Balbus, allows fire only to be the sole active
principle; an opinion which I believe you derive from Heraclitus, whom
some men understand in one sense, some in another: but since he seems
unwilling to be understood, we will pass him by. You Stoics, then, say
that 330fire is the universal principle of all things; that all living
bodies cease to live on the extinction of that heat; and that throughout
all nature whatever is sensible of that heat lives and flourishes. Now,
I cannot conceive that bodies should perish for want of heat, rather
than for want of moisture or air, especially as they even die through
excess of heat; so that the life of animals does not depend more on fire
than on the other elements.
However, air and water have this quality in common with fire and heat.
But let us see to what this tends. If I am not mistaken, you believe
that in all nature there is nothing but fire, which is self-animated.
Why fire rather than air, of which the life of animals consists, and
which is called from thence anima,248 the soul? But how is it that
you take it for granted that life is nothing but fire? It seems more
probable that it is a compound of fire and air. But if fire is
self-animated, unmixed with any other element, it must be sensitive,
because it renders our bodies sensitive; and the same objection which I
just now made will arise, that whatever is sensitive must necessarily be
susceptible of pleasure and pain, and whatever is sensible of pain is
likewise subject to the approach of death; therefore you cannot prove
fire to be eternal.
You Stoics hold that all fire has need of nourishment, without which it
cannot possibly subsist; that the sun, moon, and all the stars are fed
either with fresh or salt waters; and the reason that Cleanthes gives
why the sun is retrograde, and does not go beyond the tropics in the
summer or winter, is that he may not be too far from his sustenance.
This I shall fully examine hereafter; but at present we may conclude
that whatever may cease to be cannot of its own nature be eternal; that
if fire wants sustenance, it will cease to be, and that, therefore, fire
is not of its own nature eternal.
XV. After all, what kind of a Deity must that be who 331is not graced with
one single virtue, if we should succeed in forming this idea of such a
one? Must we not attribute prudence to a Deity? a virtue which consists
in the knowledge of things good, bad, and indifferent. Yet what need has
a being for the discernment of good and ill who neither has nor can have
any ill? Of what use is reason to him? of what use is understanding? We
men, indeed, find them useful to aid us in finding out things which are
obscure by those which are clear to us; but nothing can be obscure to a
Deity. As to justice, which gives to every one his own, it is not the
concern of the Gods; since that virtue, according to your doctrine,
received its birth from men and from civil society. Temperance consists
in abstinence from corporeal pleasures, and if such abstinence hath a
place in heaven, so also must the pleasures abstained from. Lastly, if
fortitude is ascribed to the Deity, how does it appear? In afflictions,
in labor, in danger? None of these things can affect a God. How, then,
can we conceive this to be a Deity that makes no use of reason, and is
not endowed with any virtue?
However, when I consider what is advanced by the Stoics, my contempt for
the ignorant multitude vanishes. For these are their divinities. The
Syrians worshipped a fish. The Egyptians consecrated beasts of almost
every kind. The Greeks deified many men; as Alabandus249 at Alabandæ,
Tenes at Tenedos; and all Greece pay divine honors to Leucothea (who was
before called Ino), to her son Palæmon, to Hercules, to Æsculapius, and
to the Tyndaridæ; our own people to Romulus, and to many others, who, as
citizens newly admitted into the ancient body, they imagine have been
received into heaven.
These are the Gods of the illiterate.
XVI. What are the notions of you philosophers? In what respect are they
superior to these ideas? I shall pass them over; for they are certainly
very admirable. Let the world, then, be a Deity, for that, I conceive,
is what you mean by
The refulgent heaven above,
Which all men call, unanimously, Jove.
332But why are we to add many more Gods? What a multitude of them there
is! At least, it seems so to me; for every constellation, according to
you, is a Deity: to some you give the name of beasts, as the goat, the
scorpion, the bull, the lion; to others the names of inanimate things,
as the ship, the altar, the crown.
But supposing these were to be allowed, how can the rest be granted, or
even so much as understood? When we call corn Ceres, and wine Bacchus,
we make use of the common manner of speaking; but do you think any one
so mad as to believe that his food is a Deity? With regard to those who,
you say, from having been men became Gods, I should be very willing to
learn of you, either how it was possible formerly, or, if it had ever
been, why is it not so now? I do not conceive, as things are at present,
how Hercules,
Burn’d with fiery torches on Mount Œta,
as Accius says, should rise, with the flames,
To the eternal mansions of his father.
Besides, Homer also says that Ulysses
250 met him in the shades below,
among the other dead.
But yet I should be glad to know which Hercules we should chiefly
worship; for they who have searched into those histories, which are but
little known, tell us of several. The most ancient is he who fought with
Apollo about the Tripos of Delphi, and is son of Jupiter and Lisyto; and
of the most ancient Jupiters too, for we find many Jupiters also in the
Grecian chronicles. The second is the Egyptian Hercules, and is believed
to be the son of Nilus, and to be the author of the Phrygian characters.
The third, to whom they offered sacrifices, is one of the
333Idæi
Dactyli.
251 The fourth is the son of Jupiter and Asteria, the sister
of Latona, chiefly honored by the Tyrians, who pretend that
Carthago
252 is his daughter. The fifth, called Belus, is worshipped in
India. The sixth is the son of Alcmena by Jupiter; but by the third
Jupiter, for there are many Jupiters, as you shall soon see.
XVII. Since this examination has led me so far, I will convince you that
in matters of religion I have learned more from the pontifical rites,
the customs of our ancestors, and the vessels of Numa,
253 which Lælius
mentions in his little Golden Oration, than from all the learning of the
Stoics; for tell me, if I were a disciple of your school, what answer
could I make to these questions? If there are Gods, are nymphs also
Goddesses? If they are Goddesses, are Pans and Satyrs in the same rank?
But they are not; consequently, nymphs are not Goddesses. Yet they have
temples publicly dedicated to them. What do you conclude from thence?
Others who have temples are not therefore Gods. But let us go on. You
call Jupiter and Neptune Gods; their brother Pluto, then, is one; and if
so, those rivers also are Deities which they say flow in the infernal
regions—Acheron, Cocytus, Pyriphlegethon; Charon also, and Cerberus,
are Gods; but that cannot be allowed; nor can Pluto be placed among the
Deities. What, then, will you say of his brothers?
Thus reasons Carneades; not with any design to destroy the existence of
the Gods (for what would less become a philosopher?), but to convince us
that on that matter the Stoics have said nothing plausible. If, then,
Jupiter and Neptune are Gods, adds he, can that divinity be denied to
their father Saturn, who is principally worshipped throughout the West?
If Saturn is a God, then must his father, CЕ“lus, be one too, and so must
the parents of CЕ“lus, which are the Sky and Day, as also their brothers
and sisters, which by ancient genealogists are
334thus named: Love,
Deceit, Fear, Labor, Envy, Fate, Old Age, Death, Darkness, Misery,
Lamentation, Favor, Fraud, Obstinacy, the Destinies, the Hesperides, and
Dreams; all which are the offspring of Erebus and Night. These monstrous
Deities, therefore, must be received, or else those from whom they
sprung must be disallowed.
XVIII. If you say that Apollo, Vulcan, Mercury, and the rest of that
sort are Gods, can you doubt the divinity of Hercules and Г†sculapius,
Bacchus, Castor and Pollux? These are worshipped as much as those, and
even more in some places. Therefore they must be numbered among the
Gods, though on the mother’s side they are only of mortal race.
Aristæus, who is said to have been the son of Apollo, and to have found
out the art of making oil from the olive; Theseus, the son of Neptune;
and the rest whose fathers were Deities, shall they not be placed in the
number of the Gods? But what think you of those whose mothers were
Goddesses? They surely have a better title to divinity; for, in the
civil law, as he is a freeman who is born of a freewoman, so, in the law
of nature, he whose mother is a Goddess must be a God. The isle
Astypalæa religiously honor Achilles; and if he is a Deity, Orpheus and
Rhesus are so, who were born of one of the Muses; unless, perhaps, there
may be a privilege belonging to sea marriages which land marriages have
not. Orpheus and Rhesus are nowhere worshipped; and if they are
therefore not Gods, because they are nowhere worshipped as such, how can
the others be Deities? You, Balbus, seemed to agree with me that the
honors which they received were not from their being regarded as
immortals, but as men richly endued with virtue.
But if you think Latona a Goddess, how can you avoid admitting Hecate to
be one also, who was the daughter of Asteria, Latona’s sister? Certainly
she is one, if we may judge by the altars erected to her in Greece. And
if Hecate is a Goddess, how can you refuse that rank to the Eumenides?
for they also have a temple at Athens, and, if I understand right, the
Romans have consecrated a grove to them. The Furies, too, whom we look
upon as the inspectors into and scourges of impiety, I suppose, must
have their divinity too. As you hold that there is some divinity
335presides over every human affair, there is one who presides over the
travail of matrons, whose name,
Natio, is derived
a nascentibus,
from nativities, and to whom we used to sacrifice in our processions in
the fields of Ardæa; but if she is a Deity, we must likewise acknowledge
all those you mentioned, Honor, Faith, Intellect, Concord; by the same
rule also, Hope, Juno, Moneta,
254 and every idle phantom, every child
of our imagination, are Deities. But as this consequence is quite
inadmissible, do not you either defend the cause from which it flows.
XIX. What say you to this? If these are Deities, which we worship and
regard as such, why are not Serapis and Isis
255 placed in the same
rank? And if they are admitted, what reason have we to reject the Gods
of the barbarians? Thus we should deify oxen, horses, the ibis, hawks,
asps, crocodiles, fishes, dogs, wolves, cats, and many other beasts. If
we go back to the source of this superstition, we must equally condemn
all the Deities from which they proceed. Shall Ino, whom the Greeks call
Leucothea, and we Matuta, be reputed a Goddess, because she was the
daughter of Cadmus, and shall that title be refused to Circe and
Pasiphae,
256 who had the sun for their father, and Perseis, daughter
of the Ocean, for their mother? It is true, Circe has divine honors paid
her by our colony of Circæum; therefore you call her a Goddess; but what
will you say of Medea, the granddaughter of the Sun and the Ocean, and
daughter of Г†etes and Idyia? What will you say of her brother Absyrtus,
whom Pacuvius calls Г†gialeus, though the other name is more frequent in
the writings of the ancients? If you did not deify one as well as the
other, what will become of Ino? for all these Deities have the same
origin.
Shall Amphiaraus and Tryphonius be called Gods? Our publicans, when some
lands in BЕ“otia were exempted from the tax, as belonging to the immortal
Gods, denied that
336any were immortal who had been men. But if you deify
these, Erechtheus surely is a God, whose temple and priest we have seen
at Athens. And can you, then, refuse to acknowledge also Codrus, and
many others who shed their blood for the preservation of their country?
And if it is not allowable to consider all these men as Gods, then,
certainly, probabilities are not in favor of our acknowledging the
Divinity of those previously mentioned beings from whom these have
proceeded.
It is easy to observe, likewise, that if in many countries people have
paid divine honors to the memory of those who have signalized their
courage, it was done in order to animate others to practise virtue, and
to expose themselves the more willingly to dangers in their country’s
cause. From this motive the Athenians have deified Erechtheus and his
daughters, and have erected also a temple, called Leocorion, to the
daughters of Leus.
257 Alabandus is more honored in the city which he
founded than any of the more illustrious Deities; from thence
Stratonicus had a pleasant turn—as he had many—when he was troubled
with an impertinent fellow who insisted that Alabandus was a God, but
that Hercules was not; “Very well,” says he, “then let the anger of
Alabandus fall upon me, and that of Hercules upon you.”
XX. Do you not consider, Balbus, to what lengths your arguments for the
divinity of the heaven and the stars will carry you? You deify the sun
and the moon, which the Greeks take to be Apollo and Diana. If the moon
is a Deity, the morning-star, the other planets, and all the fixed stars
are also Deities; and why shall not the rainbow be placed in that
number? for it is so wonderfully beautiful that it is justly said to be
the daughter of Thaumas.
258 But if you deify the rainbow, what regard
will you pay to the clouds? for the colors which appear in the bow are
only formed of the clouds, one of which is said to have brought forth
the Centaurs; and if you deify the clouds, you cannot pay less regard to
the seasons, which the Roman people have really consecrated. Tempests,
showers,
337storms, and whirlwinds must then be Deities. It is certain, at
least, that our captains used to sacrifice a victim to the waves before
they embarked on any voyage.
As you deify the earth under the name of Ceres,
259 because, as you
said, she bears fruits (
a gerendo), and the ocean under that of
Neptune, rivers and fountains have the same right. Thus we see that
Maso, the conqueror of Corsica, dedicated a temple to a fountain, and
the names of the Tiber, Spino, Almo, Nodinus, and other neighboring
rivers are in the prayers
260 of the augurs. Therefore, either the
number of such Deities will be infinite, or we must admit none of them,
and wholly disapprove of such an endless series of superstition.
XXI. None of all these assertions, then, are to be admitted. I must
proceed now, Balbus, to answer those who say that, with regard to those
deified mortals, so religiously and devoutly reverenced, the public
opinion should have the force of reality. To begin, then: they who are
called theologists say that there are three Jupiters; the first and
second of whom were born in Arcadia; one of whom was the son of Г†ther,
and father of Proserpine and Bacchus; the other the son of CЕ“lus, and
father of Minerva, who is called the Goddess and inventress of war; the
third one born of Saturn in the isle of Crete,
261 where his sepulchre
is shown. The sons of Jupiter (
О”О№бЅ№ПѓОєОїП…ПЃОїО№) also, among the Greeks, have
many names; first, the three who at Athens have the title of
Anactes,
262 Tritopatreus, Eubuleus, and Dionysus, sons of the most
ancient king Jupiter and Proserpine; the next are Castor and Pollux,
sons of the third Jupiter and Leda; and, lastly, three others, by some
called Alco,
263 Melampus, and Tmolus, sons of Atreus, the son of
Pelops.
338As to the Muses, there were at first four—Thelxiope, Aœde, Arche, and
Melete—daughters of the second Jupiter; afterward there were nine,
daughters of the third Jupiter and Mnemosyne; there were also nine
others, having the same appellations, born of Pierus and Antiopa, by the
poets usually called Pierides and Pieriæ. Though
Sol (the sun) is so
called, you say, because he is
solus (single); yet how many suns do
theologists mention? There is one, the son of Jupiter and grandson of
Г†ther; another, the son of Hyperion; a third, who, the Egyptians say,
was of the city Heliopolis, sprung from Vulcan, the son of Nilus; a
fourth is said to have been born at Rhodes of Acantho, in the times of
the heroes, and was the grandfather of Jalysus, Camirus, and Lindus; a
fifth, of whom, it is pretended, Aretes and Circe were born at Colchis.
XXII. There are likewise several Vulcans. The first (who had of Minerva
that Apollo whom the ancient historians call the tutelary God of Athens)
was the son of CЕ“lus; the second, whom the Egyptians call Opas,
264 and
whom they looked upon as the protector of Egypt, is the son of Nilus;
the third, who is said to have been the master of the forges at Lemnos,
was the son of the third Jupiter and of Juno; the fourth, who possessed
the islands near Sicily called Vulcaniæ,
265 was the son of Menalius.
One Mercury had CЕ“lus for his father and Dies for his mother; another,
who is said to dwell in a cavern, and is the same as Trophonius, is the
son of Valens and Phoronis. A third, of whom, and of Penelope, Pan was
the offspring, is the son of the third Jupiter and Maia. A fourth, whom
the Egyptians think it a crime to name, is the son of Nilus. A fifth,
whom we call, in their language, Thoth, as with them the first month of
the year is called, is he whom the people of Pheneum
266 worship, and
who is said to have killed Argus, to have fled for it into Egypt, and to
have given laws and learning to the Egyptians. The first of the
Г†sculapii, the God of Arcadia, who is said to have invented the probe
and to have been the first person who taught men to use bandages for
wounds, is the son of
339Apollo. The second, who was killed with thunder,
and is said to be buried in Cynosura,
267 is the brother of the second
Mercury. The third, who is said to have found out the art of purging the
stomach, and of drawing teeth, is the son of Arsippus and Arsinoe; and
in Arcadia there is shown his tomb, and the wood which is consecrated to
him, near the river Lusium.
XXIII. I have already spoken of the most ancient of the Apollos, who is
the son of Vulcan, and tutelar God of Athens. There is another, son of
Corybas, and native of Crete, for which island he is said to have
contended with Jupiter himself. A third, who came from the regions of
the Hyperborei
268 to Delphi, is the son of the third Jupiter and of
Latona. A fourth was of Arcadia, whom the Arcadians called Nomio,
269
because they regarded him as their legislator. There are likewise many
Dianas. The first, who is thought to be the mother of the winged Cupid,
is the daughter of Jupiter and Proserpine. The second, who is more
known, is daughter of the third Jupiter and of Latona. The third, whom
the Greeks often call by her father’s name, is the daughter of Upis
270
and Glauce. There are many also of the Dionysi. The first was the son of
Jupiter and Proserpine. The second, who is said to have killed Nysa, was
the son of Nilus. The third, who reigned in Asia, and for whom the
Sabazia
271 were instituted, was the son of Caprius. The fourth, for
whom they celebrate the Orphic festivals, sprung from Jupiter and Luna.
The fifth, who is supposed to have instituted the Trieterides, was the
son of Nysus and Thyone.
The first Venus, who has a temple at Elis, was the daughter of CЕ“lus and
Dies. The second arose out of the froth of the sea, and became, by
Mercury, the mother of the second Cupid. The third, the daughter of
Jupiter and Diana, was married to Vulcan, but is said to have had
Anteros by Mars. The fourth was a Syrian, born of Tyro, who is called
Astarte, and is said to have been married to
340Adonis. I have already
mentioned one Minerva, mother of Apollo. Another, who is worshipped at
Sais, a city in Egypt, sprung from Nilus. The third, whom I have also
mentioned, was daughter of Jupiter. The fourth, sprung from Jupiter and
Coryphe, the daughter of the Ocean; the Arcadians call her Coria, and
make her the inventress of chariots. A fifth, whom they paint with wings
at her heels, was daughter of Pallas, and is said to have killed her
father for endeavoring to violate her chastity. The first Cupid is said
to be the son of Mercury and the first Diana; the second, of Mercury and
the second Venus; the third, who is the same as Anteros, of Mars and the
third Venus.
All these opinions arise from old stories that were spread in Greece;
the belief in which, Balbus, you well know, ought to be stopped, lest
religion should suffer. But you Stoics, so far from refuting them, even
give them authority by the mysterious sense which you pretend to find in
them. Can you, then, think, after this plain refutation, that there is
need to employ more subtle reasonings? But to return from this
digression.
XXIV. We see that the mind, faith, hope, virtue, honor, victory, health,
concord, and things of such kind, are purely natural, and have nothing
of divinity in them; for either they are inherent in us, as the mind,
faith, hope, virtue, and concord are; or else they are to be desired, as
honor, health, and victory. I know indeed that they are useful to us,
and see that statues have been religiously erected for them; but as to
their divinity, I shall begin to believe it when you have proved it for
certain. Of this kind I may particularly mention Fortune, which is
allowed to be ever inseparable from inconstancy and temerity, which are
certainly qualities unworthy of a divine being.
But what delight do you take in the explication of fables, and in the
etymology of names?—that Cœlus was castrated by his son, and that
Saturn was bound in chains by his son! By your defence of these and such
like fictions you would make the authors of them appear not only not to
be madmen, but to have been even very wise. But the pains which you take
with your etymologies deserve our pity. That Saturn is so called because
se saturat annis, he is full of years; Mavors, Mars, because
magna
341vortit, he brings about mighty changes; Minerva, because
minuit, she
diminishes, or because
minatur, she threatens; Venus, because
venit
ad omnia, she comes to all; Ceres,
a gerendo, from bearing. How
dangerous is this method! for there are many names would puzzle you.
>From what would you derive Vejupiter and Vulcan? Though, indeed, if you
can derive Neptune
a nando, from swimming, in which you seem to me to
flounder about yourself more than Neptune, you may easily find the
origin of all names, since it is founded only upon the conformity of
some one letter. Zeno first, and after him Cleanthes and Chrysippus, are
put to the unnecessary trouble of explaining mere fables, and giving
reasons for the several appellations of every Deity; which is really
owning that those whom we call Gods are not the representations of
deities, but natural things, and that to judge otherwise is an error.
XXV. Yet this error has so much prevailed that even pernicious things
have not only the title of divinity ascribed to them, but have also
sacrifices offered to them; for Fever has a temple on the Palatine hill,
and Orbona another near that of the Lares, and we see on the Esquiline
hill an altar consecrated to Ill-fortune. Let all such errors be
banished from philosophy, if we would advance, in our dispute concerning
the immortal Gods, nothing unworthy of immortal beings. I know myself
what I ought to believe; which is far different from what you have said.
You take Neptune for an intelligence pervading the sea. You have the
same opinion of Ceres with regard to the earth. I cannot, I own, find
out, or in the least conjecture, what that intelligence of the sea or
the earth is. To learn, therefore, the existence of the Gods, and of
what description and character they are, I must apply elsewhere, not to
the Stoics.
Let us proceed to the two other parts of our dispute: first, “whether
there is a divine providence which governs the world;” and lastly,
“whether that providence particularly regards mankind;” for these are
the remaining propositions of your discourse; and I think that, if you
approve of it, we should examine these more accurately. With all my
heart, says Velleius, for I readily agree to what you have hitherto
said, and expect still greater things from you.
I am unwilling to interrupt you, says Balbus to Cotta,
342but we shall
take another opportunity, and I shall effectually convince you. But
272
*В *В *
XXVI.
Shall I adore, and bend the suppliant knee,
Who scorn their power and doubt their deity?
Does not Niobe here seem to reason, and by that reasoning to bring all
her misfortunes upon herself? But what a subtle expression is the
following!
On strength of will alone depends success;
a maxim capable of leading us into all that is bad.
Though I’m confined, his malice yet is vain,
His tortured heart shall answer pain for pain;
His ruin soothe my soul with soft content,
Lighten my chains, and welcome banishment!
This, now, is reason; that reason which you say the divine goodness has
denied to the brute creation, kindly to bestow it on men alone. How
great, how immense the favor! Observe the same Medea flying from her
father and her country:
The guilty wretch from her pursuer flies.
By her own hands the young Absyrtus slain,
His mangled limbs she scatters o’er the plain,
That the fond sire might sink beneath his woe,
And she to parricide her safety owe.
Reflection, as well as wickedness, must have been necessary to the
preparation of such a fact; and did he too, who prepared that fatal
repast for his brother, do it without reflection?
Revenge as great as Atreus’ injury
Shall sink his soul and crown his misery.
XXVII. Did not Thyestes himself, not content with having defiled his
brother’s bed (of which Atreus with great justice thus complains,
When faithless comforts, in the lewd embrace,
With vile adultery stain a royal race,
The blood thus mix’d in fouler currents flows,
Taints the rich soil, and breeds unnumber’d woes)—
343did he not, I say, by that adultery, aim at the possession of the
crown? Atreus thus continues:
A lamb, fair gift of heaven, with golden fleece,
Promised in vain to fix my crown in peace;
But base Thyestes, eager for the prey,
Crept to my bed, and stole the gem away.
Do you not perceive that Thyestes must have had a share of reason
proportionable to the greatness of his crimes—such crimes as are not
only represented to us on the stage, but such as we see committed, nay,
often exceeded, in the common course of life? The private houses of
individual citizens, the public courts, the senate, the camp, our
allies, our provinces, all agree that reason is the author of all the
ill, as well as of all the good, which is done; that it makes few act
well, and that but seldom, but many act ill, and that frequently; and
that, in short, the Gods would have shown greater benevolence in denying
us any reason at all than in sending us that which is accompanied with
so much mischief; for as wine is seldom wholesome, but often hurtful in
diseases, we think it more prudent to deny it to the patient than to run
the risk of so uncertain a remedy; so I do not know whether it would not
be better for mankind to be deprived of wit, thought, and penetration,
or what we call reason, since it is a thing pernicious to many and very
useful to few, than to have it bestowed upon them with so much
liberality and in such abundance. But if the divine will has really
consulted the good of man in this gift of reason, the good of those men
only was consulted on whom a well-regulated one is bestowed: how few
those are, if any, is very apparent. We cannot admit, therefore, that
the Gods consulted the good of a few only; the conclusion must be that
they consulted the good of none.
XXVIII. You answer that the ill use which a great part of mankind make
of reason no more takes away the goodness of the Gods, who bestow it as
a present of the greatest benefit to them, than the ill use which
children make of their patrimony diminishes the obligation which they
have to their parents for it. We grant you this; but where is the
similitude? It was far from Deianira’s design to injure Hercules when
she made him a present
344of the shirt dipped in the blood of the
Centaurs. Nor was it a regard to the welfare of Jason of Pheræ that
influenced the man who with his sword opened his imposthume, which the
physicians had in vain attempted to cure. For it has often happened that
people have served a man whom they intended to injure, and have injured
one whom they designed to serve; so that the effect of the gift is by no
means always a proof of the intention of the giver; neither does the
benefit which may accrue from it prove that it came from the hands of a
benefactor. For, in short, what debauchery, what avarice, what crime
among men is there which does not owe its birth to thought and
reflection, that is, to reason? For all opinion is reason: right reason,
if men’s thoughts are conformable to truth; wrong reason, if they are
not. The Gods only give us the mere faculty of reason, if we have any;
the use or abuse of it depends entirely upon ourselves; so that the
comparison is not just between the present of reason given us by the
Gods, and a patrimony left to a son by his father; for, after all, if
the injury of mankind had been the end proposed by the Gods, what could
they have given them more pernicious than reason? for what seed could
there be of injustice, intemperance, and cowardice, if reason were not
laid as the foundation of these vices?
XXIX. I mentioned just now Medea and Atreus, persons celebrated in
heroic poems, who had used this reason only for the contrivance and
practice of the most flagitious crimes; but even the trifling characters
which appear in comedies supply us with the like instances of this
reasoning faculty; for example, does not he, in the Eunuch, reason with
some subtlety?—
What, then, must I resolve upon?
She turn’d me out-of-doors; she sends for me back again;
Shall I go? no, not if she were to beg it of me.
Another, in the Twins, making no scruple of opposing a received maxim,
after the manner of the Academics, asserts that when a man is in love
and in want, it is pleasant
To have a father covetous, crabbed, and passionate,
Who has no love or affection for his children.
345This unaccountable opinion he strengthens thus:
You may defraud him of his profits, or forge letters in his name,
Or fright him by your servant into compliance;
And what you take from such an old hunks,
How much more pleasantly do you spend it!
On the contrary, he says that an easy, generous father is an
inconvenience to a son in love; for, says he,
I can’t tell how to abuse so good, so prudent a parent,
Who always foreruns my desires, and meets me purse in hand,
To support me in my pleasures: this easy goodness and generosity
Quite defeat all my frauds, tricks, and stratagems.
273
What are these frauds, tricks, and stratagems but the effects of reason?
O excellent gift of the Gods! Without this Phormio could not have said,
Find me out the old man: I have something hatching for him in my
head.
XXX. But let us pass from the stage to the bar. The prætor
274 takes
his seat. To judge whom? The man who set fire to our archives. How
secretly was that villany conducted! Q. Sosius, an illustrious Roman
knight, of the Picene field,
275 confessed the fact. Who else is to be
tried? He who forged the public registers—Alenus, an artful fellow, who
counterfeited the handwriting of the six officers.
276 Let us call to
mind other trials: that on the subject of the gold of Tolosa, or the
conspiracy of Jugurtha. Let us trace back the informations laid against
Tubulus for bribery in his judicial office; and, since that, the
proceedings of the tribune Peduceus concerning the
346incest of the
vestals. Let us reflect upon the trials which daily happen for
assassinations, poisonings, embezzlement of public money, frauds in
wills, against which we have a new law; then that action against the
advisers or assisters of any theft; the many laws concerning frauds in
guardianship, breaches of trust in partnerships and commissions in
trade, and other violations of faith in buying, selling, borrowing, or
lending; the public decree on a private affair by the Lætorian Law;
277
and, lastly, that scourge of all dishonesty, the law against fraud,
proposed by our friend Aquillius; that sort of fraud, he says, by which
one thing is pretended and another done. Can we, then, think that this
plentiful fountain of evil sprung from the immortal Gods? If they have
given reason to man, they have likewise given him subtlety, for subtlety
is only a deceitful manner of applying reason to do mischief. To them
likewise we must owe deceit, and every other crime, which, without the
help of reason, would neither have been thought of nor committed. As the
old woman wished
That to the fir which on Mount Pelion grew
The axe had ne’er been laid,
278
so we should wish that the Gods had never bestowed this ability on man,
the abuse of which is so general that the small number of those who make
a good use of it are often oppressed by those who make a bad use of it;
so that it seems to be given rather to help vice than to promote virtue
among us.
XXXI. This, you insist on it, is the fault of man, and not of the Gods.
But should we not laugh at a physician or pilot, though they are weak
mortals, if they were to lay the blame of their ill success on the
violence of the disease or the fury of the tempest? Had there not been
danger, 347we should say, who would have applied to you? This reasoning
has still greater force against the Deity. The fault, you say, is in
man, if he commits crimes. But why was not man endued with a reason
incapable of producing any crimes? How could the Gods err? When we leave
our effects to our children, it is in hopes that they may be well
bestowed; in which we may be deceived, but how can the Deity be
deceived? As PhЕ“bus when he trusted his chariot to his son PhaГ«thon, or
as Neptune when he indulged his son Theseus in granting him three
wishes, the consequence of which was the destruction of Hippolitus?
These are poetical fictions; but truth, and not fables, ought to proceed
from philosophers. Yet if those poetical Deities had foreseen that
their indulgence would have proved fatal to their sons, they must have
been thought blamable for it.
Aristo of Chios used often to say that the philosophers do hurt to such
of their disciples as take their good doctrine in a wrong sense; thus
the lectures of Aristippus might produce debauchees, and those of Zeno
pedants. If this be true, it were better that philosophers should be
silent than that their disciples should be corrupted by a
misapprehension of their master’s meaning; so if reason, which was
bestowed on mankind by the Gods with a good design, tends only to make
men more subtle and fraudulent, it had been better for them never to
have received it. There could be no excuse for a physician who
prescribes wine to a patient, knowing that he will drink it and
immediately expire. Your Providence is no less blamable in giving reason
to man, who, it foresaw, would make a bad use of it. Will you say that
it did not foresee it? Nothing could please me more than such an
acknowledgment. But you dare not. I know what a sublime idea you
entertain of her.
XXXII. But to conclude. If folly, by the unanimous consent of
philosophers, is allowed to be the greatest of all evils, and if no one
ever attained to true wisdom, we, whom they say the immortal Gods take
care of, are consequently in a state of the utmost misery. For that
nobody is well, or that nobody can be well, is in effect the same thing;
and, in my opinion, that no man is truly wise, or that no 348man can be
truly wise, is likewise the same thing. But I will insist no further on
so self-evident a point. Telamon in one verse decides the question. If,
says he, there is a Divine Providence,
Good men would be happy, bad men miserable.
But it is not so. If the Gods had regarded mankind, they should have
made them all virtuous; but if they did not regard the welfare of all
mankind, at least they ought to have provided for the happiness of the
virtuous. Why, therefore, was the Carthaginian in Spain suffered to
destroy those best and bravest men, the two Scipios? Why did
Maximus279 lose his son, the consul? Why did Hannibal kill Marcellus?
Why did Cannæ deprive us of Paulus? Why was the body of Regulus
delivered up to the cruelty of the Carthaginians? Why was not Africanus
protected from violence in his own house? To these, and many more
ancient instances, let us add some of later date. Why is Rutilius, my
uncle, a man of the greatest virtue and learning, now in banishment? Why
was my own friend and companion Drusus assassinated in his own house?
Why was Scævola, the high-priest, that pattern of moderation and
prudence, massacred before the statue of Vesta? Why, before that, were
so many illustrious citizens put to death by Cinna? Why had Marius, the
most perfidious of men, the power to cause the death of Catulus, a man
of the greatest dignity? But there would be no end of enumerating
examples of good men made miserable and wicked men prosperous. Why did
that Marius live to an old age, and die so happily at his own house in
his seventh consulship? Why was that inhuman wretch Cinna permitted to
enjoy so long a reign?
XXXIII. He, indeed, met with deserved punishment at last. But would it
not have been better that these inhumanities had been prevented than
that the author of them should be punished afterward? Varius, a most
impious wretch, was tortured and put to death. If this was his
punishment for the murdering Drusus by the sword, and Metellus by
poison, would it not have been better to have preserved their lives than
to have their deaths avenged on 349Varius? Dionysius was thirty-eight
years a tyrant over the most opulent and flourishing city; and, before
him, how many years did Pisistratus tyrannize in the very flower of
Greece! Phalaris and Apollodorus met with the fate they deserved, but
not till after they had tortured and put to death multitudes. Many
robbers have been executed; but the number of those who have suffered
for their crimes is short of those whom they have robbed and murdered.
Anaxarchus,280 a scholar of Democritus, was cut to pieces by command
of the tyrant of Cyprus; and Zeno of Elea281 ended his life in
tortures. What shall I say of Socrates,282 whose death, as often as I
read of it in Plato, draws fresh tears from my eyes? If, therefore, the
Gods really see everything that happens to men, you must acknowledge
they make no distinction between the good and the bad.
XXXIV. Diogenes the Cynic used to say of Harpalus, one of the most
fortunate villains of his time, that the constant prosperity of such a
man was a kind of witness against the Gods. Dionysius, of whom we have
before spoken, after he had pillaged the temple of Proserpine at Locris,
set sail for Syracuse, and, having a fair wind during his voyage, said,
with a smile, “See, my friends, what favorable winds the immortal Gods
bestow upon church-robbers.” Encouraged by this prosperous event, he
proceeded in his impiety. When he landed at Peloponnesus, he went into
the temple of Jupiter Olympius, and disrobed his statue of a golden
mantle of great weight, an ornament which the tyrant Gelo283 had given
out of the spoils of the Carthaginians, and at the same time, in a
jesting manner, he said “that a golden mantle was too heavy in summer
and too cold in winter;” and then, throwing a woollen cloak over the
statue, added, “This will serve for all seasons.” At another time, he
ordered the golden beard of Г†sculapius of Epidaurus to be taken away,
saying that “it 350was absurd for the son to have a beard, when his father
had none.” He likewise robbed the temples of the silver tables, which,
according to the ancient custom of Greece, bore this inscription, “To
the good Gods,” saying “he was willing to make use of their goodness;”
and, without the least scruple, took away the little golden emblems of
victory, the cups and coronets, which were in the stretched-out hands of
the statues, saying “he did not take, but receive them; for it would be
folly not to accept good things from the Gods, to whom we are constantly
praying for favors, when they stretch out their hands towards us.” And,
last of all, all the things which he had thus pillaged from the temples
were, by his order, brought to the market-place and sold by the common
crier; and, after he had received the money for them, he commanded every
purchaser to restore what he had bought, within a limited time, to the
temples from whence they came. Thus to his impiety towards the Gods he
added injustice to man.
XXXV. Yet neither did Olympian Jove strike him with his thunder, nor did
Г†sculapius cause him to die by tedious diseases and a lingering death.
He died in his bed, had funeral honors284 paid to him, and left his
power, which he had wickedly obtained, as a just and lawful inheritance
to his son.
It is not without concern that I maintain a doctrine which seems to
authorize evil, and which might probably give a sanction to it, if
conscience, without any divine assistance, did not point out, in the
clearest manner, the difference between virtue and vice. Without
conscience man is contemptible. For as no family or state can be
supposed to be formed with any reason or discipline if there are no
rewards for good actions nor punishment for crimes, so we cannot believe
that a Divine Providence regulates the world if there is no distinction
between the honest and the wicked.
351But the Gods, you say, neglect trifling things: the little fields or
vineyards of particular men are not worthy their attention; and if
blasts or hail destroy their product, Jupiter does not regard it, nor do
kings extend their care to the lower offices of government. This
argument might have some weight if, in bringing Rutilius as an instance,
I had only complained of the loss of his farm at Formiæ; but I spoke of
a personal misfortune, his banishment.285
XXXVI. All men agree that external benefits, such as vineyards, corn,
olives, plenty of fruit and grain, and, in short, every convenience and
property of life, are derived from the Gods; and, indeed, with reason,
since by our virtue we claim applause, and in virtue we justly glory,
which we could have no right to do if it was the gift of the Gods, and
not a personal merit. When we are honored with new dignities, or blessed
with increase of riches; when we are favored by fortune beyond our
expectation, or luckily delivered from any approaching evil, we return
thanks for it to the Gods, and assume no praise to ourselves. But who
ever thanked the Gods that he was a good man? We thank them, indeed, for
riches, health, and honor. For these we invoke the all-good and
all-powerful Jupiter; but not for wisdom, temperance, and justice. No
one ever offered a tenth of his estate to Hercules to be made wise. It
is reported, indeed, of Pythagoras that he sacrificed an ox to the Muses
upon having made some new discovery in geometry;286 but, for my part,
I cannot believe it, because he refused to sacrifice even to Apollo at
Delos, lest he should defile the altar with blood. But to return. It is
universally agreed that good fortune we must ask of the Gods, but wisdom
must arise from ourselves; and though temples have been consecrated to
the Mind, to Virtue, and to Faith, yet that does not contradict their
being 352inherent in us. In regard to hope, safety, assistance, and
victory, we must rely upon the Gods for them; from whence it follows, as
Diogenes said, that the prosperity of the wicked destroys the idea of a
Divine Providence.
XXXVII. But good men have sometimes success. They have so; but we
cannot, with any show of reason, attribute that success to the Gods.
Diagoras, who is called the atheist, being at Samothrace, one of his
friends showed him several pictures287 of people who had endured very
dangerous storms; “See,” says he, “you who deny a providence, how many
have been saved by their prayers to the Gods.” “Ay,” says Diagoras, “I
see those who were saved, but where are those painted who were
shipwrecked?” At another time, he himself was in a storm, when the
sailors, being greatly alarmed, told him they justly deserved that
misfortune for admitting him into their ship; when he, pointing to
others under the like distress, asked them “if they believed Diagoras
was also aboard those ships?” In short, with regard to good or bad
fortune, it matters not what you are, or how you have lived. The Gods,
like kings, regard not everything. What similitude is there between
them? If kings neglect anything, want of knowledge may be pleaded in
their defence; but ignorance cannot be brought as an excuse for the
Gods.
XXXVIII. Your manner of justifying them is somewhat extraordinary, when
you say that if a wicked man dies without suffering for his crimes, the
Gods inflict a punishment on his children, his children’s children, and
all his posterity. O wonderful equity of the Gods! What city would
endure the maker of a law which should condemn a son or a grandson for a
crime committed by the father or the grandfather?
Shall Tantalus’ unhappy offspring know
No end, no close, of this long scene of woe?
When will the dire reward of guilt be o’er,
And Myrtilus demand revenge no more?
288
Whether the poets have corrupted the Stoics, or the Stoics given
authority to the poets, I cannot easily determine. Both alike are to be
condemned. If those persons
353whose names have been branded in the
satires of Hipponax or Archilochus
289 were driven to despair, it did
not proceed from the Gods, but had its origin in their own minds. When
we see Г†gistus and Paris lost in the heat of an impure passion, why are
we to attribute it to a Deity, when the crime, as it were, speaks for
itself? I believe that those who recover from illness are more indebted
to the care of Hippocrates than to the power of Г†sculapius; that Sparta
received her laws from Lycurgus
290 rather than from Apollo; that those
eyes of the maritime coast, Corinth and Carthage, were plucked out, the
one by Critolaus, the other by Hasdrubal, without the assistance of any
divine anger, since you yourselves confess that a Deity cannot possibly
be angry on any provocation.
XXXIX. But could not the Deity have assisted and preserved those eminent
cities? Undoubtedly he could; for, according to your doctrine, his power
is infinite, and without the least labor; and as nothing but the will is
necessary to the motion of our bodies, so the divine will of the Gods,
with the like ease, can create, move, and change all things. This you
hold, not from a mere phantom of superstition, but on natural and
settled principles of reason; for matter, you say, of which all things
are composed and consist, is susceptible of all forms and changes, and
there is nothing which cannot be, or cease to be, in an instant; and
that Divine Providence has the command and disposal of this universal
matter, and consequently can, in any part of the universe, do whatever
she pleases: from whence I conclude that this Providence either knows
not the extent of her power, or neglects human affairs, or cannot judge
what is best for us. Providence, you say, does not extend her care to
particular men; there
354is no wonder in that, since she does not extend
it to cities, or even to nations, or people. If, therefore, she neglects
whole nations, is it not very probable that she neglects all mankind?
But how can you assert that the Gods do not enter into all the little
circumstances of life, and yet hold that they distribute dreams among
men? Since you believe in dreams, it is your part to solve this
difficulty. Besides, you say we ought to call upon the Gods. Those who
call upon the Gods are individuals. Divine Providence, therefore,
regards individuals, which consequently proves that they are more at
leisure than you imagine. Let us suppose the Divine Providence to be
greatly busied; that it causes the revolutions of the heavens, supports
the earth, and rules the seas; why does it suffer so many Gods to be
unemployed? Why is not the superintendence of human affairs given to
some of those idle Deities which you say are innumerable?
This is the purport of what I had to say concerning “the Nature of the
Gods;” not with a design to destroy their existence, but merely to show
what an obscure point it is, and with what difficulties an explanation
of it is attended.
XL. Balbus, observing that Cotta had finished his discourse—You have
been very severe, says he, against a Divine Providence, a doctrine
established by the Stoics with piety and wisdom; but, as it grows too
late, I shall defer my answer to another day. Our argument is of the
greatest importance; it concerns our altars,
291 our hearths, our
temples, nay, even the walls of our city, which you priests hold sacred;
you, who by religion defend Rome better than she is defended by her
ramparts. This is a cause which, while I have life, I think I cannot
abandon without impiety.
There is nothing, replied Cotta, which I desire more than to be
confuted. I have not pretended to decide this point, but to give you my
private sentiments upon it; and am very sensible of your great
superiority in argument.
355No doubt of it, says Velleius; we have much to
fear from one who believes that our dreams are sent from Jupiter, which,
though they are of little weight, are yet of more importance than the
discourse of the Stoics concerning the nature of the Gods. The
conversation ended here, and we parted. Velleius judged that the
arguments of Cotta were truest; but those of Balbus seemed to me to have
the greater probability.
292
357ON THE COMMONWEALTH.
PREFACE BY THE EDITOR.
This work was one of Cicero’s earlier treatises, though one of those
which was most admired by his contemporaries, and one of which he
himself was most proud. It was composed 54
b.c. It was originally in two
books: then it was altered and enlarged into nine, and finally reduced
to six. With the exception of the dream of Scipio, in the last book, the
whole treatise was lost till the year 1822, when the librarian of the
Vatican discovered a portion of them among the palimpsests in that
library. What he discovered is translated here; but it is in a most
imperfect and mutilated state.
The form selected was that of a dialogue, in imitation of those of
Plato; and the several conferences were supposed to have taken place
during the Latin holidays, 129
b.c., in the consulship of Caius
Sempronius, Tuditanus, and Marcus Aquilius. The speakers are Scipio
Africanus the younger, in whose garden the scene is laid; Caius Lælius;
Lucius Furius Philus; Marcus Manilius; Spurius Mummius, the brother of
the taker of Corinth, a Stoic; Quintus Г†lius Tubero, a nephew of
Africanus; Publius Rutilius Rufus; Quintus Mucius Scævola, the tutor of
Cicero; and Caius Fannius, who was absent, however, on the second day of
the conference.
In the first book, the first thirty-three pages are wanting, and there
are chasms amounting to thirty-eight pages more. In this book Scipio
asserts the superiority of an active over a speculative career; and
after analyzing and comparing the monarchical, aristocratic, and
democratic forms of government, gives a preference to the first;
although
358his idea of a perfect constitution would be one compounded of
three kinds in due proportion.
There are a few chasms in the earlier part of the second book, and the
latter part of it is wholly lost. In it Scipio was led on to give an
account of the rise and progress of the Roman Constitution, from which
he passed on to the examination of the great moral obligations which are
the foundations of all political union.
Of the remaining books we have only a few disjointed fragments, with the
exception, as has been before mentioned, of the dream of Scipio in the
sixth.
359INTRODUCTION TO THE FIRST BOOK,
BY THE ORIGINAL TRANSLATOR.
Cicero introduces his subject by showing that men were not born for the
mere abstract study of philosophy, but that the study of philosophic
truth should always be made as practical as possible, and applicable to
the great interests of philanthropy and patriotism. Cicero endeavors to
show the benefit of mingling the contemplative or philosophic with the
political and active life, according to that maxim of Plato—“Happy is
the nation whose philosophers are kings, and whose kings are
philosophers.”
This kind of introduction was the more necessary because many of the
ancient philosophers, too warmly attached to transcendental metaphysics
and sequestered speculations, had affirmed that true philosophers ought
not to interest themselves in the management of public affairs. Thus, as
M. Villemain observes, it was a maxim of the Epicureans, “Sapiens ne
accedat ad rempublicam” (Let no wise man meddle in politics). The
Pythagoreans had enforced the same principle with more gravity.
Aristotle examines the question on both sides, and concludes in favor of
active life. Among Aristotle’s disciples, a writer, singularly elegant
and pure, had maintained the pre-eminence of the contemplative life over
the political or active one, in a work which Cicero cites with
admiration, and to which he seems to have applied for relief whenever he
felt harassed and discouraged in public business. But here this great
man was interested by the subject he discusses, and by the whole course
of his experience and conduct, to refute the dogmas of that
pusillanimous sophistry and selfish indulgence by bringing forward the
most glorious examples and achievements of patriotism. In this strain he
had doubtless commenced his exordium, and in this strain we find him
continuing it at the point in which the palimpsest becomes legible. He
then proceeds to introduce his illustrious interlocutors, and leads them
at first to discourse on the astronomical laws that regulate the
revolutions of our planet. From this, by a very graceful and beautiful
transition, he passes on to the consideration of the best forms of
political constitutions that had prevailed in different nations, and
those modes of government which had produced the greatest benefits in
the commonwealths of antiquity.
This first book is, in fact, a splendid epitome of the political science
of the age of Cicero, and probably the most eloquent plea in favor of
mixed monarchy to be found in all literature.
360BOOK I.
I. [
Without the virtue of patriotism], neither Caius Duilius, nor Aulus
Atilius,
293 nor Lucius Metellus, could have delivered Rome by their
courage from the terror of Carthage; nor could the two Scipios, when the
fire of the second Punic War was kindled, have quenched it in their
blood; nor, when it revived in greater force, could either Quintus
Maximus
294 have enervated it, or Marcus Marcellus have crushed it;
nor, when it was repulsed from the gates of our own city, would Scipio
have confined it within the walls of our enemies.
But Cato, at first a new and unknown man, whom all we who aspire to the
same honors consider as a pattern to lead us on to industry and virtue,
was undoubtedly at liberty to enjoy his repose at Tusculum, a most
salubrious and convenient retreat. But he, mad as some people think him,
though no necessity compelled him, preferred being tossed about amidst
the tempestuous waves of politics, even till extreme old age, to living
with all imaginable luxury in that tranquillity and relaxation. I omit
innumerable men who have separately devoted themselves to the protection
of our Commonwealth; and those whose lives are within the memory of the
present generation I will not mention, lest any one should complain that
I had invidiously forgotten himself or some one of his family. This only
I insist on—that so great is the necessity of this virtue which nature
has implanted in man, and so great is the desire to defend the common
safety of our country, that its energy has continually overcome all the
blandishments of pleasure and repose.
II. Nor is it sufficient to possess this virtue as if it were some kind
of art, unless we put it in practice. An art, indeed, though not
exercised, may still be retained in knowledge; but virtue consists
wholly in its proper use
361and action. Now, the noblest use of virtue is
the government of the Commonwealth, and the carrying-out in real action,
not in words only, of all those identical theories which those
philosophers discuss at every corner. For nothing is spoken by
philosophers, so far as they speak correctly and honorably, which has
not been discovered and confirmed by those persons who have been the
founders of the laws of states. For whence comes piety, or from whom has
religion been derived? Whence comes law, either that of nations, or that
which is called the civil law? Whence comes justice, faith, equity?
Whence modesty, continence, the horror of baseness, the desire of praise
and renown? Whence fortitude in labors and perils? Doubtless, from those
who have instilled some of these moral principles into men by education,
and confirmed others by custom, and sanctioned others by laws.
Moreover, it is reported of Xenocrates, one of the sublimest
philosophers, that when some one asked him what his disciples learned,
he replied, “To do that of their own accord which they might be
compelled to do by law.” That citizen, therefore, who obliges all men to
those virtuous actions, by the authority of laws and penalties, to which
the philosophers can scarcely persuade a few by the force of their
eloquence, is certainly to be preferred to the sagest of the doctors who
spend their lives in such discussions. For which of their exquisite
orations is so admirable as to be entitled to be preferred to a
well-constituted government, public justice, and good customs?
Certainly, just as I think that magnificent and imperious cities (as
Ennius says) are superior to castles and villages, so I imagine that
those who regulate such cities by their counsel and authority are far
preferable, with respect to real wisdom, to men who are unacquainted
with any kind of political knowledge. And since we are strongly prompted
to augment the prosperity of the human race, and since we do endeavor by
our counsels and exertions to render the life of man safer and
wealthier, and since we are incited to this blessing by the spur of
nature herself, let us hold on that course which has always been pursued
by all the best men, and not listen for a moment to the signals of those
who sound a retreat so loudly that they
362sometimes call back even those
who have made considerable progress.
III. These reasons, so certain and so evident, are opposed by those who,
on the other side, argue that the labors which must necessarily be
sustained in maintaining the Commonwealth form but a slight impediment
to the vigilant and industrious, and are only a contemptible obstacle in
such important affairs, and even in common studies, offices, and
employments. They add the peril of life, that base fear of death, which
has ever been opposed by brave men, to whom it appears far more
miserable to die by the decay of nature and old age than to be allowed
an opportunity of gallantly sacrificing that life for their country
which must otherwise be yielded up to nature.
On this point, however, our antagonists esteem themselves copious and
eloquent when they collect all the calamities of heroic men, and the
injuries inflicted on them by their ungrateful countrymen. For on this
subject they bring forward those notable examples among the Greeks; and
tell us that Miltiades, the vanquisher and conqueror of the Persians,
before even those wounds were healed which he had received in that most
glorious victory, wasted away in the chains of his fellow-citizens that
life which had been preserved from the weapons of the enemy. They cite
Themistocles, expelled and proscribed by the country which he had
rescued, and forced to flee, not to the Grecian ports which he had
preserved, but to the bosom of the barbarous power which he had
defeated. There is, indeed, no deficiency of examples to illustrate the
levity and cruelty of the Athenians to their noblest citizens—examples
which, originating and multiplying among them, are said at different
times to have abounded in our own most august empire. For we are told:
of the exile of Camillus, the disgrace of Ahala, the unpopularity of
Nasica, the expulsion of Lænas,
295 the condemnation of
363Opimius, the
flight of Metellus, the cruel destruction of Caius Marius, the massacre
of our chieftains, and the many atrocious crimes which followed. My own
history is by no means free from such calamities; and I imagine that
when they recollect that by my counsel and perils they were preserved in
life and liberty, they are led by that consideration to bewail my
misfortunes more deeply and affectionately. But I cannot tell why those
who sail over the seas for the sake of knowledge and experience [should
wonder at seeing still greater hazards braved in the service of the
Commonwealth].
IV. [Since], on my quitting the consulship, I swore in the assembly of
the Roman people, who re-echoed my words, that I had saved the
Commonwealth, I console myself with this remembrance for all my cares,
troubles, and injuries. Although my misfortune had more of honor than
misfortune, and more of glory than disaster; and I derive greater
pleasure from the regrets of good men than sorrow from the exultation of
the worthless. But even if it had happened otherwise, how could I have
complained, as nothing befell me which was either unforeseen, or more
painful than I expected, as a return for my illustrious actions? For I
was one who, though it was in my power to reap more profit from leisure
than most men, on account of the diversified sweetness of my studies, in
which I had lived from boyhood—or, if any public calamity had happened,
to have borne no more than an equal share with the rest of my countrymen
in the misfortune—I nevertheless did not hesitate to oppose myself to
the most formidable tempests and torrents of sedition, for the sake of
saving my countrymen, and at my own proper danger to secure the common
safety of all the rest. For our country did not beget and educate us
with the expectation of receiving no support, as I may call it, from us;
nor for the purpose of consulting nothing but our convenience, to supply
us with a secure refuge for idleness and a tranquil spot for rest; but
rather with a view of turning to her own advantage the nobler portion of
our genius, heart, and counsel; giving us back for our private service
only what she can spare from the public interests.
V. Those apologies, therefore, in which men take refuge
364as an excuse
for their devoting themselves with more plausibility to mere inactivity
do certainly not deserve to be listened to; when, for instance, they
tell us that those who meddle with public affairs are generally
good-for-nothing men, with whom it is discreditable to be compared, and
miserable and dangerous to contend, especially when the multitude is in
an excited state. On which account it is not the part of a wise man to
take the reins, since he cannot restrain the insane and unregulated
movements of the common people. Nor is it becoming to a man of liberal
birth, say they, thus to contend with such vile and unrefined
antagonists, or to subject one’s self to the lashings of contumely, or
to put one’s self in the way of injuries which ought not to be borne by
a wise man. As if to a virtuous, brave, and magnanimous man there could
be a juster reason for seeking the government than this—to avoid being
subjected to worthless men, and to prevent the Commonwealth from being
torn to pieces by them; when, even if they were then desirous to save
her, they would not have the power.
VI. But this restriction who can approve, which would interdict the wise
man from taking any share in the government beyond such as the occasion
and necessity may compel him to? As if any greater necessity could
possibly happen to any man than happened to me. In which, how could I
have acted if I had not been consul at the time? and how could I have
been a consul unless I had maintained that course of life from my
childhood which raised me from the order of knights, in which I was
born, to the very highest station? You cannot produce
extempore, and
just when you please, the power of assisting a commonwealth, although it
may be severely pressed by dangers, unless you have attained the
position which enables you legally to do so. And what most surprises me
in the discourses of learned men, is to hear those persons who confess
themselves incapable of steering the vessel of the State in smooth seas
(which, indeed, they never learned, and never cared to know) profess
themselves ready to assume the helm amidst the fiercest tempests. For
those men are accustomed to say openly, and indeed to boast greatly,
that they have never learned, and have never taken
365the least pains to
explain, the principles of either establishing or maintaining a
commonwealth; and they look on this practical science as one which
belongs not to men of learning and wisdom, but to those who have made it
their especial study. How, then, can it be reasonable for such men to
promise their assistance to the State, when they shall be compelled to
it by necessity, while they are ignorant how to govern the republic when
no necessity presses upon it, which is a much more easy task? Indeed,
though it were true that the wise man loves not to thrust himself of his
own accord into the administration of public affairs, but that if
circumstances oblige him to it, then he does not refuse the office, yet
I think that this science of civil legislation should in no wise be
neglected by the philosopher, because all resources ought to be ready to
his hand, which he knows not how soon he may be called on to use.
VII. I have spoken thus at large for this reason, because in this work I
have proposed to myself and undertaken a discussion on the government of
a state; and in order to render it useful, I was bound, in the first
place, to do away with this pusillanimous hesitation to mingle in public
affairs. If there be any, therefore, who are too much influenced by the
authority of the philosophers, let them consider the subject for a
moment, and be guided by the opinions of those men whose authority and
credit are greatest among learned men; whom I look upon, though some of
them have not personally governed any state, as men who have
nevertheless discharged a kind of office in the republic, inasmuch as
they have made many investigations into, and left many writings
concerning, state affairs. As to those whom the Greeks entitle the Seven
Wise Men, I find that they almost all lived in the middle of public
business. Nor, indeed, is there anything in which human virtue can more
closely resemble the divine powers than in establishing new states, or
in preserving those already established.
VIII. And concerning these affairs, since it has been our good fortune
to achieve something worthy of memorial in the government of our
country, and also to have acquired some facility of explaining the
powers and resources of politics, we can treat of this subject with the
weight of
366personal experience and the habit of instruction and
illustration. Whereas before us many have been skilful in theory, though
no exploits of theirs are recorded; and many others have been men of
consideration in action, but unfamiliar with the arts of exposition.
Nor, indeed, is it at all our intention to establish a new and
self-invented system of government; but our purpose is rather to recall
to memory a discussion of the most illustrious men of their age in our
Commonwealth, which you and I, in our youth, when at Smyrna, heard
mentioned by Publius Rutilius Rufus, who reported to us a conference of
many days in which, in my opinion, there was nothing omitted that could
throw light on political affairs.
IX. For when, in the year of the consulship of Tuditanus and Aquilius,
Scipio Africanus, the son of Paulus Г†milius, formed the project of
spending the Latin holidays at his country-seat, where his most intimate
friends had promised him frequent visits during this season of
relaxation, on the first morning of the festival, his nephew, Quintus
Tubero, made his appearance; and when Scipio had greeted him heartily
and embraced him—How is it, my dear Tubero, said he, that I see you so
early? For these holidays must afford you a capital opportunity of
pursuing your favorite studies. Ah! replied Tubero, I can study my books
at any time, for they are always disengaged; but it is a great
privilege, my Scipio, to find you at leisure, especially in this
restless period of public affairs. You certainly have found me so, said
Scipio, but, to speak truth, I am rather relaxing from business than
from study. Nay, said Tubero, you must try to relax from your studies
too, for here are several of us, as we have appointed, all ready, if it
suits your convenience, to aid you in getting through this leisure time
of yours. I am very willing to consent, answered Scipio, and we may be
able to compare notes respecting the several topics that interest us.
X. Be it so, said Tubero; and since you invite me to discussion, and
present the opportunity, let us first examine, before any one else
arrives, what can be the nature of the parhelion, or double sun, which
was mentioned in the senate. Those that affirm they witnessed this
prodigy
367are neither few nor unworthy of credit, so that there is more
reason for investigation than incredulity.
296
Ah! said Scipio, I wish we had our friend Panætius with us, who is fond
of investigating all things of this kind, but especially all celestial
phenomena. As for my opinion, Tubero, for I always tell you just what I
think, I hardly agree in these subjects with that friend of mine, since,
respecting things of which we can scarcely form a conjecture as to their
character, he is as positive as if he had seen them with his own eyes
and felt them with his own hands. And I cannot but the more admire the
wisdom of Socrates, who discarded all anxiety respecting things of this
kind, and affirmed that these inquiries concerning the secrets of nature
were either above the efforts of human reason, or were absolutely of no
consequence at all to human life.
But, then, my Africanus, replied Tubero, of what credit is the tradition
which states that Socrates rejected all these physical investigations,
and confined his whole attention to men and manners? For, with respect
to him what better authority can we cite than Plato? in many passages of
whose works Socrates speaks in such a manner that even when he is
discussing morals, and virtues, and even public affairs and politics, he
endeavors to interweave, after the fashion of Pythagoras, the doctrines
of arithmetic, geometry, and harmonic proportions with them.
That is true, replied Scipio; but you are aware, I believe, that Plato,
after the death of Socrates, was induced to visit Egypt by his love of
science, and that after that he proceeded to Italy and Sicily, from his
desire of understanding the Pythagorean dogmas; that he conversed much
with Archytas of Tarentum and Timæus of Locris;
368that he collected the
works of Philolaus; and that, finding in these places the renown of
Pythagoras flourishing, he addicted himself exceedingly to the disciples
of Pythagoras, and their studies; therefore, as he loved Socrates with
his whole heart, and wished to attribute all great discoveries to him,
he interwove the Socratic elegance and subtlety of eloquence with
somewhat of the obscurity of Pythagoras, and with that notorious gravity
of his diversified arts.
XI. When Scipio had spoken thus, he suddenly saw Lucius Furius
approaching, and saluting him, and embracing him most affectionately, he
gave him a seat on his own couch. And as soon as Publius Rutilius, the
worthy reporter of the conference to us, had arrived, when we had
saluted him, he placed him by the side of Tubero. Then said Furius, What
is it that you are about? Has our entrance at all interrupted any
conversation of yours? By no means, said Scipio, for you yourself too
are in the habit of investigating carefully the subject which Tubero was
a little before proposing to examine; and our friend Rutilius, even
under the walls of Numantia, was in the habit at times of conversing
with me on questions of the same kind. What, then, was the subject of
your discussion? said Philus. We were talking, said Scipio, of the
double suns that recently appeared, and I wish, Philus, to hear what you
think of them.
XII. Just as he was speaking, a boy announced that Lælius was coming to
call on him, and that he had already left his house. Then Scipio,
putting on his sandals and robes, immediately went forth from his
chamber, and when he had walked a little time in the portico, he met
Lælius, and welcomed him and those that accompanied him, namely, Spurius
Mummius, to whom he was greatly attached, and C. Fannius and Quintus
Scævola, sons-in-law of Lælius, two very intelligent young men, and now
of the quæstorian age.
297
When he had saluted them all, he returned through the portico, placing
Lælius in the middle; for there was in their friendship a sort of law of
reciprocal courtesy, so
369that in the camp Lælius paid Scipio almost
divine honors, on account of his eminent renown in war and in private
life; in his turn Scipio reverenced Lælius, even as a father, because he
was older than himself.
Then after they had exchanged a few words, as they walked up and down,
Scipio, to whom their visit was extremely welcome and agreeable, wished
to assemble them in a sunny corner of the gardens, because it was still
winter; and when they had agreed to this, there came in another friend,
a learned man, much beloved and esteemed by all of them, M. Manilius,
who, after having been most warmly welcomed by Scipio and the rest,
seated himself next to Lælius.
XIII. Then Philus, commencing the conversation, said: It does not appear
to me that the presence of our new guests need alter the subject of our
discussion, but only that it should induce us to treat it more
philosophically, and in a manner more worthy of our increased audience.
What do you allude to? said Lælius; or what was the discussion we broke
in upon? Scipio was asking me, replied Philus, what I thought of the
parhelion, or mock sun, whose recent apparition was so strongly
attested.
Lælius. Do you say then, my Philus, that we have sufficiently examined
those questions which concern our own houses and the Commonwealth, that
we begin to investigate the celestial mysteries?
And Philus replied: Do you think, then, that it does not concern our
houses to know what happens in that vast home which is not included in
walls of human fabrication, but which embraces the entire universe—a
home which the Gods share with us, as the common country of all
intelligent beings? Especially when, if we are ignorant of these things,
there are also many great practical truths which result from them, and
which bear directly on the welfare of our race, of which we must be also
ignorant. And here I can speak for myself, as well as for you, Lælius,
and all men who are ambitious of wisdom, that the knowledge and
consideration of the facts of nature are by themselves very delightful.
Lælius. I have no objection to the discussion, especially as it is
holiday-time with us. But cannot we have the
370pleasure of hearing you
resume it, or are we come too late?
Philus. We have not yet commenced the discussion, and since the
question remains entire and unbroken, I shall have the greatest
pleasure, my Lælius, in handing over the argument to you.
Lælius. No, I had much rather hear you, unless, indeed, Manilius
thinks himself able to compromise the suit between the two suns, that
they may possess heaven as joint sovereigns without intruding on each
other’s empire.
Then Manilius said: Are you going, Lælius, to ridicule a science in
which, in the first place, I myself excel; and, secondly, without which
no one can distinguish what is his own, and what is another’s? But to
return to the point. Let us now at present listen to Philus, who seems
to me to have started a greater question than any of those that have
engaged the attention of either Publius Mucius or myself.
XIV. Then Philus said: I am not about to bring you anything new, or
anything which has been thought over or discovered by me myself. But I
recollect that Caius Sulpicius Gallus, who was a man of profound
learning, as you are aware, when this same thing was reported to have
taken place in his time, while he was staying in the house of Marcus
Marcellus, who had been his colleague in the consulship, asked to see a
celestial globe which Marcellus’s grandfather had saved after the
capture of Syracuse from that magnificent and opulent city, without
bringing to his own home any other memorial out of so great a booty;
which I had often heard mentioned on account of the great fame of
Archimedes; but its appearance, however, did not seem to me particularly
striking. For that other is more elegant in form, and more generally
known, which was made by the same Archimedes, and deposited by the same
Marcellus in the Temple of Virtue at Rome. But as soon as Gallus had
begun to explain, in a most scientific manner, the principle of this
machine, I felt that the Sicilian geometrician must have possessed a
genius superior to anything we usually conceive to belong to our nature.
For Gallus assured us that that other solid and compact globe was a very
ancient invention, and that the first
371model had been originally made by
Thales of Miletus. That afterward Eudoxus of Cnidus, a disciple of
Plato, had traced on its surface the stars that appear in the sky, and
that many years subsequently, borrowing from Eudoxus this beautiful
design and representation, Aratus had illustrated it in his verses, not
by any science of astronomy, but by the ornament of poetic description.
He added that the figure of the globe, which displayed the motions of
the sun and moon, and the five planets, or wandering stars, could not be
represented by the primitive solid globe; and that in this the invention
of Archimedes was admirable, because he had calculated how a single
revolution should maintain unequal and diversified progressions in
dissimilar motions. In fact, when Gallus moved this globe, we observed
that the moon succeeded the sun by as many turns of the wheel in the
machine as days in the heavens. From whence it resulted that the
progress of the sun was marked as in the heavens, and that the moon
touched the point where she is obscured by the earth’s shadow at the
instant the sun appears opposite.
298 *В *В *
XV. *В *В *
299 I had myself a great affection for this Gallus, and I
know that he was very much beloved and esteemed by my father Paulus. I
recollect that when I was very young, when my father, as consul,
commanded in Macedonia, and we were in the camp, our army was seized
with a pious terror, because suddenly, in a clear night, the bright and
full moon became eclipsed. And Gallus, who was then our lieutenant, the
year before that in which he was elected consul, hesitated not, next
morning, to state in the camp that it was no prodigy, and that the
phenomenon which had then appeared would always appear at certain
periods, when the sun was so placed that he could not affect the moon
with his light.
372But do you mean, said Tubero, that he dared to speak thus to men almost
entirely uneducated and ignorant?
Scipio. He did, and with great *В *В * for his opinion was no result of
insolent ostentation, nor was his language unbecoming the dignity of so
wise a man: indeed, he performed a very noble action in thus freeing his
countrymen from the terrors of an idle superstition.
XVI. And they relate that in a similar way, in the great war in which
the Athenians and Lacedæmonians contended with such violent resentment,
the famous Pericles, the first man of his country in credit, eloquence,
and political genius, observing the Athenians overwhelmed with an
excessive alarm during an eclipse of the sun which caused a sudden
darkness, told them, what he had learned in the school of Anaxagoras,
that these phenomena necessarily happened at precise and regular periods
when the body of the moon was interposed between the sun and the earth,
and that if they happened not before every new moon, still they could
not possibly happen except at the exact time of the new moon. And when
he had proved this truth by his reasonings, he freed the people from
their alarms; for at that period the doctrine was new and unfamiliar
that the sun was accustomed to be eclipsed by the interposition of the
moon, which fact they say that Thales of Miletus was the first to
discover. Afterward my friend Ennius appears to have been acquainted
with the same theory, who, writing about 350
300 years after the
foundation of Rome, says, “In the nones of June the sun was covered by
the moon and night.” The calculations in the astronomical art have
attained such perfection that from that day, thus described to us by
Ennius and recorded in the pontifical registers, the anterior eclipses
of the sun have been computed as far back as the nones of July in the
reign of Romulus, when that eclipse took place, in the obscurity of
which it was affirmed that Virtue bore Romulus to heaven, in spite of
the perishable nature which carried him off by the common fate of
humanity.
373XVII. Then said Tubero: Do not you think, Scipio, that this
astronomical science, which every day proves so useful, just now
appeared in a different light to you,
301 *В *В * which the rest may see.
Moreover, who can think anything in human affairs of brilliant
importance who has penetrated this starry empire of the gods? Or who can
think anything connected with mankind long who has learned to estimate
the nature of eternity? or glorious who is aware of the insignificance
of the size of the earth, even in its whole extent, and especially in
the portion which men inhabit? And when we consider that almost
imperceptible point which we ourselves occupy unknown to the majority of
nations, can we still hope that our name and reputation can be widely
circulated? And then our estates and edifices, our cattle, and the
enormous treasures of our gold and silver, can they be esteemed or
denominated as desirable goods by him who observes their perishable
profit, and their contemptible use, and their uncertain domination,
often falling into the possession of the very worst men? How happy,
then, ought we to esteem that man who alone has it in his power, not by
the law of the Romans, but by the privilege of philosophers, to enjoy
all things as his own; not by any civil bond, but by the common right of
nature, which denies that anything can really be possessed by any one
but him who understands its true nature and use; who reckons our
dictatorships and consulships rather in the rank of necessary offices
than desirable employments, and thinks they must be endured rather as
acquittances of our debt to our country than sought for the sake of
emolument or glory—the man, in short, who can apply to himself the
sentence which Cato tells us my ancestor Africanus loved to repeat,
“that he was never so busy as when he did nothing, and never less
solitary than when alone.”
For who can believe that Dionysius, when after every possible effort he
ravished from his fellow-citizens their liberty, had performed a nobler
work than Archimedes, when, without appearing to be doing anything, he
manufactured the globe which we have just been describing?
374Who does not
see that those men are in reality more solitary who, in the midst of a
crowd, find no one with whom they can converse congenially than those
who, without witnesses, hold communion with themselves, and enter into
the secret counsels of the sagest philosophers, while they delight
themselves in their writings and discoveries? And who would think any
one richer than the man who is in want of nothing which nature requires;
or more powerful than he who has attained all that she has need of; or
happier than he who is free from all mental perturbation; or more secure
in future than he who carries all his property in himself, which is thus
secured from shipwreck? And what power, what magistracy, what royalty,
can be preferred to a wisdom which, looking down on all terrestrial
objects as low and transitory things, incessantly directs its attention
to eternal and immutable verities, and which is persuaded that though
others are called men, none are really so but those who are refined by
the appropriate acts of humanity?
In this sense an expression of Plato or some other philosopher appears
to me exceedingly elegant, who, when a tempest had driven his ship on an
unknown country and a desolate shore, during the alarms with which their
ignorance of the region inspired his companions, observed, they say,
geometrical figures traced in the sand, on which he immediately told
them to be of good cheer, for he had observed the indications of Man. A
conjecture he deduced, not from the cultivation of the soil which he
beheld, but from the symbols of science. For this reason, Tubero,
learning and learned men, and these your favorite studies, have always
particularly pleased me.
XVIII. Then Lælius replied: I cannot venture, Scipio, to answer your
arguments, or to [maintain the discussion either against] you, Philus,
or Manilius.
302 *В *В *
We had a friend in Tubero’s father’s family, who in these respects may
serve him as a model.
Sextus so wise, and ever on his guard.
Wise and cautious indeed he was, as Ennius justly describes him—not
because he searched for what he could
375never find, but because he knew
how to answer those who prayed for deliverance from cares and
difficulties. It is he who, reasoning against the astronomical studies
of Gallus, used frequently to repeat these words of Achilles in the
Iphigenia
303:
They note the astrologic signs of heaven,
Whene’er the goats or scorpions of great Jove,
Or other monstrous names of brutal forms,
Rise in the zodiac; but not one regards
The sensible facts of earth, on which we tread,
While gazing on the starry prodigies.
He used, however, to say (and I have often listened to him with
pleasure) that for his part he thought that Zethus, in the piece of
Pacuvius, was too inimical to learning. He much preferred the
Neoptolemus of Ennius, who professes himself desirous of philosophizing
only in moderation; for that he did not think it right to be wholly
devoted to it. But though the studies of the Greeks have so many charms
for you, there are others, perhaps, nobler and more extensive, which we
may be better able to apply to the service of real life, and even to
political affairs. As to these abstract sciences, their utility, if they
possess any, lies principally in exciting and stimulating the abilities
of youth, so that they more easily acquire more important
accomplishments.
XIX. Then Tubero said: I do not mean to disagree with you, Lælius; but,
pray, what do you call more important studies?
Lælius. I will tell you frankly, though perhaps you will think lightly
of my opinion, since you appeared so eager in interrogating Scipio
respecting the celestial phenomena; but I happen to think that those
things which are every day before our eyes are more particularly
deserving of our attention. Why should the child of Paulus Г†milius, the
nephew of Г†milius, the descendant of such a noble family and so glorious
a republic, inquire how there can be two suns in heaven, and not ask how
there can be two senates in one Commonwealth, and, as it were, two
distinct peoples?
376For, as you see, the death of Tiberius Gracchus, and
the whole system of his tribuneship, has divided one people into two
parties. But the slanderers and the enemies of Scipio, encouraged by P.
Crassus and Appius Claudius, maintained, after the death of these two
chiefs, a division of nearly half the senate, under the influence of
Metellus and Mucius. Nor would they permit the man
304 who alone could
have been of service to help us out of our difficulties during the
movement of the Latins and their allies towards rebellion, violating all
our treaties in the presence of factious triumvirs, and creating every
day some fresh intrigue, to the disturbance of the worthier and
wealthier citizens. This is the reason, young men, if you will listen to
me, why you should regard this new sun with less alarm; for, whether it
does exist, or whether it does not exist, it is, as you see, quite
harmless to us. As to the manner of its existence, we can know little or
nothing; and even if we obtained the most perfect understanding of it,
this knowledge would make us but little wiser or happier. But that there
should exist a united people and a united senate is a thing which
actually may be brought about, and it will be a great evil if it is not;
and that it does not exist at present we are aware; and we see that if
it can be effected, our lives will be both better and happier.
XX. Then Mucius said: What, then, do you consider, my Lælius, should be
our best arguments in endeavoring to bring about the object of your
wishes?
Lælius. Those sciences and arts which teach us how we may be most
useful to the State; for I consider that the most glorious office of
wisdom, and the noblest proof and business of virtue. In order,
therefore, that we may consecrate these holidays as much as possible to
conversations which may be profitable to the Commonwealth, let us beg
Scipio to explain to us what in his estimation appears to be the best
form of government. Then let us pass on to other points, the knowledge
of which may lead us, as I hope, to sound political views, and unfold
the causes of the dangers which now threaten us.
XXI. When Philus, Manilius, and Mummius had all expressed
377their great
approbation of this idea
305 *В *В * I have ventured [to open our
discussion] in this way, not only because it is but just that on State
politics the chief man in the State should be the principal speaker, but
also because I recollect that you, Scipio, were formerly very much in
the habit of conversing with Panætius and Polybius, two Greeks,
exceedingly learned in political questions, and that you are master of
many arguments by which you prove that by far the best condition of
government is that which our ancestors have handed down to us. And as
you, therefore, are familiar with this subject, if you will explain to
us your views respecting the general principles of a state (I speak for
my friends as well as myself), we shall feel exceedingly obliged to you.
XXII. Then Scipio said: I must acknowledge that there is no subject of
meditation to which my mind naturally turns with more ardor and
intensity than this very one which Lælius has proposed to us. And,
indeed, as I see that in every profession, every artist who would
distinguish himself, thinks of, and aims at, and labors for no other
object but that of attaining perfection in his art, should not I, whose
main business, according to the example of my father and my ancestors,
is the advancement and right administration of government, be confessing
myself more indolent than any common mechanic if I were to bestow on
this noblest of sciences less attention and labor than they devote to
their insignificant trades? However, I am neither entirely satisfied
with the decisions which the greatest and wisest men of Greece have left
us; nor, on the other hand, do I venture to prefer my own opinions to
theirs. Therefore, I must request you not to consider me either entirely
ignorant of the Grecian literature, nor yet disposed, especially in
political questions, to yield it the pre-eminence over our own; but
rather to regard me as a true-born Roman, not illiberally instructed by
the care of my father, and inflamed with the desire of knowledge, even
from my boyhood, but still even more familiar with domestic precepts and
practices than the literature of books.
XXIII. On this Philus said: I have no doubt, my Scipio, that no one is
superior to you in natural genius,
378and that you are very far superior
to every one in the practical experience of national government and of
important business. We are also acquainted with the course which your
studies have at all times taken; and if, as you say, you have given so
much attention to this science and art of politics, we cannot be too
much obliged to Lælius for introducing the subject: for I trust that
what we shall hear from you will be far more useful and available than
all the writings put together which the Greeks have written for us.
Then Scipio replied: You are raising a very high expectation of my
discourse, such as is a most oppressive burden to a man who is required
to discuss grave subjects.
And Philus said: Although that may be a difficulty, my Scipio, still you
will be sure to conquer it, as you always do; nor is there any danger of
eloquence failing you, when you begin to speak on the affairs of a
commonwealth.
XXIV. Then Scipio proceeded: I will do what you wish, as far as I can;
and I shall enter into the discussion under favor of that rule which, I
think, should be adopted by all persons in disputations of this kind, if
they wish to avoid being misunderstood; namely, that when men have
agreed respecting the proper name of the matter under discussion, it
should be stated what that name exactly means, and what it legitimately
includes. And when that point is settled, then it is fit to enter on the
discussion; for it will never be possible to arrive at an understanding
of what the character of the subject of the discussion is, unless one
first understands exactly what it is. Since, then, our investigations
relate to a commonwealth, we must first examine what this name properly
signifies.
And when Lælius had intimated his approbation of this course, Scipio
continued:
I shall not adopt, said he, in so clear and simple a manner that system
of discussion which goes back to first principles; as learned men often
do in this sort of discussion, so as to go back to the first meeting of
male and female, and then to the first birth and formation of the first
family, and define over and over again what there is in words, and in
how many manners each thing is stated.
379For, as I am speaking to men of
prudence, who have acted with the greatest glory in the Commonwealth,
both in peace and war, I will take care not to allow the subject of the
discussion itself to be clearer than my explanation of it. Nor have I
undertaken this task with the design of examining all its minuter
points, like a school-master; nor will I promise you in the following
discourse not to omit any single particular.
Then Lælius said: For my part, I am impatient for exactly that kind of
disquisition which you promise us.
XXV. Well, then, said Africanus, a commonwealth is a constitution of the
entire people. But the people is not every association of men, however
congregated, but the association of the entire number, bound together by
the compact of justice, and the communication of utility. The first
cause of this association is not so much the weakness of man as a
certain spirit of congregation which naturally belongs to him. For the
human race is not a race of isolated individuals, wandering and
solitary; but it is so constituted that even in the affluence of all
things [and without any need of reciprocal assistance, it spontaneously
seeks society].
XXVI. [It is necessary to presuppose] these original seeds, as it were,
since we cannot discover any primary establishment of the other virtues,
or even of a commonwealth itself. These unions, then, formed by the
principle which I have mentioned, established their headquarters
originally in certain central positions, for the convenience of the
whole population; and having fortified them by natural and artificial
means, they called this collection of houses a city or town,
distinguished by temples and public squares. Every people, therefore,
which consists of such an association of the entire multitude as I have
described, every city which consists of an assemblage of the people, and
every commonwealth which embraces every member of these associations,
must be regulated by a certain authority, in order to be permanent.
This intelligent authority should always refer itself to that grand
first principle which established the Commonwealth. It must be deposited
in the hands of one supreme person, or intrusted to the administration
of certain delegated
380rulers, or undertaken by the whole multitude. When
the direction of all depends on one person, we call this individual a
king, and this form of political constitution a kingdom. When it is in
the power of privileged delegates, the State is said to be ruled by an
aristocracy; and when the people are all in all, they call it a
democracy, or popular constitution. And if the tie of social affection,
which originally united men in political associations for the sake of
public interest, maintains its force, each of these forms of government
is, I will not say perfect, nor, in my opinion, essentially good, but
tolerable, and such that one may accidentally be better than another:
either a just and wise king, or a selection of the most eminent
citizens, or even the populace itself (though this is the least
commendable form), may, if there be no interference of crime and
cupidity, form a constitution sufficiently secure.
XXVII. But in a monarchy the other members of the State are often too
much deprived of public counsel and jurisdiction; and under the rule of
an aristocracy the multitude can hardly possess its due share of
liberty, since it is allowed no share in the public deliberation, and no
power. And when all things are carried by a democracy, although it be
just and moderate, yet its very equality is a culpable levelling,
inasmuch as it allows no gradations of rank. Therefore, even if Cyrus,
the King of the Persians, was a most righteous and wise monarch, I
should still think that the interest of the people (for this is, as I
have said before, the same as the Commonwealth) could not be very
effectually promoted when all things depended on the beck and nod of one
individual. And though at present the people of Marseilles, our clients,
are governed with the greatest justice by elected magistrates of the
highest rank, still there is always in this condition of the people a
certain appearance of servitude; and when the Athenians, at a certain
period, having demolished their Areopagus, conducted all public affairs
by the acts and decrees of the democracy alone, their State, as it no
longer contained a distinct gradation of ranks, was no longer able to
retain its original fair appearance.
XXVIII. I have reasoned thus on the three forms of government, not
looking on them in their disorganized
381and confused conditions, but in
their proper and regular administration. These three particular forms,
however, contained in themselves, from the first, the faults and defects
I have mentioned; but they have also other dangerous vices, for there is
not one of these three forms of government which has not a precipitous
and slippery passage down to some proximate abuse. For, after thinking
of that endurable, or, as you will have it, most amiable king, Cyrus—to
name him in preference to any one else—then, to produce a change in our
minds, we behold the barbarous Phalaris, that model of tyranny, to which
the monarchical authority is easily abused by a facile and natural
inclination. And, in like manner, along-side of the wise aristocracy of
Marseilles, we might exhibit the oligarchical faction of the thirty
tyrants which once existed at Athens. And, not to seek for other
instances, among the same Athenians, we can show you that when unlimited
power was cast into the hands of the people, it inflamed the fury of the
multitude, and aggravated that universal license which ruined their
State.
306 *В *В *
XXIX. The worst condition of things sometimes results from a confusion
of those factious tyrannies into which kings, aristocrats, and democrats
are apt to degenerate. For thus, from these diverse elements, there
occasionally arises (as I have said before) a new kind of government.
And wonderful indeed are the revolutions and periodical returns in
natural constitutions of such alternations and vicissitudes, which it is
the part of the wise politician to investigate with the closest
attention. But to calculate their approach, and to join to this
foresight the skill which moderates the course of events, and retains in
a steady hand the reins of that authority which safely conducts the
people through all the dangers to which they expose themselves, is the
work of a most illustrious citizen, and of almost divine genius.
There is a fourth kind of government, therefore, which, in my opinion,
is preferable to all these: it is that mixed and moderate government
which is composed of the three particular forms which I have already
noticed.
XXX.
Lælius. I am not ignorant, Scipio, that such is
382your opinion,
for I have often heard you say so. But I do not the less desire, if it
is not giving you too much trouble, to hear which you consider the best
of these three forms of commonwealths. For it may be of some use in
considering
307 *В *В *
XXXI. *В *В * And each commonwealth corresponds to the nature and will of
him who governs it. Therefore, in no other constitution than that in
which the people exercise sovereign power has liberty any sure abode,
than which there certainly is no more desirable blessing. And if it be
not equally established for every one, it is not even liberty at all.
And how can there be this character of equality, I do not say under a
monarchy, where slavery is least disguised or doubtful, but even in
those constitutions in which the people are free indeed in words, for
they give their suffrages, they elect officers, they are canvassed and
solicited for magistracies; but yet they only grant those things which
they are obliged to grant whether they will or not, and which are not
really in their free power, though others ask them for them? For they
are not themselves admitted to the government, to the exercise of public
authority, or to offices of select judges, which are permitted to those
only of ancient families and large fortunes. But in a free people, as
among the Rhodians and Athenians, there is no citizen who
308 *В *В *
XXXII. *В *В * No sooner is one man, or several, elevated by wealth and
power, than they say that *В *В * arise from their pride and arrogance,
when the idle and the timid give way, and bow down to the insolence of
riches. But if the people knew how to maintain its rights, then they say
that nothing could be more glorious and prosperous than democracy;
inasmuch as they themselves would be the sovereign dispensers of laws,
judgments, war, peace, public treaties, and, finally, of the fortune and
life of each individual citizen; and this condition of things is the
only one which, in their opinion, can be really called a commonwealth,
that is to say, a constitution of the people. It is on this principle
that, according to them, a people often vindicates its liberty from the
domination of kings and
383nobles; while, on the other hand, kings are not
sought for among free peoples, nor are the power and wealth of
aristocracies. They deny, moreover, that it is fair to reject this
general constitution of freemen, on account of the vices of the
unbridled populace; but that if the people be united and inclined, and
directs all its efforts to the safety and freedom of the community,
nothing can be stronger or more unchangeable; and they assert that this
necessary union is easily obtained in a republic so constituted that the
good of all classes is the same; while the conflicting interests that
prevail in other constitutions inevitably produce dissensions;
therefore, say they, when the senate had the ascendency, the republic
had no stability; and when kings possess the power, this blessing is
still more rare, since, as Ennius expresses it,
In kingdoms there’s no faith, and little love.
Wherefore, since the law is the bond of civil society, and the justice
of the law equal, by what rule can the association of citizens be held
together, if the condition of the citizens be not equal? For if the
fortunes of men cannot be reduced to this equality—if genius cannot be
equally the property of all—rights, at least, should be equal among
those who are citizens of the same republic. For what is a republic but
an association of rights?
309 *В *В *
XXXIII. But as to the other political constitutions, these democratical
advocates do not think they are worthy of being distinguished by the
name which they claim. For why, say they, should we apply the name of
king, the title of Jupiter the Beneficent, and not rather the title of
tyrant, to a man ambitious of sole authority and power, lording it over
a degraded multitude? For a tyrant may be as merciful as a king may be
oppressive; so that the whole difference to the people is, whether they
serve an indulgent master or a cruel one, since serve some one they
must. But how could Sparta, at the period of the boasted superiority of
her political institution, obtain a constant enjoyment of just and
virtuous kings, when they necessarily received an hereditary monarch,
good, bad, or indifferent, because he happened to be of the blood royal?
As to
384aristocrats, Who will endure, say they, that men should
distinguish themselves by such a title, and that not by the voice of the
people, but by their own votes? For how is such a one judged to be best
either in learning, sciences, or arts?
310 *В *В *
XXXIV. *В *В * If it does so by hap-hazard, it will be as easily upset as
a vessel if the pilot were chosen by lot from among the passengers. But
if a people, being free, chooses those to whom it can trust itself—and,
if it desires its own preservation, it will always choose the
noblest—then certainly it is in the counsels of the aristocracy that
the safety of the State consists, especially as nature has not only
appointed that these superior men should excel the inferior sort in high
virtue and courage, but has inspired the people also with the desire of
obedience towards these, their natural lords. But they say this
aristocratical State is destroyed by the depraved opinions of men, who,
through ignorance of virtue (which, as it belongs to few, can be
discerned and appreciated by few), imagine that not only rich and
powerful men, but also those who are nobly born, are necessarily the
best. And so when, through this popular error, the riches, and not the
virtue, of a few men has taken possession of the State, these chiefs
obstinately retain the title of nobles, though they want the essence of
nobility. For riches, fame, and power, without wisdom and a just method
of regulating ourselves and commanding others, are full of discredit and
insolent arrogance; nor is there any kind of government more deformed
than that in which the wealthiest are regarded as the noblest.
But when virtue governs the Commonwealth, what can be more glorious?
When he who commands the rest is himself enslaved by no lust or passion;
when he himself exhibits all the virtues to which he incites and
educates the citizens; when he imposes no law on the people which he
does not himself observe, but presents his life as a living law to his
fellow-countrymen; if a single individual could thus suffice for all,
there would be no need of more; and if the community could find a chief
ruler thus worthy of all their suffrages, none would require elected
magistrates.
385It was the difficulty of forming plans which transferred the government
from a king into the hands of many; and the error and temerity of the
people likewise transferred it from the hands of the many into those of
the few. Thus, between the weakness of the monarch and the rashness of
the multitude, the aristocrats have occupied the middle place, than
which nothing can be better arranged; and while they superintend the
public interest, the people necessarily enjoy the greatest possible
prosperity, being free from all care and anxiety, having intrusted their
security to others, who ought sedulously to defend it, and not allow the
people to suspect that their advantage is neglected by their rulers.
For as to that equality of rights which democracies so loudly boast of,
it can never be maintained; for the people themselves, so dissolute and
so unbridled, are always inclined to flatter a number of demagogues; and
there is in them a very great partiality for certain men and dignities,
so that their equality, so called, becomes most unfair and iniquitous.
For as equal honor is given to the most noble and the most infamous,
some of whom must exist in every State, then the equity which they
eulogize becomes most inequitable—an evil which never can happen in
those states which are governed by aristocracies. These reasonings, my
Lælius, and some others of the same kind, are usually brought forward by
those that so highly extol this form of political constitution.
XXXV. Then Lælius said: But you have not told us, Scipio, which of these
three forms of government you yourself most approve.
Scipio. You are right to shape your question, which of the three I
most approve, for there is not one of them which I approve at all by
itself, since, as I told you, I prefer that government which is mixed
and composed of all these forms, to any one of them taken separately.
But if I must confine myself to one of these particular forms simply and
exclusively, I must confess I prefer the royal one, and praise that as
the first and best. In this, which I here choose to call the primitive
form of government, I find the title of father attached to that of king,
to express that he watches over the citizens as over his children, and
endeavors
386rather to preserve them in freedom than reduce them to
slavery. So that it is more advantageous for those who are insignificant
in property and capacity to be supported by the care of one excellent
and eminently powerful man. The nobles here present themselves, who
profess that they can do all this in much better style; for they say
that there is much more wisdom in many than in one, and at least as much
faith and equity. And, last of all, come the people, who cry with a loud
voice that they will render obedience neither to the one nor the few;
that even to brute beasts nothing is so dear as liberty; and that all
men who serve either kings or nobles are deprived of it. Thus, the kings
attract us by affection, the nobles by talent, the people by liberty;
and in the comparison it is hard to choose the best.
Lælius. I think so too, but yet it is impossible to despatch the other
branches of the question, if you leave this primary point undetermined.
XXXVI.
Scipio. We must then, I suppose, imitate Aratus, who, when he
prepared himself to treat of great things, thought himself in duty bound
to begin with Jupiter.
Lælius. Wherefore Jupiter? and what is there in this discussion which
resembles that poem?
Scipio. Why, it serves to teach us that we cannot better commence our
investigations than by invoking him whom, with one voice, both learned
and unlearned extol as the universal king of all gods and men.
How so? said Lælius.
Do you, then, asked Scipio, believe in nothing which is not before your
eyes? whether these ideas have been established by the chiefs of states
for the benefit of society, that there might be believed to exist one
Universal Monarch in heaven, at whose nod (as Homer expresses it) all
Olympus trembles, and that he might be accounted both king and father of
all creatures; for there is great authority, and there are many
witnesses, if you choose to call all many, who attest that all nations
have unanimously recognized, by the decrees of their chiefs, that
nothing is better than a king, since they think that all the Gods are
governed by the divine power of one sovereign; or if we suspect
387that
this opinion rests on the error of the ignorant, and should be classed
among the fables, let us listen to those universal testimonies of
erudite men, who have, as it were, seen with their eyes those things to
the knowledge of which we can hardly attain by report.
What men do you mean? said Lælius.
Those, replied Scipio, who, by the investigation of nature, have arrived
at the opinion that the whole universe [is animated] by a single
Mind
311. *В *В *
XXXVII. But if you please, my Lælius, I will bring forward evidences
which are neither too ancient nor in any respect barbarous.
Those, said Lælius, are what I want.
Scipio. You are aware that it is now not four centuries since this
city of ours has been without kings.
Lælius. You are correct; it is less than four centuries.
Scipio. Well, then, what are four centuries in the age of a state or
city? is it a long time?
Lælius. It hardly amounts to the age of maturity.
Scipio. You say truly; and yet not four centuries have elapsed since
there was a king in Rome.
Lælius. And he was a proud king.
Scipio. But who was his predecessor?
Lælius. He was an admirably just one; and, indeed, we must bestow the
same praise on all his predecessors as far back as Romulus, who reigned
about six centuries ago.
Scipio. Even he, then, is not very ancient.
Lælius. No; he reigned when Greece was already becoming old.
Scipio. Agreed. Was Romulus, then, think you, king of a barbarous
people?
Lælius. Why, as to that, if we were to follow the example of the
Greeks, who say that all people are either Greeks or barbarians, I am
afraid that we must confess that he was a king of barbarians; but if
this name belongs rather to manners than to languages, then I believe
the Greeks were just as barbarous as the Romans.
Then Scipio said: But with respect to the present question, we do not so
much need to inquire into the nation as into the disposition. For if
intelligent men, at a period so
388little remote, desired the government
of kings, you will confess that I am producing authorities that are
neither antiquated, rude, nor insignificant.
XXXVIII. Then Lælius said: I see, Scipio, that you are very sufficiently
provided with authorities; but with me, as with every fair judge,
authorities are worth less than arguments.
Scipio replied: Then, Lælius, you shall yourself make use of an argument
derived from your own senses.
Lælius. What senses do you mean?
Scipio. The feelings which you experience when at any time you happen
to feel angry with any one.
Lælius. That happens rather oftener than I could wish.
Scipio. Well, then, when you are angry, do you permit your anger to
triumph over your judgment?
No, by Hercules! said Lælius; I imitate the famous Archytas of Tarentum,
who, when he came to his villa, and found all its arrangements were
contrary to his orders, said to his steward, “Ah! you unlucky scoundrel,
I would flog you to death, if it were not that I am in a rage with you.”
Capital, said Scipio. Archytas, then, regarded unreasonable anger as a
kind of sedition and rebellion of nature which he sought to appease by
reflection. And so, if we examine avarice, the ambition of power or of
glory, or the lusts of concupiscence and licentiousness, we shall find a
certain conscience in the mind of man, which, like a king, sways by the
force of counsel all the inferior faculties and propensities; and this,
in truth, is the noblest portion of our nature; for when conscience
reigns, it allows no resting-place to lust, violence, or temerity.
Lælius. You have spoken the truth.
Scipio. Well, then, does a mind thus governed and regulated meet your
approbation?
Lælius. More than anything upon earth.
Scipio. Then you would not approve that the evil passions, which are
innumerable, should expel conscience, and that lusts and animal
propensities should assume an ascendency over us?
Lælius. For my part, I can conceive nothing more wretched than a mind
thus degraded, or a man animated by a soul so licentious.
389Scipio. You desire, then, that all the faculties of the mind should
submit to a ruling power, and that conscience should reign over them
all?
Lælius. Certainly, that is my wish.
Scipio. How, then, can you doubt what opinion to form on the subject
of the Commonwealth? in which, if the State is thrown into many hands,
it is very plain that there will be no presiding authority; for if power
be not united, it soon comes to nothing.
XXXIX. Then Lælius asked: But what difference is there, I should like to
know, between the one and the many, if justice exists equally in many?
And Scipio said: Since I see, my Lælius, that the authorities I have
adduced have no great influence on you, I must continue to employ you
yourself as my witness in proof of what I am saying.
In what way, said Lælius, are you going to make me again support your
argument?
Scipio. Why, thus: I recollect, when we were lately at Formiæ, that
you told your servants repeatedly to obey the orders of more than one
master only.
Lælius. To be sure, those of my steward.
Scipio. What do you at home? Do you commit your affairs to the hands
of many persons?
Lælius. No, I trust them to myself alone.
Scipio. Well, in your whole establishment, is there any other master
but yourself?
Lælius. Not one.
Scipio. Then I think you must grant me that, as respects the State,
the government of single individuals, provided they are just, is
superior to any other.
Lælius. You have conducted me to this conclusion, and I entertain very
nearly that opinion.
XL. And Scipio said: You would still further agree with me, my Lælius,
if, omitting the common comparisons, that one pilot is better fitted to
steer a ship, and a physician to treat an invalid, provided they be
competent men in their respective professions, than many could be, I
should come at once to more illustrious examples.
Lælius. What examples do you mean?
Scipio. Do not you observe that it was the cruelty and
390pride of one
single Tarquin only that made the title of king unpopular among the
Romans?
Lælius. Yes, I acknowledge that.
Scipio. You are also aware of this fact, on which I think I shall
debate in the course of the coming discussion, that after the expulsion
of King Tarquin, the people was transported by a wonderful excess of
liberty. Then innocent men were driven into banishment; then the estates
of many individuals were pillaged, consulships were made annual, public
authorities were overawed by mobs, popular appeals took place in all
cases imaginable; then secessions of the lower orders ensued, and,
lastly, those proceedings which tended to place all powers in the hands
of the populace.
Lælius. I must confess this is all too true.
All these things now, said Scipio, happened during periods of peace and
tranquillity, for license is wont to prevail when there is little to
fear, as in a calm voyage or a trifling disease. But as we observe the
voyager and the invalid implore the aid of some one competent director,
as soon as the sea grows stormy and the disease alarming, so our nation
in peace and security commands, threatens, resists, appeals from, and
insults its magistrates, but in war obeys them as strictly as kings; for
public safety is, after all, rather more valuable than popular license.
And in the most serious wars, our countrymen have even chosen the entire
command to be deposited in the hands of some single chief, without a
colleague; the very name of which magistrate indicates the absolute
character of his power. For though he is evidently called dictator
because he is appointed (dicitur), yet do we still observe him, my
Lælius, in our sacred books entitled Magister Populi (the master of the
people).
This is certainly the case, said Lælius.
Our ancestors, therefore, said Scipio, acted wisely.
312 *В *В *
XLI. When the people is deprived of a just king, as Ennius says, after
the death of one of the best of monarchs,
They hold his memory dear, and, in the warmth
Of their discourse, they cry, O Romulus!
O prince divine, sprung from the might of Mars
To be thy country’s guardian! O our sire!
Be our protector still, O heaven-begot!
391Not heroes, nor lords alone, did they call those whom they lawfully
obeyed; nor merely as kings did they proclaim them; but they pronounced
them their country’s guardians, their fathers, and their Gods. Nor,
indeed, without cause, for they added,
Thou, Prince, hast brought us to the gates of light.
And truly they believed that life and honor and glory had arisen to them
from the justice of their king. The same good-will would doubtless have
remained in their descendants, if the same virtues had been preserved on
the throne; but, as you see, by the injustice of one man the whole of
that kind of constitution fell into ruin.
I see it indeed, said Lælius, and I long to know the history of these
political revolutions both in our own Commonwealth and in every other.
XLII. And Scipio said: When I shall have explained my opinion respecting
the form of government which I prefer, I shall be able to speak to you
more accurately respecting the revolutions of states, though I think
that such will not take place so easily in the mixed form of government
which I recommend. With respect, however, to absolute monarchy, it
presents an inherent and invincible tendency to revolution. No sooner
does a king begin to be unjust than this entire form of government is
demolished, and he at once becomes a tyrant, which is the worst of all
governments, and one very closely related to monarchy. If this State
falls into the hands of the nobles, which is the usual course of events,
it becomes an aristocracy, or the second of the three kinds of
constitutions which I have described; for it is, as it were, a
royal—that is to say, a paternal—council of the chief men of the State
consulting for the public benefit. Or if the people by itself has
expelled or slain a tyrant, it is moderate in its conduct as long as it
has sense and wisdom, and while it rejoices in its exploit, and applies
itself to maintaining the constitution which it has established. But if
ever the people has raised its forces against a just king and robbed him
of his throne, or, as has frequently happened, has tasted the blood of
its legitimate nobles, and subjected the whole Commonwealth to its own
license, you can imagine 392no flood or conflagration so terrible, or any
whose violence is harder to appease than this unbridled insolence of the
populace.
XLIII. Then we see realized that which Plato so vividly describes, if I
can but express it in our language. It is by no means easy to do it
justice in translation: however, I will try.
When, says Plato, the insatiate jaws of the populace are fired with the
thirst of liberty, and when the people, urged on by evil ministers,
drains in its thirst the cup, not of tempered liberty, but unmitigated
license, then the magistrates and chiefs, if they are not utterly
subservient and remiss, and shameless promoters of the popular
licentiousness, are pursued, incriminated, accused, and cried down under
the title of despots and tyrants. I dare say you recollect the passage.
Yes, said Lælius, it is familiar to me.
Scipio. Plato thus proceeds: Then those who feel in duty bound to obey
the chiefs of the State are persecuted by the insensate populace, who
call them voluntary slaves. But those who, though invested with
magistracies, wish to be considered on an equality with private
individuals, and those private individuals who labor to abolish all
distinctions between their own class and the magistrates, are extolled
with acclamations and overwhelmed with honors, so that it inevitably
happens in a commonwealth thus revolutionized that liberalism abounds in
all directions, due authority is found wanting even in private families,
and misrule seems to extend even to the animals that witness it. Then
the father fears the son, and the son neglects the father. All modesty
is banished; they become far too liberal for that. No difference is made
between the citizen and the alien; the master dreads and cajoles his
scholars, and the scholars despise their masters. The young men assume
the gravity of sages, and sages must stoop to the follies of children,
lest they should be hated and oppressed by them. The very slaves even
are under but little restraint; wives boast the same rights as their
husbands; dogs, horses, and asses are emancipated in this outrageous
excess of freedom, and run about so violently that they frighten the
passengers from the road. At length 393the termination of all this
infinite licentiousness is, that the minds of the citizens become so
fastidious and effeminate, that when they observe even the slightest
exertion of authority they grow angry and seditious, and thus the laws
begin to be neglected, so that the people are absolutely without any
master at all.
Then Lælius said: You have very accurately rendered the opinions which
he expressed.
XLIV. Scipio. Now, to return to the argument of my discourse. It
appears that this extreme license, which is the only liberty in the eyes
of the vulgar, is, according to Plato, such that from it as a sort of
root tyrants naturally arise and spring up. For as the excessive power
of an aristocracy occasions the destruction of the nobles, so this
excessive liberalism of democracies brings after it the slavery of the
people. Thus we find in the weather, the soil, and the animal
constitution the most favorable conditions are sometimes suddenly
converted by their excess into the contrary, and this fact is especially
observable in political governments; and this excessive liberty soon
brings the people collectively and individually to an excessive
servitude. For, as I said, this extreme liberty easily introduces the
reign of tyranny, the severest of all unjust slaveries. In fact, from
the midst of this unbridled and capricious populace, they elect some one
as a leader in opposition to their afflicted and expelled nobles: some
new chief, forsooth, audacious and impure, often insolently persecuting
those who have deserved well of the State, and ready to gratify the
populace at his neighbor’s expense as well as his own. Then, since the
private condition is naturally exposed to fears and alarms, the people
invest him with many powers, and these are continued in his hands. Such
men, like Pisistratus of Athens, will soon find an excuse for
surrounding themselves with body-guards, and they will conclude by
becoming tyrants over the very persons who raised them to dignity. If
such despots perish by the vengeance of the better citizens, as is
generally the case, the constitution is re-established; but if they fall
by the hands of bold insurgents, then the same faction succeeds them,
which is only another species of tyranny. And the same revolution arises
394from the fair system of aristocracy when any corruption has betrayed
the nobles from the path of rectitude. Thus the power is like the ball
which is flung from hand to hand: it passes from kings to tyrants, from
tyrants to the aristocracy, from them to democracy, and from these back
again to tyrants and to factions; and thus the same kind of government
is seldom long maintained.
XLV. Since these are the facts of experience, royalty is, in my opinion,
very far preferable to the three other kinds of political constitutions.
But it is itself inferior to that which is composed of an equal mixture
of the three best forms of government, united and modified by one
another. I wish to establish in a commonwealth a royal and pre-eminent
chief. Another portion of power should be deposited in the hands of the
aristocracy, and certain things should be reserved to the judgment and
wish of the multitude. This constitution, in the first place, possesses
that great equality without which men cannot long maintain their
freedom; secondly, it offers a great stability, while the particular
separate and isolated forms easily fall into their contraries; so that a
king is succeeded by a despot, an aristocracy by a faction, a democracy
by a mob and confusion; and all these forms are frequently sacrificed to
new revolutions. In this united and mixed constitution, however, similar
disasters cannot happen without the greatest vices in public men. For
there can be little to occasion revolution in a state in which every
person is firmly established in his appropriate rank, and there are but
few modes of corruption into which we can fall.
XLVI. But I fear, Lælius, and you, my amiable and learned friends, that
if I were to dwell any longer on this argument, my words would seem
rather like the lessons of a master, and not like the free conversation
of one who is uniting with you in the consideration of truth. I shall
therefore pass on to those things which are familiar to all, and which I
have long studied. And in these matters I believe, I feel, and I affirm
that of all governments there is none which, either in its entire
constitution or the distribution of its parts, or in the discipline of
its manners, is comparable to that which our fathers received from our
earliest ancestors, and which they have handed down to 395us. And since
you wish to hear from me a development of this constitution, with which
you are all acquainted, I shall endeavor to explain its true character
and excellence. Thus keeping my eye fixed on the model of our Roman
Commonwealth, I shall endeavor to accommodate to it all that I have to
say on the best form of government. And by treating the subject in this
way, I think I shall be able to accomplish most satisfactorily the task
which Lælius has imposed on me.
XLVII. Lælius. It is a task most properly and peculiarly your own, my
Scipio; for who can speak so well as you either on the subject of the
institutions of our ancestors, since you yourself are descended from
most illustrious ancestors, or on that of the best form of a
constitution which, if we possess (though at this moment we do not,
still), when we do possess such a thing, who will be more flourishing in
it than you? or on that of providing counsels for the future, as you,
who, by dispelling two mighty perils from our city, have provided for
its safety forever?
FRAGMENTS.
XLVIII. As our country is the source of the greatest benefits, and is a
parent dearer than those who have given us life, we owe her still warmer
gratitude than belongs to our human relations. *В *В *
Nor would Carthage have continued to flourish during six centuries
without wisdom and good institutions. *В *В *
In truth, says Cicero, although the reasonings of those men may contain
most abundant fountains of science and virtue; still, if we compare them
with the achievements and complete actions of statesmen, they will seem
not to have been of so much service in the actual business of men as of
amusement for their leisure.
396INTRODUCTION TO THE SECOND BOOK,
BY THE ORIGINAL TRANSLATOR.
In this second book of his Commonwealth, Cicero gives us a spirited and
eloquent review of the history and successive developments of the Roman
constitution. He bestows the warmest praises on its early kings, points
out the great advantages which had resulted from its primitive
monarchical system, and explains how that system had been gradually
broken up. In order to prove the importance of reviving it, he gives a
glowing picture of the evils and disasters that had befallen the Roman
State in consequence of that overcharge of democratic folly and violence
which had gradually gained an alarming preponderance, and describes,
with a kind of prophetic sagacity, the fruit of his political
experience, the subsequent revolutions of the Roman State, which such a
state of things would necessarily bring about.
BOOK II.
I. [
When, therefore, he observed all his friends kindled with the
de]sire of hearing him, Scipio thus opened the discussion. I will
commence, said Scipio, with a sentiment of old Cato, whom, as you know,
I singularly loved and exceedingly admired, and to whom, in compliance
with the judgment of both my parents, and also by my own desire, I was
entirely devoted during my youth; of whose discourse, indeed, I could
never have enough, so much experience did he possess as a statesman
respecting the republic which he had so long governed, both in peace and
war, with so much success. There was also an admirable propriety in his
style of conversation, in which wit was tempered with gravity; a
wonderful aptitude for acquiring, and at the same time communicating,
information; and his life was in perfect correspondence and unison with
his language. He used to say that the government of Rome was superior to
that of other states for this reason, because in nearly all of them
there had been single individuals, each of whom had regulated their
commonwealth
397according to their own laws and their own ordinances. So
Minos had done in Crete, and Lycurgus in Sparta; and in Athens, which
experienced so many revolutions, first Theseus, then Draco, then Solon,
then Clisthenes, afterward many others; and, lastly, when it was almost
lifeless and quite prostrate, that great and wise man, Demetrius
Phalereus, supported it. But our Roman constitution, on the contrary,
did not spring from the genius of one individual, but from that of many;
and it was established, not in the lifetime of one man, but in the
course of several ages and centuries. For, added he, there never yet
existed any genius so vast and comprehensive as to allow nothing at any
time to escape its attention; and all the geniuses in the world united
in a single mind could never, within the limits of a single life, exert
a foresight sufficiently extensive to embrace and harmonize all, without
the aid of experience and practice.
Thus, according to Cato’s usual habit, I now ascend in my discourse to
the “origin of the people,” for I like to adopt the expression of Cato.
I shall also more easily execute my proposed task if I thus exhibit to
you our political constitution in its infancy, progress, and maturity,
now so firm and fully established, than if, after the example of
Socrates in the books of Plato, I were to delineate a mere imaginary
republic.
II. When all had signified their approbation, Scipio resumed: What
commencement of a political constitution can we conceive more brilliant,
or more universally known, than the foundation of Rome by the hand of
Romulus? And he was the son of Mars: for we may grant this much to the
common report existing among men, especially as it is not merely
ancient, but one also which has been wisely maintained by our ancestors,
in order that those who have done great service to communities may enjoy
the reputation of having received from the Gods, not only their genius,
but their very birth.
It is related, then, that soon after the birth of Romulus and his
brother Remus, Amulius, King of Alba, fearing that they might one day
undermine his authority, ordered that they should be exposed on the
banks of the Tiber; and that in this situation the infant Romulus was
suckled
398by a wild beast; that he was afterward educated by the
shepherds, and brought up in the rough way of living and labors of the
countrymen; and that he acquired, when he grew up, such superiority over
the rest by the vigor of his body and the courage of his soul, that all
the people who at that time inhabited the plains in the midst of which
Rome now stands, tranquilly and willingly submitted to his government.
And when he had made himself the chief of those bands, to come from
fables to facts, he took Alba Longa, a powerful and strong city at that
time, and slew its king, Amulius.
III. Having acquired this glory, he conceived the design (as they tell
us) of founding a new city and establishing a new state. As respected
the site of his new city, a point which requires the greatest foresight
in him who would lay the foundation of a durable commonwealth, he chose
the most convenient possible position. For he did not advance too near
the sea, which he might easily have done with the forces under his
command, either by entering the territory of the Rutuli and Aborigines,
or by founding his citadel at the mouth of the Tiber, where many years
after Ancus Martius established a colony. But Romulus, with admirable
genius and foresight, observed and perceived that sites very near the
sea are not the most favorable positions for cities which would attain a
durable prosperity and dominion. And this, first, because maritime
cities are always exposed, not only to many attacks, but to perils they
cannot provide against. For the continued land gives notice, by many
indications, not only of any regular approaches, but also of any sudden
surprises of an enemy, and announces them beforehand by the mere sound.
There is no adversary who, on an inland territory, can arrive so swiftly
as to prevent our knowing not only his existence, but his character too,
and where he comes from. But a maritime and naval enemy can fall upon a
town on the sea-coast before any one suspects that he is about to come;
and when he does come, nothing exterior indicates who he is, or whence
he comes, or what he wishes; nor can it even be determined and
distinguished on all occasions whether he is a friend or a foe.
IV. But maritime cities are likewise naturally exposed
399to corrupt
influences, and revolutions of manners. Their civilization is more or
less adulterated by new languages and customs, and they import not only
foreign merchandise, but foreign fashions, to such a degree that nothing
can continue unalloyed in the national institutions. Those who inhabit
these maritime towns do not remain in their native place, but are urged
afar from their homes by winged hope and speculation. And even when they
do not desert their country in person, still their minds are always
expatiating and voyaging round the world.
Nor, indeed, was there any cause which more deeply undermined Corinth
and Carthage, and at last overthrew them both, than this wandering and
dispersion of their citizens, whom the passion of commerce and
navigation had induced to abandon the cultivation of their lands and
their attention to military pursuits.
The proximity of the sea likewise administers to maritime cities a
multitude of pernicious incentives to luxury, which are either acquired
by victory or imported by commerce; and the very agreeableness of their
position nourishes many expensive and deceitful gratifications of the
passions. And what I have spoken of Corinth may be applied, for aught I
know, without incorrectness to the whole of Greece. For the Peloponnesus
itself is almost wholly on the sea-coast; nor, besides the Phliasians,
are there any whose lands do not touch the sea; and beyond the
Peloponnesus, the Г†nianes, the Dorians, and the Dolopes are the only
inland people. Why should I speak of the Grecian islands, which, girded
by the waves, seem all afloat, as it were, together with the
institutions and manners of their cities? And these things, I have
before noticed, do not respect ancient Greece only; for which of all
those colonies which have been led from Greece into Asia, Thracia,
Italy, Sicily, and Africa, with the single exception of Magnesia, is
there that is not washed by the sea? Thus it seems as if a sort of
Grecian coast had been annexed to territories of the barbarians. For
among the barbarians themselves none were heretofore a maritime people,
if we except the Carthaginians and Etruscans; one for the sake of
commerce, the other of pillage. And this is one evident reason of the
calamities and revolutions of Greece,
400because she became infected with
the vices which belong to maritime cities, which I just now briefly
enumerated. But yet, notwithstanding these vices, they have one great
advantage, and one which is of universal application, namely, that there
is a great facility for new inhabitants flocking to them. And, again,
that the inhabitants are enabled to export and send abroad the produce
of their native lands to any nation they please, which offers them a
market for their goods.
V. By what divine wisdom, then, could Romulus embrace all the benefits
that could belong to maritime cities, and at the same time avoid the
dangers to which they are exposed, except, as he did, by building his
city on the bank of an inexhaustible river, whose equal current
discharges itself into the sea by a vast mouth, so that the city could
receive all it wanted from the sea, and discharge its superabundant
commodities by the same channel? And in the same river a communication
is found by which it not only receives from the sea all the productions
necessary to the conveniences and elegances of life, but those also
which are brought from the inland districts. So that Romulus seems to me
to have divined and anticipated that this city would one day become the
centre and abode of a powerful and opulent empire; for there is no other
part of Italy in which a city could be situated so as to be able to
maintain so wide a dominion with so much ease.
VI. As to the natural fortifications of Rome, who is so negligent and
unobservant as not to have them depicted and deeply stamped on his
memory? Such is the plan and direction of the walls, which, by the
prudence of Romulus and his royal successors, are bounded on all sides
by steep and rugged hills; and the only aperture between the Esquiline
and Quirinal mountains is enclosed by a formidable rampart, and
surrounded by an immense fosse. And as for our fortified citadel, it is
so secured by a precipitous barrier and enclosure of rocks, that, even
in that horrible attack and invasion of the Gauls, it remained
impregnable and inviolable. Moreover, the site which he selected had
also an abundance of fountains, and was healthy, though it was in the
midst of a pestilential region; for there are hills which at once create
a current
401of fresh air, and fling an agreeable shade over the valleys.
VII. These things he effected with wonderful rapidity, and thus
established the city, which, from his own name Romulus, he determined to
call Rome. And in order to strengthen his new city, he conceived a
design, singular enough, and even a little rude, yet worthy of a great
man, and of a genius which discerned far away in futurity the means of
strengthening his power and his people. The young Sabine females of
honorable birth who had come to Rome, attracted by the public games and
spectacles which Romulus then, for the first time, established as annual
games in the circus, were suddenly carried off at the feast of
Consus
313 by his orders, and were given in marriage to the men of the
noblest families in Rome. And when, on this account, the Sabines had
declared war against Rome, the issue of the battle being doubtful and
undecided, Romulus made an alliance with Tatius, King of the Sabines, at
the intercession of the matrons themselves who had been carried off. By
this compact he admitted the Sabines into the city, gave them a
participation in the religious ceremonies, and divided his power with
their king.
VIII. But after the death of Tatius, the entire government was again
vested in the hands of Romulus, although, besides making Tatius his own
partner, he had also elected some of the chiefs of the Sabines into the
royal council, who on account of their affectionate regard for the
people were called
patres, or fathers. He also divided the people into
three tribes, called after the name of Tatius, and his own name, and
that of Locumo, who had fallen as his ally in the Sabine war; and also
into thirty curiæ, designated by the names of those Sabine virgins, who,
after being carried off at the festivals, generously offered themselves
as the mediators of peace and coalition.
But though these orders were established in the life of Tatius, yet,
after his death, Romulus reigned with still greater power by the counsel
and authority of the senate.
IX. In this respect he approved and adopted the principle which Lycurgus
but little before had applied to the government of Lacedæmon; namely,
that the monarchical
402authority and the royal power operate best in the
government of states when to this supreme authority is joined the
influence of the noblest of the citizens.
Therefore, thus supported, and, as it were, propped up by this council
or senate, Romulus conducted many wars with the neighboring nations in a
most successful manner; and while he refused to take any portion of the
booty to his own palace, he did not cease to enrich the citizens. He
also cherished the greatest respect for that institution of hierarchical
and ecclesiastical ordinances which we still retain to the great benefit
of the Commonwealth; for in the very commencement of his government he
founded the city with religious rites, and in the institution of all
public establishments he was equally careful in attending to these
sacred ceremonials, and associated with himself on these occasions
priests that were selected from each of the tribes. He also enacted that
the nobles should act as patrons and protectors to the inferior
citizens, their natural clients and dependants, in their respective
districts, a measure the utility of which I shall afterward notice.—The
judicial punishments were mostly fines of sheep and oxen; for the
property of the people at that time consisted in their fields and
cattle, and this circumstance has given rise to the expressions which
still designate real and personal wealth. Thus the people were kept in
order rather by mulctations than by bodily inflictions.
X. After Romulus had thus reigned thirty-seven years, and established
these two great supports of government, the hierarchy and the senate,
having disappeared in a sudden eclipse of the sun, he was thought worthy
of being added to the number of the Gods—an honor which no mortal man
ever was able to attain to but by a glorious pre-eminence of virtue. And
this circumstance was the more to be admired in the case of Romulus
because most of the great men that have been deified were so exalted to
celestial dignities by the people, in periods very little enlightened,
when fiction was easy and ignorance went hand-in-hand with credulity.
But with respect to Romulus we know that he lived less than six
centuries ago, at a time when science and literature were already
advanced, and had got rid of many of the ancient errors that had
403prevailed among less civilized peoples. For if, as we consider proved
by the Grecian annals, Rome was founded in the seventh Olympiad, the
life of Romulus was contemporary with that period in which Greece
already abounded in poets and musicians—an age when fables, except
those concerning ancient matters, received little credit.
For, one hundred and eight years after the promulgation of the laws of
Lycurgus, the first Olympiad was established, which indeed, through a
mistake of names, some authors have supposed constituted, by Lycurgus
likewise. And Homer himself, according to the best computation, lived
about thirty years before the time of Lycurgus. We must conclude,
therefore, that Homer flourished very many years before the date of
Romulus. So that, as men had now become learned, and as the times
themselves were not destitute of knowledge, there was not much room left
for the success of mere fictions. Antiquity indeed has received fables
that have at times been sufficiently improbable: but this epoch, which
was already so cultivated, disdaining every fiction that was impossible,
rejected
314 *В *В * We may therefore, perhaps, attach some credit to
this story of Romulus’s immortality, since human life was at that time
experienced, cultivated, and instructed. And doubtless there was in him
such energy of genius and virtue that it is not altogether impossible to
believe the report of Proculus Julius, the husbandman, of that
glorification having befallen Romulus which for many ages we have denied
to less illustrious men. At all events, Proculus is reported to have
stated in the council, at the instigation of the senators, who wished to
free themselves from all suspicion of having been accessaries to the
death of Romulus, that he had seen him on that hill which is now called
the Quirinal, and that he had commanded him to inform the people that
they should build him a temple on that same hill, and offer him
sacrifices under the name of Quirinus.
XI. You see, therefore, that the genius of this great man did not merely
establish the constitution of a new people, and then leave them, as it
were, crying in their cradle; but he still continued to superintend
their education
404till they had arrived at an adult and wellnigh a mature
age.
Then Lælius said: We now see, my Scipio, what you meant when you said
that you would adopt a new method of discussing the science of
government, different from any found in the writings of the Greeks. For
that prime master of philosophy, whom none ever surpassed in eloquence,
I mean Plato, chose an open plain on which to build an imaginary city
after his own taste—a city admirably conceived, as none can deny, but
remote enough from the real life and manners of men. Others, without
proposing to themselves any model or type of government whatever, have
argued on the constitutions and forms of states. You, on the contrary,
appear to be about to unite these two methods; for, as far as you have
gone, you seem to prefer attributing to others your discoveries, rather
than start new theories under your own name and authority, as Socrates
has done in the writings of Plato. Thus, in speaking of the site of
Rome, you refer to a systematic policy, to the acts of Romulus, which
were many of them the result of necessity or chance; and you do not
allow your discourse to run riot over many states, but you fix and
concentrate it on our own Commonwealth. Proceed, then, in the course you
have adopted; for I see that you intend to examine our other kings, in
your pursuit of a perfect republic, as it were.
XII. Therefore, said Scipio, when that senate of Romulus which was
composed of the nobles, whom the king himself respected so highly that
he designated them
patres, or fathers, and their children patricians,
attempted after the death of Romulus to conduct the government without a
king, the people would not suffer it, but, amidst their regret for
Romulus, desisted not from demanding a fresh monarch. The nobles then
prudently resolved to establish an interregnum—a new political form,
unknown to other nations. It was not without its use, however, since,
during the interval which elapsed before the definitive nomination of
the new king, the State was not left without a ruler, nor subjected too
long to the same governor, nor exposed to the fear lest some one, in
consequence of the prolonged enjoyment of power, should become more
unwilling
405to lay it aside, or more powerful if he wished to secure it
permanently for himself. At which time this new nation discovered a
political provision which had escaped the Spartan Lycurgus, who
conceived that the monarch ought not to be elective—if indeed it is
true that this depended on Lycurgus—but that it was better for the
Lacedæmonians to acknowledge as their sovereign the next heir of the
race of Hercules, whoever he might be: but our Romans, rude as they
were, saw the importance of appointing a king, not for his family, but
for his virtue and experience.
XIII. And fame having recognized these eminent qualities in Numa
Pompilius, the Roman people, without partiality for their own citizens,
committed itself, by the counsel of the senators, to a king of foreign
origin, and summoned this Sabine from the city of Cures to Rome, that he
might reign over them. Numa, although the people had proclaimed him king
in their Comitia Curiata, did nevertheless himself pass a Lex Curiata
respecting his own authority; and observing that the institutions of
Romulus had too much excited the military propensities of the people, he
judged it expedient to recall them from this habit of warfare by other
employments.
XIV. And, in the first place, he divided severally among the citizens
the lands which Romulus had conquered, and taught them that even without
the aid of pillage and devastation they could, by the cultivation of
their own territories, procure themselves all kinds of commodities. And
he inspired them with the love of peace and tranquillity, in which faith
and justice are likeliest to flourish, and extended the most powerful
protection to the people in the cultivation of their fields and the
enjoyment of their produce. Pompilius likewise having created
hierarchical institutions of the highest class, added two augurs to the
old number. He intrusted the superintendence of the sacred rites to five
pontiffs, selected from the body of the nobles; and by those laws which
we still preserve on our monuments he mitigated, by religious
ceremonials, the minds that had been too long inflamed by military
enthusiasm and enterprise.
He also established the Flamines and the Salian priests
406and the Vestal
Virgins, and regulated all departments of our ecclesiastical policy with
the most pious care. In the ordinance of sacrifices, he wished that the
ceremonial should be very arduous and the expenditure very light. He
thus appointed many observances, whose knowledge is extremely important,
and whose expense far from burdensome. Thus in religious worship he
added devotion and removed costliness. He was also the first to
introduce markets, games, and the other usual methods of assembling and
uniting men. By these establishments, he inclined to benevolence and
amiability spirits whom the passion for war had rendered savage and
ferocious. Having thus reigned in the greatest peace and concord
thirty-nine years—for in dates we mainly follow our Polybius, than whom
no one ever gave more attention to the investigation of the history of
the times—he departed this life, having corroborated the two grand
principles of political stability, religion and clemency.
XV. When Scipio had concluded these remarks, Is it not, said Manilius, a
true tradition which is current, that our king Numa was a disciple of
Pythagoras himself, or that at least he was a Pythagorean in his
doctrines? For I have often heard this from my elders, and we know that
it is the popular opinion; but it does not seem to be clearly proved by
the testimony of our public annals.
Then Scipio replied: The supposition is false, my Manilius; it is not
merely a fiction, but a ridiculous and bungling one too; and we should
not tolerate those statements, even in fiction, relating to facts which
not only did not happen, but which never could have happened. For it was
not till the fourth year of the reign of Tarquinius Superbus that
Pythagoras is ascertained to have come to Sybaris, Crotona, and this
part of Italy. And the sixty-second Olympiad is the common date of the
elevation of Tarquin to the throne, and of the arrival of Pythagoras.
>From which it appears, when we calculate the duration of the reigns of
the kings, that about one hundred and forty years must have elapsed
after the death of Numa before Pythagoras first arrived in Italy. And
this fact, in the minds of men who have carefully studied the annals of
time, has never been at all doubted.
407O ye immortal Gods! said Manilius, how deep and how inveterate is this
error in the minds of men! However, it costs me no effort to concede
that our Roman sciences were not imported from beyond the seas, but that
they sprung from our own indigenous and domestic virtues.
XVI. You will become still more convinced of this fact, said Africanus,
when tracing the progress of our Commonwealth as it became gradually
developed to its best and maturest condition. And you will find yet
further occasion to admire the wisdom of our ancestors on this very
account, since you will perceive, that even those things which they
borrowed from foreigners received a much higher improvement among us
than they possessed in the countries from whence they were imported
among us; and you will learn that the Roman people was aggrandized, not
by chance or hazard, but rather by counsel and discipline, to which
fortune indeed was by no means unfavorable.
XVII. After the death of King Pompilius, the people, after a short
period of interregnum, chose Tullus Hostilius for their king, in the
Comitia Curiata; and Tullus, after Numa’s example, consulted the people
in their curias to procure a sanction for his government. His excellence
chiefly appeared in his military glory and great achievements in war. He
likewise, out of his military spoils, constructed and decorated the
House of Comitia and the Senate-house. He also settled the ceremonies of
the proclamation of hostilities, and consecrated their righteous
institution by the religious sanction of the Fetial priests, so that
every war which was not duly announced and declared might be adjudged
illegal, unjust, and impious. And observe how wisely our kings at that
time perceived that certain rights ought to be allowed to the people, of
which we shall have a good deal to say hereafter. Tullus did not even
assume the ensigns of royalty without the approbation of the people; and
when he appointed twelve lictors, with their axes to go before him
315 *В *В *
XVIII. *В *В * [
Manilius.] This Commonwealth of Rome, which you are so
eloquently describing, did not creep towards perfection; it rather flew
at once to the maturity of its grandeur.
408[
Scipio.] After Tullus, Ancus Martius, a descendant of Numa by his
daughter, was appointed king by the people. He also procured the passing
of a law
316 through the Comitia Curiata respecting his government.
This king having conquered the Latins, admitted them to the rights of
citizens of Rome. He added to the city the Aventine and Cælian hills; he
distributed the lands he had taken in war; he bestowed on the public all
the maritime forests he had acquired; and he built the city Ostia, at
the mouth of the Tiber, and colonized it. When he had thus reigned
twenty-three years, he died.
Then said Lælius: Doubtless this king deserves our praises, but the
Roman history is obscure. We possess, indeed, the name of this monarch’s
mother, but we know nothing of his father.
It is so, said Scipio; but in those ages little more than the names of
the kings were recorded.
XIX. For the first time at this period, Rome appears to have become more
learned by the study of foreign literature; for it was no longer a
little rivulet, flowing from Greece towards the walls of our city, but
an overflowing river of Grecian sciences and arts. This is generally
attributed to Demaratus, a Corinthian, the first man of his country in
reputation, honor, and wealth; who, not being able to bear the despotism
of Cypselus, tyrant of Corinth, fled with large treasures, and arrived
at Tarquinii, the most flourishing city in Etruria. There, understanding
that the domination of Cypselus was thoroughly established, he, like a
free and bold-hearted man, renounced his country, and was admitted into
the number of the citizens of Tarquinii, and fixed his residence in that
city. And having married a woman of the city, he instructed his two
sons, according to the method of Greek education, in all kinds of
sciences and arts.
317 *В *В *
XX. *В *В * [One of these sons] was easily admitted to
409the rights of
citizenship at Rome; and on account of his accomplished manners and
learning, he became a favorite of our king Ancus to such a degree that
he was a partner in all his counsels, and was looked upon almost as his
associate in the government. He, besides, possessed wonderful
affability, and was very kind in assistance, support, protection, and
even gifts of money, to the citizens.
When, therefore, Ancus died, the people by their unanimous suffrages
chose for their king this Lucius Tarquinius (for he had thus transformed
the Greek name of his family, that he might seem in all respects to
imitate the customs of his adopted countrymen). And when he, too, had
procured the passing of a law respecting his authority, he commenced his
reign by doubling the original number of the senators. The ancient
senators he called patricians of the major families (
patres majorum
gentium), and he asked their votes first; and those new senators whom
he himself had added, he entitled patricians of minor families. After
this, he established the order of knights, on the plan which we maintain
to this day. He would not, however, change the denomination of the
Tatian, Rhamnensian, and Lucerian orders, though he wished to do so,
because Attus Nævius, an augur of the highest reputation, would not
sanction it. And, indeed, I am aware that the Corinthians were
remarkably attentive to provide for the maintenance and good condition
of their cavalry by taxes levied on the inheritance of widows and
orphans. To the first equestrian orders Lucius also added new ones,
composing a body of three hundred knights. And this number he doubled,
after having conquered the Г†quicoli, a large and ferocious people, and
dangerous enemies of the Roman State. Having likewise repulsed from our
walls an invasion of the Sabines, he routed them by the aid of his
cavalry, and subdued them. He also was the first person who instituted
the grand games which are now called the Roman Games. He fulfilled his
vow to build a temple to the all-good and all-powerful Jupiter in the
Capitol—a vow which he made during a battle in the Sabine war—and died
after a reign of thirty-eight years.
XXI. Then Lælius said: All that you have been relating corroborates the
saying of Cato, that the constitution
410of the Roman Commonwealth is not
the work of one man, or one age; for we can clearly see what a great
progress in excellent and useful institutions was continued under each
successive king. But we are now arrived at the reign of a monarch who
appears to me to have been of all our kings he who had the greatest
foresight in matters of political government.
So it appears to me, said Scipio; for after Tarquinius Priscus comes
Servius Sulpicius, who was the first who is reported to have reigned
without an order from the people. He is supposed to have been the son of
a female slave at Tarquinii, by one of the soldiers or clients of King
Priscus; and as he was educated among the servants of this prince, and
waiting on him at table, the king soon observed the fire of his genius,
which shone forth even from his childhood, so skilful was he in all his
words and actions. Therefore, Tarquin, whose own children were then very
young, so loved Servius that he was very commonly believed to be his own
son, and he instructed him with the greatest care in all the sciences
with which he was acquainted, according to the most exact discipline of
the Greeks.
But when Tarquin had perished by the plots of the sons of Ancus, and
Servius (as I have said) had begun to reign, not by the order, but yet
with the good-will and consent, of the citizens—because, as it was
falsely reported that Priscus was recovering from his wounds, Servius,
arrayed in the royal robes, delivered judgment, freed the debtors at his
own expense, and, exhibiting the greatest affability, announced that he
delivered judgment at the command of Priscus—he did not commit himself
to the senate; but, after Priscus was buried, he consulted the people
respecting his authority, and, being authorized by them to assume the
dominion, he procured a law to be passed through the Comitia Curiata,
confirming his government.
He then, in the first place, avenged the injuries of the Etruscans by
arms. After which
318 *В *В *
XXII. *В *В * he enrolled eighteen centuries of knights of the first
order. Afterward, having created a great number of knights from the
common mass of the people, he
411divided the rest of the people into five
classes, distinguishing between the seniors and the juniors. These he so
constituted as to place the suffrages, not in the hands of the
multitude, but in the power of the men of property. And he took care to
make it a rule of ours, as it ought to be in every government, that the
greatest number should not have the greatest weight. You are well
acquainted with this institution, otherwise I would explain it to you;
but you are familiar with the whole system, and know how the centuries
of knights, with six suffrages, and the first class, comprising eighty
centuries, besides one other century which was allotted to the
artificers, on account of their utility to the State, produce
eighty-nine centuries. If to these there are added twelve centuries—for
that is the number of the centuries of the knights which
remain
319—the entire force of the State is summed up; and the
arrangement is such that the remaining and far more numerous multitude,
which is distributed through the ninety-six last centuries, is not
deprived of a right of suffrage, which would be an arrogant measure;
nor, on the other hand, permitted to exert too great a preponderance in
the government, which would be dangerous.
In this arrangement, Servius was very cautious in his choice of terms
and denominations. He called the rich
assidui, because they afforded
pecuniary succor
320 to the State. As to those whoso fortune did not
exceed 1500 pence, or those who had nothing but their labor, he called
them
proletarii classes, as if the State should expect from them a
hardy progeny
321 and population.
Even a single one of the ninety-six last centuries contained numerically
more citizens than the entire first class. Thus, no one was excluded
from his right of voting, yet the preponderance of votes was secured to
those who had the deepest stake in the welfare of the State. Moreover,
with reference to the accensi, velati, trumpeters, hornblowers,
proletarii
322 *В *В *
XXIII. *В *В * That that republic is arranged in the best manner which,
being composed in due proportions of those
412three elements, the
monarchical, the aristocratical, and the democratic, does not by
punishment irritate a fierce and savage mind. *В *В * [A similar
institution prevailed at Carthage], which was sixty-five years more
ancient than Rome, since it was founded thirty-nine years before the
first Olympiad; and that most ancient law-giver Lycurgus made nearly the
same arrangements. Thus the system of regular subordination, and this
mixture of the three principal forms of government, appear to me common
alike to us and them. But there is a peculiar advantage in our
Commonwealth, than which nothing can be more excellent, which I shall
endeavor to describe as accurately as possible, because it is of such a
character that nothing analogous can be discovered in ancient states;
for these political elements which I have noticed were so united in the
constitutions of Rome, of Sparta, and of Carthage, that they were not
counterbalanced by any modifying power. For in a state in which one man
is invested with a perpetual domination, especially of the monarchical
character, although there be a senate in it, as there was in Rome under
the kings, and in Sparta, by the laws of Lycurgus, or even where the
people exercise a sort of jurisdiction, as they used in the days of our
monarchy, the title of king must still be pre-eminent; nor can such a
state avoid being, and being called, a kingdom. And this kind of
government is especially subject to frequent revolutions, because the
fault of a single individual is sufficient to precipitate it into the
most pernicious disasters.
In itself, however, royalty is not only not a reprehensible form of
government, but I do not know whether it is not far preferable to all
other simple constitutions, if I approved of any simple constitution
whatever. But this preference applies to royalty so long only as it
maintains its appropriate character; and this character provides that
one individual’s perpetual power, and justice, and universal wisdom
should regulate the safety, equality, and tranquillity of the whole
people. But many privileges must be wanting to communities that live
under a king; and, in the first place, liberty, which does not consist
in slavery to a just master, but in slavery to no master at all
323 *В *В *
413XXIV. *В *В * [Let us now pass on to the reign of the seventh and last
king of Rome, Tarquinius Superbus.] And even this unjust and cruel
master had good fortune for his companion for some time in all his
enterprises. For he subdued all Latium; he captured Suessa Pometia, a
powerful and wealthy city, and, becoming possessed of an immense spoil
of gold and silver, he accomplished his father’s vow by the building of
the Capitol. He established colonies, and, faithful to the institutions
of those from whom he sprung, he sent magnificent presents, as tokens of
gratitude for his victories, to Apollo at Delphi.
XXV. Here begins the revolution of our political system of government,
and I must beg your attention to its natural course and progression. For
the grand point of political science, the object of our discourses, is
to know the march and the deviations of governments, that when we are
acquainted with the particular courses and inclinations of
constitutions, we may be able to restrain them from their fatal
tendencies, or to oppose adequate obstacles to their decline and fall.
For this Tarquinius Superbus, of whom I am speaking, being first of all
stained with the blood of his admirable predecessor on the throne, could
not be a man of sound conscience and mind; and as he feared himself the
severest punishment for his enormous crime, he sought his protection in
making himself feared. Then, in the glory of his victories and his
treasures, he exulted in insolent pride, and could neither regulate his
own manners nor the passions of the members of his family.
When, therefore, his eldest son had offered violence to Lucretia,
daughter of Tricipitinus and wife of Collatinus, and this chaste and
noble lady had stabbed herself to death on account of the injury she
could not survive—then a man eminent for his genius and virtue, Lucius
Brutus, dashed from his fellow-citizens this unjust yoke of odious
servitude; and though he was but a private man, he sustained the
government of the entire Commonwealth, and was the first that taught the
people in this State that no one was a private man when the preservation
of our liberties was concerned. Beneath his authority and command our
city rose against tyranny, and, stirred by the recent
414grief of the
father and relatives of Lucretia, and with the recollections of
Tarquin’s haughtiness, and the numberless crimes of himself and his
sons, they pronounced sentence of banishment against him and his
children, and the whole race of the Tarquins.
XXVI. Do you not observe, then, how the king sometimes degenerates into
the despot, and how, by the fault of one individual, a form of
government originally good is abused to the worst of purposes? Here is a
specimen of that despot over the people whom the Greeks denominate a
tyrant. For, according to them, a king is he who, like a father,
consults the interests of his people, and who preserves those whom he is
set over in the very best condition of life. This indeed is, as I have
said, an excellent form of government, yet still liable, and, as it
were, inclined, to a pernicious abuse. For as soon as a king assumes an
unjust and despotic power, he instantly becomes a tyrant, than which
nothing baser or fouler, than which no imaginable animal can be more
detestable to gods or men; for though in form a man, he surpasses the
most savage monsters in ferocious cruelty. For who can justly call him a
human being, who admits not between himself and his fellow-countrymen,
between himself and the whole human race, any communication of justice,
any association of kindness? But we shall find some fitter occasion of
speaking of the evils of tyranny when the subject itself prompts us to
declare against them who, even in a state already liberated, have
affected these despotic insolencies.
XXVII. Such is the first origin and rise of a tyrant. For this was the
name by which the Greeks choose to designate an unjust king; and by the
title king our Romans universally understand every man who exercises
over the people a perpetual and undivided domination. Thus Spurius
Cassius, and Marcus Manlius, and Spurius Mælius, are said to have wished
to seize upon the kingly power, and lately [Tiberius Gracchus incurred
the same accusation].
324 *В *В *
XXVIII. *В *В * [Lycurgus, in Sparta, formed, under the name of Elders,] a
small council consisting of twenty-eight members only; to these he
allotted the supreme legislative
415authority, while the king held the
supreme executive authority. Our Romans, emulating his example, and
translating his terms, entitled those whom he had called Elders,
Senators, which, as we have said, was done by Romulus in reference to
the elect patricians. In this constitution, however, the power, the
influence, and name of the king is still pre-eminent. You may
distribute, indeed, some show of power to the people, as Lycurgus and
Romulus did, but you inflame them, with the thirst of liberty by
allowing them even the slightest taste of its sweetness; and still their
hearts will be overcast with alarm lest their king, as often happens,
should become unjust. The prosperity of the people, therefore, can be
little better than fragile, when placed at the disposal of any one
individual, and subjected to his will and caprices.
XXIX. Thus the first example, prototype, and original of tyranny has
been discovered by us in the history of our own Roman State, religiously
founded by Romulus, without applying to the theoretical Commonwealth
which, according to Plato’s recital, Socrates was accustomed to describe
in his peripatetic dialogues. We have observed Tarquin, not by the
usurpation of any new power, but by the unjust abuse of the power which
he already possessed, overturn the whole system of our monarchical
constitution.
Let us oppose to this example of the tyrant another, a virtuous
king—wise, experienced, and well informed respecting the true interest
and dignity of the citizens—a guardian, as it were, and superintendent
of the Commonwealth; for that is a proper name for every ruler and
governor of a state. And take you care to recognize such a man when you
meet him, for he is the man who, by counsel and exertion, can best
protect the nation. And as the name of this man has not yet been often
mentioned in our discourse, and as the character of such a man must be
often alluded to in our future conversations, [I shall take an early
opportunity of describing it.]
325 *В *В *
XXX. *В *В * [Plato has chosen to suppose a territory and establishments
of citizens, whose fortunes] were precisely equal. And he has given us a
description of a city, rather to be desired than expected; and he has
made out
416not such a one as can really exist, but one in which the
principles of political affairs may be discerned. But for me, if I can
in any way accomplish it, while I adopt the same general principles as
Plato, I am seeking to reduce them to experience and practice, not in
the shadow and picture of a state, but in a real and actual
Commonwealth, of unrivalled amplitude and power; in order to be able to
point out, with the most graphic precision, the causes of every
political good and social evil.
For after Rome had flourished more than two hundred and forty years
under her kings and interreges, and after Tarquin was sent into
banishment, the Roman people conceived as much detestation of the name
of king as they had once experienced regret at the death, or rather
disappearance, of Romulus. Therefore, as in the first instance they
could hardly bear the idea of losing a king, so in the latter, after the
expulsion of Tarquin, they could not endure to hear the name of a
king.
326 *В *В *
XXXI. *В *В * Therefore, when that admirable constitution of Romulus had
lasted steadily about two hundred and forty years. *В *В * The whole of
that law was abolished. In this humor, our ancestors banished
Collatinus, in spite of his innocence, because of the suspicion that
attached to his family, and all the rest of the Tarquins, on account of
the unpopularity of their name. In the same humor, Valerius Publicola
was the first to lower the fasces before the people, when he spoke in
the assembly of the people. He also had the materials of his house
conveyed to the foot of Mount Velia, having observed that the
commencement of his edifice on the summit of this hill, where King
Tullius had once dwelt, excited the suspicions of the people.
It was the same man, who in this respect pre-eminently deserved the name
of Publicola, who carried in favor of the people the first law received
in the Comitia Centuriata, that no magistrate should sentence to death
or scourging a Roman citizen who appealed from his authority to the
people. And the pontifical books attest that the right of appeal had
existed, even against the decision of the kings. Our augural books
affirm the same thing. And the Twelve
417Tables prove, by a multitude of
laws, that there was a right of appeal from every judgment and penalty.
Besides, the historical fact that the decemviri who compiled the laws
were created with the privilege of judging without appeal, sufficiently
proves that the other magistrates had not the same power. And a consular
law, passed by Lucius Valerius Politus and Marcus Horatius Barbatus, men
justly popular for promoting union and concord, enacted that no
magistrate should thenceforth be appointed with authority to judge
without appeal; and the Portian laws, the work of three citizens of the
name of Portius, as you are aware, added nothing new to this edict but a
penal sanction.
Therefore Publicola, having promulgated this law in favor of appeal to
the people, immediately ordered the axes to be removed from the fasces,
which the lictors carried before the consuls, and the next day appointed
Spurius Lucretius for his colleague. And as the new consul was the
oldest of the two, Publicola ordered his lictors to pass over to him;
and he was the first to establish the rule, that each of the consuls
should be preceded by the lictors in alternate months, that there should
be no greater appearance of imperial insignia among the free people than
they had witnessed in the days of their kings. Thus, in my opinion, he
proved himself no ordinary man, as, by so granting the people a moderate
degree of liberty, he more easily maintained the authority of the
nobles.
Nor is it without reason that I have related to you these ancient and
almost obsolete events; but I wished to adduce my instances of men and
circumstances from illustrious persons and times, as it is to such
events that the rest of my discourse will be directed.
XXXII. At that period, then, the senate preserved the Commonwealth in
such a condition that though the people were really free, yet few acts
were passed by the people, but almost all, on the contrary, by the
authority, customs, and traditions of the senate. And over all the
consuls exercised a power—in time, indeed, only annual, but in nature
and prerogative completely royal.
The consuls maintained, with the greatest energy, that rule which so
much conduces to the power of our nobles and great men, that the acts of
the commons of the people
418shall not be binding, unless the authority of
the patricians has approved them. About the same period, and scarcely
ten years after the first consuls, we find the appointment of the
dictator in the person of Titus Lartius. And this new kind of
power—namely, the dictatorship—appears exceedingly similar to the
monarchical royalty. All his power, however, was vested in the supreme
authority of the senate, to which the people deferred; and in these
times great exploits were performed in war by brave men invested with
the supreme command, whether dictators or consuls.
XXXIII. But as the nature of things necessarily brought it to pass that
the people, once freed from its kings, should arrogate to itself more
and more authority, we observe that after a short interval of only
sixteen years, in the consulship of Postumus Cominius and Spurius
Cassius, they attained their object; an event explicable, perhaps, on no
distinct principle, but, nevertheless, in a manner independent of any
distinct principle. For recollect what I said in commencing our
discourse, that if there exists not in the State a just distribution and
subordination of rights, offices, and prerogatives, so as to give
sufficient domination to the chiefs, sufficient authority to the counsel
of the senators, and sufficient liberty to the people, this form of the
government cannot be durable.
For when the excessive debts of the citizens had thrown the State into
disorder, the people first retired to Mount Sacer, and next occupied
Mount Aventine. And even the rigid discipline of Lycurgus could not
maintain those restraints in the case of the Greeks. For in Sparta
itself, under the reign of Theopompus, the five magistrates whom they
term Ephori, and in Crete ten whom they entitle Cosmi, were established
in opposition to the royal power, just as tribunes were added among us
to counterbalance the consular authority.
XXXIV. There might have been a method, indeed, by which our ancestors
could have been relieved from the pressure of debt, a method with which
Solon the Athenian, who lived at no very distant period before, was
acquainted, and which our senate did not neglect when, in the
indignation which the odious avarice of one individual excited,
419all the
bonds of the citizens were cancelled, and the right of arrest for a
while suspended. In the same way, when the plebeians were oppressed by
the weight of the expenses occasioned by public misfortunes, a cure and
remedy were sought for the sake of public security. The senate, however,
having forgotten their former decision, gave an advantage to the
democracy; for, by the creation of two tribunes to appease the sedition
of the people, the power and authority of the senate were diminished;
which, however, still remained dignified and august, inasmuch as it was
still composed of the wisest and bravest men, who protected their
country both with their arms and with their counsels; whose authority
was exceedingly strong and flourishing, because in honor they were as
much before their fellow-citizens as they were inferior in
luxuriousness, and, as a general rule, not superior to them in wealth.
And their public virtues were the more agreeable to the people, because
even in private matters they were ready to serve every citizen, by their
exertions, their counsels, and their liberality.
XXXV. Such was the situation of the Commonwealth when the quæstor
impeached Spurius Cassius of being so much emboldened by the excessive
favor of the people as to endeavor to make himself master of monarchical
power. And, as you have heard, his own father, having said that he had
found that his son was really guilty of this crime, condemned him to
death at the instance of the people. About fifty-four years after the
first consulate, Spurius Tarpeius and Aulus Aternius very much gratified
the people by proposing, in the Comitia Centuriata, the substitution of
fines instead of corporal punishments. Twenty years afterward, Lucius
Papirius and Publius Pinarius, the censors, having by a strict levy of
fines confiscated to the State the entire flocks and herds of many
private individuals, a light tax on the cattle was substituted for the
law of fines in the consulship of Caius Julius and Publius Papirius.
XXXVI. But, some years previous to this, at a period when the senate
possessed the supreme influence, and the people were submissive and
obedient, a new system was adopted. At that time both the consuls and
tribunes of
420the people abdicated their magistracies, and the decemviri
were appointed, who were invested with great authority, from which there
was no appeal whatever, so as to exercise the chief domination, and to
compile the laws. After having composed, with much wisdom and equity,
the Ten Tables of laws, they nominated as their successors in the
ensuing year other decemviri, whose good faith and justice do not
deserve equal praise. One member of this college, however, merits our
highest commendation. I allude to Caius Julius, who declared respecting
the nobleman Lucius Sestius, in whose chamber a dead body had been
exhumed under his own eyes, that though as decemvir he held the highest
power without appeal, he still required bail, because he was unwilling
to neglect that admirable law which permitted no court but the Comitia
Centuriata to pronounce final sentence on the life of a Roman citizen.
XXXVII. A third year followed under the authority of the same decemvirs,
and still they were not disposed to appoint their successors. In a
situation of the Commonwealth like this, which, as I have often
repeated, could not be durable, because it had not an equal operation
with respect to all the ranks of the citizens, the whole public power
was lodged in the hands of the chiefs and decemvirs of the highest
nobility, without the counterbalancing authority of the tribunes of the
people, without the sanction of any other magistracies, and without
appeal to the people in the case of a sentence of death or scourging.
Thus, out of the injustice of these men, there was suddenly produced a
great revolution, which changed the entire condition of the government,
or they added two tables of very tyrannical laws, and though matrimonial
alliances had always been permitted, even with foreigners, they forbade,
by the most abominable and inhuman edict, that any marriages should take
place between the nobles and the commons—an order which was afterward
abrogated by the decree of Canuleius. Besides, they introduced into all
their political measures corruption, cruelty, and avarice. And indeed
the story is well known, and celebrated in many literary compositions,
that a certain Decimus Virginius was obliged, on account of the
libidinous violence of one of these decemvirs, to stab his virgin
daughter
421in the midst of the forum. Then, when he in his desperation
had fled to the Roman army which was encamped on Mount Algidum, the
soldiers abandoned the war in which they were engaged, and took
possession of the Sacred Mount, as they had done before on a similar
occasion, and next invested Mount Aventine in their arms.
327 Our
ancestors knew how to prove most thoroughly, and to retain most wisely.
*В *В *
XXXVIII. And when Scipio had spoken in this manner, and all his friends
were awaiting in silence the rest of his discourse, then said Tubero:
Since these men who are older than I, my Scipio, make no fresh demands
on you, I shall take the liberty to tell you what I particularly wish
you would explain in your subsequent remarks.
Do so, said Scipio, and I shall be glad to hear.
Then Tubero said: You appear to me to have spoken a panegyric on our
Commonwealth of Rome exclusively, though Lælius requested your views not
only of the government of our own State, but of the policy of states in
general. I have not, therefore, yet sufficiently learned from your
discourse, with respect to that mixed form of government you most
approve, by what discipline, moral and legal, we may be best able to
establish and maintain it.
XXXIX. Africanus replied: I think that we shall soon find an occasion
better adapted to the discussion you have proposed, respecting the
constitution and conservatism of states. As to the best form of
government, I think on this point I have sufficiently answered the
question of Lælius. For in answering him, I, in the first place,
specifically noticed the three simple forms of government—monarchy,
aristocracy, and democracy; and the three vicious constitutions contrary
to them, into which they often degenerate; and I said that none of these
forms, taken separately, was absolutely good; but I described as
preferable to either of them that mixed government which is composed of
a proper amalgamation of these simple ingredients. If I have since
depicted our own Roman constitution as an example, it was not in order
to define the very best form of government, for that may be understood
without an example; but I wished, in the exhibition of a
422mighty
commonwealth actually in existence, to render distinct and visible what
reason and discourse would vainly attempt to display without the
assistance of experimental illustration. Yet, if you still require me to
describe the best form of government, independent of all particular
examples, we must consult that exactly proportioned and graduated image
of government which nature herself presents to her investigators. Since
you *В *В * this model of a city and people
328 *В *В *
XL. *В *В * which I also am searching for, and which I am anxious to
arrive at.
Lælius. You mean the model that would be approved by the truly
accomplished politician?
Scipio. The same.
Lælius. You have plenty of fair patterns even now before you, if you
would but begin with yourself.
Then Scipio said: I wish I could find even one such, even in the entire
senate. For he is really a wise politician who, as we have often seen in
Africa, while seated on a huge and unsightly elephant, can guide and
rule the monster, and turn him whichever way he likes by a slight
admonition, without any actual exertion.
Lælius. I recollect, and when I was your lieutenant I often saw, one
of these drivers.
Scipio. Thus an Indian or Carthaginian regulates one of these huge
animals, and renders him docile and familiar with human manners. But the
genius which resides in the mind of man, by whatever name it may be
called, is required to rein and tame a monster far more multiform and
intractable, whenever it can accomplish it, which indeed is seldom. It
is necessary to hold in with a strong hand that ferocious
329 *В *В *
XLI. *В *В * [beast, denominated the mob, which thirsts after blood] to
such a degree that it can scarcely be sated with the most hideous
massacres of men. *В *В *
But to a man who is greedy, and grasping, and lustful, and fond of
wallowing in voluptuousness.
423The fourth kind of anxiety is that which is prone to mourning and
melancholy, and which is constantly worrying itself.
XLII. *В *В * can be said.
Then Lælius said: I now see the sort of politician you require, on whom
you would impose the office and task of government, which is what I
wished to understand.
He must be an almost unique specimen, said Africanus, for the task which
I set him comprises all others. He must never cease from cultivating and
studying himself, that he may excite others to imitate him, and become,
through the splendor of his talents and enterprises, a living mirror to
his countrymen. For as in flutes and harps, and in all vocal
performances, a certain unison and harmony must be preserved amidst the
distinctive tones, which cannot be broken or violated without offending
experienced ears; and as this concord and delicious harmony is produced
by the exact gradation and modulation of dissimilar notes; even so, by
means of the just apportionment of the highest, middle, and lower
classes, the State is maintained in concord and peace by the harmonic
subordination of its discordant elements: and thus, that which is by
musicians called harmony in song answers and corresponds to what we call
concord in the State—concord, the strongest and loveliest bond of
security in every commonwealth, being always accompanied by justice and
equity.
XLIII. And after this, when Scipio had discussed with considerable
breadth of principle and felicity of illustration the great advantage
that justice is to a state, and the great injury which would arise if it
were
424wanting, Pilus, one of those who were present at the discussion,
took up the matter and demanded that this question should be argued more
carefully, and that something more should be said about justice, on
account of a sentiment that was now obtaining among people in general,
that political affairs could not be wholly carried on without some
disregard of justice.
XLIV. *В *В * to be full of justice.
Then Scipio replied: I certainly think so. And I declare to you that I
consider that all I have spoken respecting the government of the State
is worth nothing, and that it will be useless to proceed further, unless
I can prove that it is a false assertion that political business cannot
be conducted without injustice and corruption; and, on the other hand,
establish as a most indisputable fact that without the strictest justice
no government whatever can last long.
But, with your permission, we have had discussion enough for the day.
The rest—and much remains for our consideration—we will defer till
to-morrow. When they had all agreed to this, the debate of the day was
closed.
INTRODUCTION TO THE THIRD BOOK,
BY THE ORIGINAL TRANSLATOR.
Cicero here enters on the grand question of Political Justice, and
endeavors to evince throughout the absolute verity of that inestimable
proverb, “Honesty is the best policy,” in all public as well as in all
private affairs. St. Augustine, in his City of God, has given the
following analysis of this magnificent disquisition:
“In the third book of Cicero’s Commonwealth” (says he) “the question of
Political Justice is most earnestly discussed. Philus is appointed to
support, as well as he can, the sophistical arguments of those who think
that political government cannot be carried on without the aid of
injustice and chicanery. He denies holding any such opinion himself;
yet, in order to exhibit the truth more vividly through the force of
contrast, he pleads with the utmost ingenuity the cause of injustice
against justice; and endeavors to show, by plausible examples and
specious dialectics, that injustice is as useful to a statesman as
justice would be injurious. Then Lælius, at the general request, takes
up the plea for justice, and maintains with all his eloquence that
nothing could be so ruinous to states as injustice and dishonesty, and
that 425without a supreme justice, no political government could expect a
long duration. This point being sufficiently proved, Scipio returns to
the principal discussion. He reproduces and enforces the short
definition that he had given of a commonwealth—that it consisted in the
welfare of the entire people, by which word �people’ he does not mean
the mob, but the community, bound together by the sense of common rights
and mutual benefits. He notices how important such just definitions are
in all debates whatever, and draws this conclusion from the preceding
arguments—that the Commonwealth is the common welfare whenever it is
swayed with justice and wisdom, whether it be subordinated to a king, an
aristocracy, or a democracy. But if the king be unjust, and so becomes a
tyrant; and the aristocracy unjust, which makes them a faction; or the
democrats unjust, and so degenerate into revolutionists and
destructives—then not only the Commonwealth is corrupted, but in fact
annihilated. For it can be no longer the common welfare when a tyrant or
a faction abuse it; and the people itself is no longer the people when
it becomes unjust, since it is no longer a community associated by a
sense of right and utility, according to the definition.”—Aug. Civ.
Dei. 3-21.
This book is of the utmost importance to statesmen, as it serves to
neutralize the sophistries of Machiavelli, which are still repeated in
many cabinets.
BOOK III.
I. *В *В *
331 Cicero, in the third book of his treatise On a
Commonwealth, says that nature has treated man less like a mother than a
step-dame, for she has cast him into mortal life with a body naked,
fragile, and infirm, and with a mind agitated by troubles, depressed by
fears, broken by labors, and exposed to passions. In this mind, however,
there lies hidden, and, as it were, buried, a certain divine spark of
genius and intellect.
Though man is born a frail and powerless being, nevertheless he is safe
from all animals destitute of voice; and at the same time those other
animals of greater strength, although they bravely endure the violence
of weather, cannot be safe from man. And the result is, that reason does
more for man than nature does for brutes; since, in the latter, neither
the greatness of their strength nor the firmness of their bodies can
save them from being oppressed by us, and made subject to our power. *В *В *
426Plato returned thanks to nature that he had been born a man.
II. *В *В * aiding our slowness by carriages, and when it had taught men
to utter the elementary and confused sounds of unpolished expression,
articulated and distinguished them into their proper classes, and, as
their appropriate signs, attached certain words to certain things, and
thus associated, by the most delightful bond of speech, the once divided
races of men.
And by a similar intelligence, the inflections of the voice, which
appeared infinite, are, by the discovery of a few alphabetic characters,
all designated and expressed; by which we maintain converse with our
absent friends, by which also indications of our wishes and monuments of
past events are preserved. Then came the use of numbers—a thing
necessary to human life, and at the same time immutable and eternal; a
science which first urged us to raise our views to heaven, and not gaze
without an object on the motions of the stars, and the distribution of
days and nights.
III. *В *В *
332 [Then appeared the sages of philosophy], whose minds
took a higher flight, and who were able to conceive and to execute
designs worthy of the gifts of the Gods. Wherefore let those men who
have left us sublime essays on the principles of living be regarded as
great men—which indeed they are—as learned men, as masters of truth
and virtue; provided that these principles of civil government, this
system of governing people, whether it be a thing discovered by men who
have lived amidst a variety of political events, or one discussed amidst
their opportunities of literary tranquillity, is remembered to be, as
indeed it is, a thing by no means to be despised, being one which causes
in first-rate minds, as we not unfrequently see, an incredible and
almost divine virtue. And when to these high faculties of soul, received
from nature and expanded by social institutions, a politician adds
learning and extensive information concerning things in general, like
those illustrious personages who conduct the dialogue in the present
treatise, none will refuse to confess the superiority of such persons to
all others; for, in fact, what
427can be more admirable than the study and
practice of the grand affairs of state, united to a literary taste and a
familiarity with the liberal arts? or what can we imagine more perfect
than a Scipio, a Lælius, or a Philus, who, not to omit anything which
belonged to the most perfect excellence of the greatest men, joined to
the examples of our ancestors and the traditions of our countrymen the
foreign philosophy of Socrates?
Wherefore he who had both the desire and the power to acquaint himself
thoroughly both with the customs and the learning of his ancestors
appears to me to have attained to the very highest glory and honor. But
if we cannot combine both, and are compelled to select one of these two
paths to wisdom—though to some people the tranquil life spent in the
research of literature and arts may appear to be the most happy and
delectable—yet, doubtless, the science of politics is more laudable and
illustrious, for in this political field of exertion our greatest men
have reaped their honors, like the invincible Curius,
Whom neither gold nor iron could subdue.
IV. *В *В *
333 that wisdom existed still. There existed this general
difference between these two classes, that among the one the development
of the principles of nature is the subject of their study and eloquence,
and among the other national laws and institutions form the principal
topics of investigation.
In honor of our country, we may assert that she has produced within
herself a great number, I will not say of sages (since philosophy is so
jealous of this name), but of men worthy of the highest celebrity,
because by them the precepts and discoveries of the sages have been
carried out into actual practice. And, moreover, though there have
existed, and still do exist, many great and glorious empires, yet since
the noblest masterpiece of genius in the world is the establishment of a
state and commonwealth which shall be a lasting one, even if we reckon
but a single legislator for each empire, the number of these excellent
men will appear very numerous. To be convinced of this, we have only to
turn our eyes on any nation of Italy, Latium, the
428Sabines, the
Volscians, the Samnites, or the Etrurians, and then direct our attention
to that mighty nation of the Greeks, and then to the Assyrians,
Persians, and Carthaginians, and
334 *В *В *
V. *В *В * [Scipio and his friends having again assembled, Scipio spoke as
follows: In our last conversation, I promised to prove that honesty is
the best policy in all states and commonwealths whatsoever. But if I am
to plead in favor of strict honesty and justice in all public affairs,
no less than in private, I must request Philus, or some one else, to
take up the advocacy of the other side; the truth will then become more
manifest, from the collision of opposite arguments, as we see every day
exemplified at the Bar.]
And Philus replied: In good truth, you have allotted me a very
creditable cause when you wish me to undertake the defence of vice.
Perhaps, said Lælius, you are afraid, lest, in reproducing the ordinary
objections made to justice in politics, you should seem to express your
own sentiments; though you are universally respected as an almost unique
example of the ancient probity and good faith; nor is it unknown how
familiar you are with the lawyer-like habit of disputing on both sides
of a question, because you think that this is the best way of getting at
the truth.
And Philus said: Very well; I obey you, and wilfully, with my eyes open,
I will undertake this dirty business; because, since those who seek for
gold do not flinch at the sight of the mud, so we who are searching for
justice, which is far more precious than gold, are bound to shrink from
no annoyance. And I wish, as I am about to make use of the antagonist
arguments of a foreigner, I might also employ a foreign language. The
pleas, therefore, now to be urged by Lucius Furius Philus are those
[once employed by] the Greek Carneades, a man who was accustomed to
express whatever [served his turn].
335 *В *В *
336429Let it be understood,
therefore, that I by no means express my own sentiments, but those of
Carneades, in order that you may refute this philosopher, who was wont
to turn the best causes into joke, through the mere wantonness of wit.
VI. He was a philosopher of the Academic School; and if any one is
ignorant of his great power, and eloquence, and acuteness in
arguing, he may learn it from the mention made of him by Cicero or
by Lucilius, when Neptune, discoursing on a very difficult subject,
declares that it cannot be explained, not even if hell were to
restore Carneades himself for the purpose. This philosopher, having
been sent by the Athenians to Rome as an ambassador, discussed the
subject of justice very amply in the hearing of Galba and Cato the
Censor, who were the greatest orators of the day. And the next day
he overturned all his arguments by others of a contrary tendency,
and disparaged justice, which the day before he had extolled;
speaking not indeed with the gravity of a philosopher whose wisdom
ought to be steady, and whose opinions unchangeable, but in a kind
of rhetorical exercise of arguing on each side—a practice which he
was accustomed to adopt, in order to be able to refute others who
were asserting anything. The arguments by which he disparaged
justice are mentioned by Lucius Furius in Cicero; I suppose, since
he was discussing the Commonwealth, in order to introduce a defence
and panegyric of that quality without which he did not think a
commonwealth could be administered. But Carneades, in order to
refute Aristotle and Plato, the advocates of justice, collected in
his first argument everything that was in the habit of being
advanced on behalf of justice, in order afterward to be able to
overturn it, as he did.
VII. Many philosophers indeed, and especially Plato and Aristotle,
have spoken a great deal of justice, inculcating that virtue, and
extolling it with the highest praise, as giving to every one what
belongs to him, as preserving equity in all things, and urging that
while the other virtues are, as it were, silent and shut up,
justice is the only one which
430is not absorbed in considerations of
self-interest, and which is not secret, but finds its whole field
for exercise out-of-doors, and is desirous of doing good and
serving as many people as possible; as if, forsooth, justice ought
to exist in judges only, and in men invested with a certain
authority, and not in every one! But there is no one, not even a
man of the lowest class, or a beggar, who is destitute of
opportunities of displaying justice. But because these philosophers
knew not what its essence was, or whence it proceeded, or what its
employment was, they attributed that first of all virtues, which is
the common good of all men, to a few only, and asserted that it
aimed at no advantage of its own, but was anxious only for that of
others. So it was well that Carneades, a man of the greatest genius
and acuteness, refuted their assertions, and overthrew that justice
which had no firm foundation; not because he thought justice itself
deserving of blame, but in order to show that those its defenders
had brought forward no trustworthy or strong arguments in its
behalf.
Justice looks out-of-doors, and is prominent and conspicuous in its
whole essence.
Which virtue, beyond all others, wholly devotes and dedicates
itself to the advantage of others.
VIII. *В *В * Both to discover and maintain. While the other, Aristotle,
has filled four large volumes with a discussion on abstract justice. For
I did not expect anything grand or magnificent from Chrysippus, who,
after his usual fashion, examines everything rather by the signification
of words than the reality of things. But it was surely worthy of those
heroes of philosophy to ennoble by their genius a virtue so eminently
beneficent and liberal, which everywhere exalts the social interests
above the selfish, and teaches us to love others rather than ourselves.
It was worthy of their genius, we say, to elevate this virtue to a
divine throne, not far from that of Wisdom. And certainly they neither
wanted the will to accomplish this (for what else could be the cause of
their writing on the subject, or what could have been their design?) nor
the genius, in which they excelled all men. But the weakness of their
cause was too great for either their intention or their eloquence to
make it popular. In fact, this justice on which we reason is a civil
right, but no natural one; for if it were natural and universal, then
justice and injustice would be recognized similarly by all men, just as
the heat and cold, sweetness and bitterness.
IX. Now, if any one, carried in that chariot of winged serpents of which
the poet Pacuvius makes mention, could
431take his flight over all nations
and cities, and accurately observe their proceedings, he would see that
the sense of justice and right varies in different regions. In the first
place, he would behold among the unchangeable people of Egypt, which
preserves in its archives the memory of so many ages and events, a bull
adored as a Deity, under the name of Apis, and a multitude of other
monsters, and all kinds of animals admitted by the same nation into the
number of the Gods.
In the next place, he would see in Greece, as among ourselves,
magnificent temples consecrated by images in human form, which the
Persians regarded as impious; and it is affirmed that the sole motive of
Xerxes for commanding the conflagration of the Athenian temples was the
belief that it was a superstitious sacrilege to keep confined within
narrow walls the Gods, whose proper home was the entire universe. But
afterward Philip, in his hostile projects against the Persians, and
Alexander, who carried them into execution, alleged this plea for war,
that they were desirous to avenge the temples of Greece, which the
Greeks had thought proper never to rebuild, that this monument of the
impiety of the Persians might always remain before the eyes of their
posterity.
How many—such as the inhabitants of Taurica along the Euxine Sea; as
the King of Egypt, Busiris; as the Gauls and the Carthaginians—have
thought it exceedingly pious and agreeable to the Gods to sacrifice men!
And, besides, the customs of life are so various that the Cretans and
Ætolians regard robbery as honorable. And the Lacedæmonians say that
their territory extends to all places which they can touch with a lance.
The Athenians had a custom of swearing, by a public proclamation, that
all the lands which produced olives and corn were their own. The Gauls
consider it a base employment to raise corn by agricultural labor, and
go with arms in their hands, and mow down the harvests of neighboring
peoples. But we ourselves, the most equitable of all nations, who, in
order to raise the value of our vines and olives, do not permit the
races beyond the Alps to cultivate either vineyards or oliveyards, are
said in this matter to act with prudence, but not with justice. You see,
then, that wisdom
432and policy are not always the same as equity. And
Lycurgus, that famous inventor of a most admirable jurisprudence and
most wholesome laws, gave the lands of the rich to be cultivated by the
common people, who were reduced to slavery.
X. If I were to describe the diverse kinds of laws, institutions,
manners, and customs, not only as they vary in the numerous nations, but
as they vary likewise in single cities—in this one of ours, for
example—I could prove that they have had a thousand revolutions. For
instance, that eminent expositor of our laws who sits in the present
company—I mean Manilius—if you were to consult him relative to the
legacies and inheritances of women, he would tell you that the present
law is quite different from that he was accustomed to plead in his
youth, before the Voconian enactment came into force—an edict which was
passed in favor of the interests of the men, but which is evidently full
of injustice with regard to women. For why should a woman be disabled
from inheriting property? Why can a vestal virgin become an heir, while
her mother cannot? And why, admitting that it is necessary to set some
limit to the wealth of women, should Crassus’s daughter, if she be his
only child, inherit thousands without offending the law, while my
daughter can only receive a small share in a bequest.
337 *В *В *
XI. *В *В * [If this justice were natural, innate, and universal, all men
would admit the same] law and right, and the same men would not enact
different laws at different times. If a just man and a virtuous man is
bound to obey the laws, I ask, what laws do you mean? Do you intend all
the laws indifferently? But neither does virtue permit this inconstancy
in moral obligation, nor is such a variation compatible with natural
conscience. The laws are, therefore, based not on our sense of justice,
but on our fear of punishment. There is, therefore, no natural justice;
and hence it follows that men cannot be just by nature.
Are men, then, to say that variations indeed do exist in the laws, but
that men who are virtuous through natural conscience follow that which
is really justice, and not a mere semblance and disguise, and that it is
the distinguishing
433characteristic of the truly just and virtuous man to
render every one his due rights? Are we, then, to attribute the first of
these characteristics to animals? For not only men of moderate
abilities, but even first-rate sages and philosophers, as Pythagoras and
Empedocles, declare that all kinds of living creatures have a right to
the same justice. They declare that inexpiable penalties impend over
those who have done violence to any animal whatsoever. It is, therefore,
a crime to injure an animal, and the perpetrator of such crime
338 *В *В *
XII. For when he
339 inquired of a pirate by what right he dared
to infest the sea with his little brigantine: “By the same right,”
he replied, “which is your warrant for conquering the world.” * * *
Wisdom and prudence instruct us by all means to increase our power,
riches, and estates. For by what means could this same Alexander, that
illustrious general, who extended his empire over all Asia, without
violating the property of other men, have acquired such universal
dominion, enjoyed so many pleasures, such great power, and reigned
without bound or limit?
But justice commands us to have mercy upon all men, to consult the
interests of the whole human race, to give to every one his due, and
injure no sacred, public, or foreign rights, and to forbear touching
what does not belong to us. What is the result, then? If you obey the
dictates of wisdom, then wealth, power, riches, honors, provinces, and
kingdoms, from all classes, peoples, and nations, are to be aimed at.
However, as we are discussing public matters, those examples are more
illustrious which refer to what is done publicly. And since the question
between justice and policy applies equally to private and public
affairs, I think it well to speak of the wisdom of the people. I will
not, however, mention other nations, but come at once to our own Roman
people, whom Africanus, in his discourse yesterday, traced from the
cradle, and whose empire now embraces the whole world. Justice is
340 *В *В *
434XIII. How far utility is at variance with justice we may learn from
the Roman people itself, which, declaring war by means of the
fecials, and committing injustice with all legal formality, always
coveting and laying violent hands on the property of others,
acquired the possession of the whole world.
What is the advantage of one’s own country but the disadvantage of
another state or nation, by extending one’s dominions by
territories evidently wrested from others, increasing one’s power,
improving one’s revenues, etc.? Therefore, whoever has obtained
these advantages for his country—that is to say, whoever has
overthrown cities, subdued nations, and by these means filled the
treasury with money, taken lands, and enriched his
fellow-citizens—such a man is extolled to the skies; is believed
to be endowed with consummate and perfect virtue; and this mistake
is fallen into not only by the populace and the ignorant, but by
philosophers, who even give rules for injustice.
XIV. *В *В * For all those who have the right of life and death over the
people are in fact tyrants; but they prefer being called by the title of
king, which belongs to the all-good Jupiter. But when certain men, by
favor of wealth, birth, or any other means, get possession of the entire
government, it is a faction; but they choose to denominate themselves an
aristocracy. If the people gets the upper hand, and rules everything
after its capricious will, they call it liberty, but it is in fact
license. And when every man is a guard upon his neighbor, and every
class is a guard upon every other class, then because no one trusts in
his own strength, a kind of compact is formed between the great and the
little, from whence arises that mixed kind of government which Scipio
has been commending. Thus justice, according to these facts, is not the
daughter of nature or conscience, but of human imbecility. For when it
becomes necessary to choose between these three predicaments, either to
do wrong without retribution, or to do wrong with retribution, or to do
no wrong at all, it is best to do wrong with impunity; next, neither to
do wrong nor to suffer for it; but nothing is more wretched than to
struggle incessantly between the wrong we inflict and that we receive.
Therefore, he who attains to that first end
341 *В *В *
XV. This was the sum of the argument of Carneades: that men had
established laws among themselves from considerations of advantage,
435varying them according to their different customs, and altering
them often so as to adapt them to the times; but that there was no
such thing as natural law; that all men and all other animals are
led to their own advantage by the guidance of nature; that there is
no such thing as justice, or, if there be, that it is extreme
folly, since a man would injure himself while consulting the
interests of others. And he added these arguments, that all nations
who were flourishing and dominant, and even the Romans themselves,
who were the masters of the whole world, if they wished to be
just—that is to say, if they restored all that belonged to
others—would have to return to their cottages, and to lie down in
want and misery.
Except, perhaps, of the Arcadians and Athenians, who, I presume,
dreading that this great act of retribution might one day arrive,
pretend that they were sprung from the earth, like so many field-mice.
XVI. In reply to these statements, the following arguments are often
adduced by those who are not unskilful in discussions, and who, in this
question, have all the greater weight of authority, because, when we
inquire, Who is a good man?—understanding by that term a frank and
single-minded man—we have little need of captious casuists, quibblers,
and slanderers. For those men assert that the wise man does not seek
virtue because of the personal gratification which the practice of
justice and beneficence procures him, but rather because the life of the
good man is free from fear, care, solicitude, and peril; while, on the
other hand, the wicked always feel in their souls a certain suspicion,
and always behold before their eyes images of judgment and punishment.
Do not you think, therefore, that there is any benefit, or that there is
any advantage which can be procured by injustice, precious enough to
counterbalance the constant pressure of remorse, and the haunting
consciousness that retribution awaits the sinner, and hangs over his
devoted head.
342 *В *В *
XVII. [Our philosophers, therefore, put a case. Suppose, say they, two
men, one of whom is an excellent and admirable person, of high honor and
remarkable integrity; the latter is distinguished by nothing but his
vice and audacity. And suppose that their city has so mistaken their
characters as to imagine the good man to be a scandalous, impious, and
audacious criminal, and to esteem the wicked
436man, on the contrary, as a
pattern of probity and fidelity. On account of this error of their
fellow-citizens, the good man is arrested and tormented, his hands are
cut off, his eyes are plucked out, he is condemned, bound, burned,
exterminated, reduced to want, and to the last appears to all men to be
most deservedly the most miserable of men. On the other hand, the
flagitious wretch is exalted, worshipped, loved by all, and honors,
offices, riches, and emoluments are all conferred on him, and he shall
be reckoned by his fellow-citizens the best and worthiest of mortals,
and in the highest degree deserving of all manner of prosperity. Yet,
for all this, who is so mad as to doubt which of these two men he would
rather be?
XVIII. What happens among individuals happens also among nations. There
is no state so absurd and ridiculous as not to prefer unjust dominion to
just subordination. I need not go far for examples. During my own
consulship, when you were my fellow-counsellors, we consulted respecting
the treaty of Numantia. No one was ignorant that Quintus Pompey had
signed a treaty, and that Mancinus had done the same. The latter, being
a virtuous man, supported the proposition which I laid before the
people, after the decree of the senate. The former, on the other side,
opposed it vehemently. If modesty, probity, or faith had been regarded,
Mancinus would have carried his point; but in reason, counsel, and
prudence, Pompey surpassed him. Whether
343 *В *В *
XIX. If a man should have a faithless slave, or an unwholesome house,
with whose defect he alone was acquainted, and he advertised them for
sale, would he state the fact that his servant was infected with
knavery, and his house with malaria, or would he conceal these
objections from the buyer? If he stated those facts, he would be honest,
no doubt, because he would deceive nobody; but still he would be thought
a fool, because he would either get very little for his property, or
else fail to sell it at all. By concealing these defects, on the other
hand, he will be called a shrewd man—as one who has taken care of his
own interest; but he will be a rogue, notwithstanding, because he will
be deceiving his neighbors. Again,
437let us suppose that one man meets
another, who sells gold and silver, conceiving them to be copper or
lead; shall he hold his peace that he may make a capital bargain, or
correct the mistake, and purchase at a fair rate? He would evidently be
a fool in the world’s opinion if he preferred the latter.
XX. It is justice, beyond all question, neither to commit murder nor
robbery. What, then, would your just man do, if, in a case of shipwreck,
he saw a weaker man than himself get possession of a plank? Would he not
thrust him off, get hold of the timber himself, and escape by his
exertions, especially as no human witness could be present in the
mid-sea? If he acted like a wise man of the world, he would certainly do
so, for to act in any other way would cost him his life. If, on the
other hand, he prefers death to inflicting unjustifiable injury on his
neighbor, he will be an eminently honorable and just man, but not the
less a fool, because he saved another’s life at the expense of his own.
Again, if in case of a defeat and rout, when the enemy were pressing in
the rear, this just man should find a wounded comrade mounted on a
horse, shall he respect his right at the risk of being killed himself,
or shall he fling him from the horse in order to preserve his own life
from the pursuers? If he does so, he is a wise man, but at the same time
a wicked one; if he does not, he is admirably just, but at the same time
stupid.
XXI.
Scipio. I might reply at great length to these sophistical
objections of Philus, if it were not, my Lælius, that all our friends
are no less anxious than myself to hear you take a leading part in the
present debate, especially as you promised yesterday that you would
plead at large on my side of the argument. If you cannot spare time for
this, at any rate do not desert us; we all ask it of you.
Lælius. This Carneades ought not to be even listened to by our young
men. I think all the while that I am hearing him that he must be a very
impure person; if he be not, as I would fain believe, his discourse is
not less pernicious.
XXII.
344 True law is right reason conformable to nature,
438universal,
unchangeable, eternal, whose commands urge us to duty, and whose
prohibitions restrain us from evil. Whether it enjoins or forbids, the
good respect its injunctions, and the wicked treat them with
indifference. This law cannot be contradicted by any other law, and is
not liable either to derogation or abrogation. Neither the senate nor
the people can give us any dispensation for not obeying this universal
law of justice. It needs no other expositor and interpreter than our own
conscience. It is not one thing at Rome, and another at Athens; one
thing to-day, and another to-morrow; but in all times and nations this
universal law must forever reign, eternal and imperishable. It is the
sovereign master and emperor of all beings. God himself is its author,
its promulgator, its enforcer. And he who does not obey it flies from
himself, and does violence to the very nature of man. And by so doing he
will endure the severest penalties even if he avoid the other evils
which are usually accounted punishments.
XXIII. I am aware that in the third book of Cicero’s treatise on
the Commonwealth (unless I am mistaken) it is argued that no war is
ever undertaken by a well-regulated commonwealth unless it be one
either for the sake of keeping faith, or for safety; and what he
means by a war for safety, and what safety he wishes us to
understand, he points out in another passage, where he says, “But
private men often escape from these penalties, which even the most
stupid persons feel—want, exile, imprisonment, and stripes—by
embracing the opportunity of a speedy death; but to states death
itself is a penalty, though it appears to deliver individuals from
punishment. For a state ought to be established so as to be
eternal: therefore, there is no natural decease for a state, as
there is for a man, in whose case death is not only inevitable, but
often even desirable; but when a state is put an end to, it is
destroyed, extinguished. It is in some degree, to compare small
things with great, as if this whole world were to perish and fall
to pieces.”
In his treatise on the Commonwealth, Cicero says those wars are
unjust which are undertaken without reason. Again, after a few
sentences, he adds, No war is considered just unless it be formally
announced and declared, and unless it be to obtain restitution of
what has been taken away.
But our nation, by defending its allies, has now become the master
of all the whole world.
XXIV. Also, in that same treatise on the Commonwealth, he argues
most strenuously and vigorously in the cause of justice against
injustice. And since, when a little time before the part of
injustice was upheld against justice, and the doctrine was urged
that a republic could not
439prosper and flourish except by
injustice, this was put forward as the strongest argument, that it
was unjust for men to serve other men as their masters; but that
unless a dominant state, such as a great republic, acted on this
injustice, it could not govern its provinces; answer was made on
behalf of justice, that it was just that it should be so, because
slavery is advantageous to such men, and their interests are
consulted by a right course of conduct—that is, by the license of
doing injury being taken from the wicked—and they will fare better
when subjugated, because when not subjugated they fared worse: and
to confirm this reasoning, a noble instance, taken, as it were,
from nature, was added, and it was said, Why, then, does God govern
man, and why does the mind govern the body, and reason govern lust,
and the other vicious parts of the mind?
XXV. Hear what Tully says more plainly still in the third book of
his treatise on the Commonwealth, when discussing the reasons for
government. Do we not, says he, see that nature herself has given
the power of dominion to everything that is best, to the extreme
advantage of what is subjected to it? Why, then, does God govern
man, and why does the mind govern the body, and reason govern lust
and passion and the other vicious parts of the same mind? Listen
thus far; for presently he adds, But still there are
dissimilarities to be recognized in governing and in obeying. For
as the mind is said to govern the body, and also to govern lust,
still it governs the body as a king governs his subjects, or a
parent his children; but it governs lust as a master governs his
slaves, because it restrains and breaks it. The authority of kings,
of generals, of magistrates, of fathers, and of nations, rules
their subjects and allies as the mind rules bodies; but masters
control their slaves, as the best part of the mind—that is to say,
wisdom—controls the vicious and weak parts of itself, such as
lust, passion, and the other perturbations.
For there is a kind of unjust slavery when those belong to some one
else who might be their own masters; but when those are slaves who
cannot govern themselves, there is no injury done.
XXVI. If, says Carneades, you were to know that an asp was lying
hidden anywhere, and that some one who did not know it was going to
sit upon it, whose death would be a gain to you, you would act
wickedly if you did not warn him not to sit down. Still, you would
not be liable to punishment; for who could prove that you had
known? But we are bringing forward too many instances; for it is
plain that unless equity, good faith, and justice proceed from
nature, and if all these things are referred to interest, a good
man cannot be found. And on these topics a great deal is said by
Lælius in our treatise on the Republic.
If, as we are reminded by you, we have spoken well in that
treatise, when we said that nothing is good excepting what is
honorable, and nothing bad excepting what is disgraceful. *В *В *
XXVII. I am glad that you approve of the doctrine that the
affection borne to our children is implanted by nature; indeed, if
it be not, there can be no conection between man and man which has
its origin in nature. And if there be not, then there is an end of
all society in life. May it turn out well, says Carneades, speaking
shamelessly, but still
440more sensibly than my friend Lucius or
Patro: for, as they refer everything to themselves, do they think
that anything is ever done for the sake of another? And when they
say that a man ought to be good, in order to avoid misfortune, not
because it is right by nature, they do not perceive that they are
speaking of a cunning man, not of a good one. But these arguments
are argued, I think, in those books by praising which you have
given me spirits.
In which I agree that an anxious and hazardous justice is not that
of a wise man.
XXVIII. And again, in Cicero, that same advocate of justice,
Lælius, says, Virtue is clearly eager for honor, nor has she any
other reward; which, however, she accepts easily, and exacts
without bitterness. And in another place the same Lælius says:
When a man is inspired by virtue such as this, what bribes can you offer
him, what treasures, what thrones, what empires? He considers these but
mortal goods, and esteems his own divine. And if the ingratitude of the
people, and the envy of his competitors, or the violence of powerful
enemies, despoil his virtue of its earthly recompense, he still enjoys a
thousand consolations in the approbation of conscience, and sustains
himself by contemplating the beauty of moral rectitude.
XXIX. *В *В * This virtue, in order to be true, must be universal.
Tiberius Gracchus continued faithful to his fellow-citizens, but he
violated the rights and treaties guaranteed to our allies and the Latin
peoples. But if this habit of arbitrary violence begins to extend itself
further, and perverts our authority, leading it from right to violence,
so that those who had voluntarily obeyed us are only restrained by fear,
then, although we, during our days, may escape the peril, yet am I
solicitous respecting the safety of our posterity and the immortality of
the Commonwealth itself, which, doubtless, might become perpetual and
invincible if our people would maintain their ancient institutions and
manners.
XXX. When Lælius had ceased to speak, all those that were present
expressed the extreme pleasure they found in his discourse. But Scipio,
more affected than the rest, and ravished with the delight of sympathy,
exclaimed: You have pleaded, my Lælius, many causes with an eloquence
superior to that of Servius Galba, our colleague, whom you used during
his life to prefer to all others, even to the Attic orators [and never
did I hear you speak with
441more energy than to-day, while pleading the
cause of justice]
345 *В *В *
*В *В * That two things were wanting to enable him to speak in public
and in the forum, confidence and voice.
XXXI. *В *В * This justice, continued Scipio, is the very foundation of
lawful government in political constitutions. Can we call the State of
Agrigentum a commonwealth, where all men are oppressed by the cruelty of
a single tyrant—where there is no universal bond of right, nor social
consent and fellowship, which should belong to every people, properly so
named? It is the same in Syracuse—that illustrious city which Timæus
calls the greatest of the Grecian towns. It was indeed a most beautiful
city; and its admirable citadel, its canals distributed through all its
districts, its broad streets, its porticoes, its temples, and its walls,
gave Syracuse the appearance of a most flourishing state. But while
Dionysius its tyrant reigned there, nothing of all its wealth belonged
to the people, and the people were nothing better than the slaves of one
master. Thus, wherever I behold a tyrant, I know that the social
constitution must be not merely vicious and corrupt, as I stated
yesterday, but in strict truth no social constitution at all.
XXXII.
Lælius. You have spoken admirably, my Scipio, and I see the
point of your observations.
Scipio. You grant, then, that a state which is entirely in the power
of a faction cannot justly be entitled a political community?
Lælius. That is evident.
Scipio. You judge most correctly. For what was the State of Athens
when, during the great Peloponnesian war, she fell under the unjust
domination of the thirty tyrants? The antique glory of that city, the
imposing aspect of its edifices, its theatre, its gymnasium, its
porticoes, its temples, its citadel, the admirable sculptures of
Phidias, and the magnificent harbor of Piræus—did they constitute it a
commonwealth?
Lælius. Certainly not, because these did not constitute the real
welfare of the community.
442Scipio. And at Rome, when the decemvirs ruled without appeal from
their decisions, in the third year of their power, had not liberty lost
all its securities and all its blessings?
Lælius. Yes; the welfare of the community was no longer consulted, and
the people soon roused themselves, and recovered their appropriate
rights.
XXXIII.
Scipio. I now come to the third, or democratical, form of
government, in which a considerable difficulty presents itself, because
all things are there said to lie at the disposition of the people, and
are carried into execution just as they please. Here the populace
inflict punishments at their pleasure, and act, and seize, and keep
possession, and distribute property, without let or hinderance. Can you
deny, my Lælius, that this is a fair definition of a democracy, where
the people are all in all, and where the people constitute the State?
Lælius. There is no political constitution to which I more absolutely
deny the name of a
commonwealth than that in which all things lie in
the power of the multitude. If a commonwealth, which implies the welfare
of the entire community, could not exist in Agrigentum, Syracuse, or
Athens when tyrants reigned over them—if it could not exist in Rome
when under the oligarchy of the decemvirs—neither do I see how this
sacred name of commonwealth can be applied to a democracy and the sway
of the mob; because, in the first place, my Scipio, I build on your own
admirable definition, that there can be no community, properly so
called, unless it be regulated by a combination of rights. And, by this
definition, it appears that a multitude of men may be just as tyrannical
as a single despot; and it is so much the worse, since no monster can be
more barbarous than the mob, which assumes the name and appearance of
the people. Nor is it at all reasonable, since the laws place the
property of madmen in the hands of their sane relations, that we should
do the [very reverse in politics, and throw the property of the sane
into the hands of the mad multitude]
346 *В *В *
XXXIV. *В *В * [It is far more rational] to assert that a wise and
virtuous aristocratical government deserves
443the title of a
commonwealth, as it approaches to the nature of a kingdom.
And much more so in my opinion, said Mummius. For the unity of power
often exposes a king to become a despot; but when an aristocracy,
consisting of many virtuous men, exercise power, that is the most
fortunate circumstance possible for any state. However this be, I much
prefer royalty to democracy; for that is the third kind of government
which you have remaining, and a most vicious one it is.
XXXV. Scipio replied: I am well acquainted, my Mummius, with your
decided antipathy to the democratical system. And, although, we may
speak of it with rather more indulgence than you are accustomed to
accord it, I must certainly agree with you, that of all the three
particular forms of government, none is less commendable than democracy.
I do not agree with you, however, when you would imply that aristocracy
is preferable to royalty. If you suppose that wisdom governs the State,
is it not as well that this wisdom should reside in one monarch as in
many nobles?
But we are led away by a certain incorrectness of terms in a discussion
like the present. When we pronounce the word “aristocracy,” which, in
Greek, signifies the government of the best men, what can be conceived
more excellent? For what can be thought better than the best? But when,
on the other hand, the title “king” is mentioned, we begin to imagine a
tyrant; as if a king must be necessarily unjust. But we are not speaking
of an unjust king when we are examining the true nature of royal
authority. To this name of king, therefore, do but attach the idea of a
Romulus, a Numa, a Tullus, and perhaps you will be less severe to the
monarchical form of constitution.
Mummius. Have you, then, no commendation at all for any kind of
democratical government?
Scipio. Why, I think some democratical forms less objectionable than
others; and, by way of illustration, I will ask you what you thought of
the government in the isle of Rhodes, where we were lately together; did
it appear to you a legitimate and rational constitution?
444Mummius. It did, and not much liable to abuse.
Scipio. You say truly. But, if you recollect, it was a very
extraordinary experiment. All the inhabitants were alternately senators
and citizens. Some months they spent in their senatorial functions, and
some months they spent in their civil employments. In both they
exercised judicial powers; and in the theatre and the court, the same
men judged all causes, capital and not capital. And they had as much
influence, and were of as much importance as *В *В *
FRAGMENTS.
XXXVI. There is therefore some unquiet feeling in individuals,
which either exults in pleasure or is crushed by annoyance.
No war can be undertaken by a just and wise state unless for faith or
self-defence. This self-defence of the State is enough to insure its
perpetuity, and this perpetuity is what all patriots desire. Those
afflictions which even the hardiest spirits smart under—poverty, exile,
prison, and torment—private individuals seek to escape from by an
instantaneous death. But for states, the greatest calamity of all is
that of death, which to individuals appears a refuge. A state should be
so constituted as to live forever. For a commonwealth there is no
natural dissolution as there is for a man, to whom death not only
becomes necessary, but often desirable. And when a state once decays and
falls, it is so utterly revolutionized, that, if we may compare great
things with small, it resembles the final wreck of the universe.
All wars undertaken without a proper motive are unjust. And no war can
be reputed just unless it be duly announced and proclaimed, and if it be
not preceded by a rational demand for restitution.
Our Roman Commonwealth, by defending its allies, has got possession of
the world.
446INTRODUCTION TO THE FOURTH BOOK,
BY THE ORIGINAL TRANSLATOR.
In this fourth book Cicero treats of morals and education, and the
use and abuse of stage entertainments. We retain nothing of this
important book save a few scattered fragments, the beauty of which
fills us with the greater regret for the passages we have lost.
BOOK IV.
FRAGMENTS.
I. *В *В * Since mention has been made of the body and of the mind, I
will endeavor to explain the theory of each as well as the weakness
of my understanding is able to comprehend it—a duty which I think
it the more becoming in me to undertake, because Marcus Tullius, a
man of singular genius, after having attempted to perform it in the
fourth book of his treatise on the Commonwealth, compressed a
subject of wide extent within narrow limits, only touching lightly
on all the principal points. And that there might be no excuse
alleged for his not having followed out this topic, he himself has
assured us that he was not wanting either in inclination or in
anxiety to do so; for, in the first book of his treatise on Laws,
when he was touching briefly on the same subject, he speaks thus:
“This topic Scipio, in my opinion, has sufficiently discussed in
those books which you have read.”
And the mind itself, which sees the future, remembers the past.
Well did Marcus Tullius say, In truth, if there is no one who would
not prefer death to being changed into the form of some beast,
although he were still to retain the mind of a man, how much more
wretched is it to have the mind of a beast in the form of a man! To
me this fate appears as much worse than the other as the mind is
superior to the body.
Tullius says somewhere that he does not think the good of a ram and
of Publius Africanus identical.
And also by its being interposed, it causes shade and night, which
is adapted both to the numbering of days and to rest from labor.
And as in the autumn he has opened the earth to receive seeds, in
winter relaxed it that it may digest them, and by the ripening
powers of summer softened some and burned up others.
When the shepherds use *В *В * for cattle.
Cicero, in the fourth book of his Commonwealth, uses the word
“armentum,” and “armentarius,” derived from it.
447II. The great law of just and regular subordination is the basis of
political prosperity. There is much advantage in the harmonious
succession of ranks and orders and classes, in which the suffrages of
the knights and the senators have their due weight. Too many have
foolishly desired to destroy this institution, in the vain hope of
receiving some new largess, by a public decree, out of a distribution of
the property of the nobility.
III. Consider, now, how wisely the other provisions have been adopted,
in order to secure to the citizens the benefits of an honest and happy
life; for that is, indeed, the grand object of all political
association, and that which every government should endeavor to procure
for the people, partly by its institutions, and partly by its laws.
Consider, in the first place, the national education of the people—a
matter on which the Greeks have expended much labor in vain, and which
is the only point on which Polybius, who settled among us, accuses the
negligence of our institutions. For our countrymen have thought that
education ought not to be fixed, nor regulated by laws, nor be given
publicly and uniformly to all classes of society. For
347 *В *В *
According to Tully, who says that men going to serve in the army
have guardians assigned to them, by whom they are governed the
first year.
IV. [In our ancient laws, young men were prohibited from appearing]
naked in the public baths, so far back were the principles of modesty
traced by our ancestors. Among the Greeks, on the contrary, what an
absurd system of training youth is exhibited in their gymnasia! What a
frivolous preparation for the labors and hazards of war! what indecent
spectacles, what impure and licentious amours are permitted! I do not
speak only of the Eleans and Thebans, among whom, in all love affairs,
passion is allowed to run into shameless excesses; but the Spartans,
while they permit every kind of license to their young men, save that of
violation, fence off, by a very slight wall, the very exception on which
they insist, besides other crimes which I will not mention.
448Then Lælius said: I see, my Scipio, that on the subject of the Greek
institutions, which you censure, you prefer attacking the customs of the
most renowned peoples to contending with your favorite Plato, whose name
you have avoided citing, especially as * * *
V. So that Cicero, in his treatise on the Commonwealth, says that
it was a reproach to young men if they had no lovers.
Not only as at Sparta, where boys learn to steal and plunder.
And our master Plato, even more than Lycurgus, who would have
everything to be common, so that no one should be able to call
anything his own property.
I would send him to the same place whither he sends Homer, crowned
with chaplets and anointed with perfumes, banishing him from the
city which he is describing.
VI. The judgment of the censor inflicts scarcely anything more than
a blush on the man whom he condemns. Therefore as all that
adjudication turns solely on the name (
nomen), the punishment is
called ignominy.
Nor should a prefect be set over women, an officer who is created
among the Greeks; but there should be a censor to teach husbands to
manage their wives.
So the discipline of modesty has great power. All women abstain
from wine.
And also if any woman was of bad character, her relations used not
to kiss her.
So petulance is derived from asking (
petendo); wantonness
(
procacitas) from
procando, that is, from demanding.
VII. For I do not approve of the same nation being the ruler and
the farmer of lands. But both in private families and in the
affairs of the Commonwealth I look upon economy as a revenue.
Faith (
fides) appears to me to derive its name from that being
done (
fit) which is said.
In a citizen of rank and noble birth, caressing manners, display,
and ambition are marks of levity.
Examine for a while the books on the Republic, and learn that good
men know no bound or limit in consulting the interests of their
country. See in that treatise with what praises frugality, and
continency, and fidelity to the marriage tie, and chaste,
honorable, and virtuous manners are extolled.
VIII. I marvel at the elegant choice, not only of the facts, but of
the language. If they dispute (
jurgant). It is a contest between
well-wishers, not a quarrel between enemies, that is called a
dispute (
jurgium),
Therefore the law considers that neighbors dispute (
jurgare)
rather than quarrel (
litigare) with one another.
The bounds of man’s care and of man’s life are the same; so by the
pontifical law the sanctity of burial * * *
They put them to death, though innocent, because they had left
those men unburied whom they could not rescue from the sea because
of the violence of the storm.
449Nor in this discussion have I advocated the cause of the populace,
but of the good.
For one cannot easily resist a powerful people if one gives them
either no rights at all or very little.
In which case I wish I could augur first with truth and fidelity * * *
IX. Cicero saying this in vain, when speaking of poets, “And when
the shouts and approval of the people, as of some great and wise
teacher, has reached them, what darkness do they bring on! what
alarms do they cause! what desires do they excite!”
Cicero says that if his life were extended to twice its length, he
should not have time to read the lyric poets.
X. As Scipio says in Cicero, “As they thought the whole histrionic
art, and everything connected with the theatre, discreditable, they
thought fit that all men of that description should not only be
deprived of the honors belonging to the rest of the citizens, but
should also be deprived of their franchise by the sentence of the
censors.”
And what the ancient Romans thought on this subject Cicero informs
us, in those books which he wrote on the Commonwealth, where Scipio
argues and says *В *В *
Comedies could never (if it had not been authorized by the common
customs of life) have made theatres approve of their scandalous
exhibitions. And the more ancient Greeks provided a certain correction
for the vicious taste of the people, by making a law that it should be
expressly defined by a censorship what subjects comedy should treat, and
how she should treat them.
Whom has it not attacked? or, rather, whom has it not wounded? and whom
has it spared? In this, no doubt, it sometimes took the right side, and
lashed the popular demagogues and seditious agitators, such as Cleon,
Cleophon, and Hyperbolus. We may tolerate that; though indeed the
censure of the magistrate would, in these cases, have been more
efficacious than the satire of the poet. But when Pericles, who governed
the Athenian Commonwealth for so many years with the highest authority,
both in peace and war, was outraged by verses, and these were acted on
the stage, it was hardly more decent than if, among us, Plautus and
Nævius had attacked Publius and Cnæus, or Cæcilius had ventured to
revile Marcus Cato.
Our laws of the Twelve Tables, on the contrary—so careful to attach
capital punishment to a very few crimes only—have included in this
class of capital offences the offence of composing or publicly reciting
verses of libel, slander, and defamation, in order to cast dishonor and
infamy
450on a fellow-citizen. And they have decided wisely; for our life
and character should, if suspected, be submitted to the sentence of
judicial tribunals and the legal investigations of our magistrates, and
not to the whims and fancies of poets. Nor should we be exposed to any
charge of disgrace which we cannot meet by legal process, and openly
refute at the bar.
In our laws, I admire the justice of their expressions, as well as their
decisions. Thus the word
pleading signifies rather an amicable suit
between friends than a quarrel between enemies.
It is not easy to resist a powerful people, if you allow them no rights,
or next to none.
The old Romans would not allow any living man to be either praised
or blamed on the stage.
XI. Cicero says that comedy is an imitation of life; a mirror of
customs, an image of truth.
Since, as is mentioned in that book on the Commonwealth, not only
did Г†schines the Athenian, a man of the greatest eloquence, who,
when a young man, had been an actor of tragedies, concern himself
in public affairs, but the Athenians often sent Aristodemus, who
was also a tragic actor, to Philip as an ambassador, to treat of
the most important affairs of peace and war.
INTRODUCTION TO THE FIFTH BOOK,
BY THE ORIGINAL TRANSLATOR.
In this fifth book Cicero explains and enforces the duties of
magistrates, and the importance of practical experience to all who
undertake their important functions. Only a few fragments have
survived the wreck of ages and descended to us.
BOOK V.
FRAGMENTS.
I.
Ennius has told us—
Of men and customs mighty Rome consists;
which verse, both for its precision and its verity, appears to me as if
it had issued from an oracle; for neither the 451men, unless the State had
adopted a certain system of manners—nor the manners, unless they had
been illustrated by the men—could ever have established or maintained
for so many ages so vast a republic, or one of such righteous and
extensive sway.
Thus, long before our own times, the force of hereditary manners of
itself moulded most eminent men; and admirable citizens, in return, gave
new weight to the ancient customs and institutions of our ancestors. But
our age, on the contrary, having received the Commonwealth as a finished
picture of another century, but one already beginning to fade through
the lapse of years, has not only neglected to renew the colors of the
original painting, but has not even cared to preserve its general form
and prominent lineaments.
For what now remains of those antique manners, of which the poet said
that our Commonwealth consisted? They have now become so obsolete and
forgotten that they are not only not cultivated, but they are not even
known. And as to the men, what shall I say? For the manners themselves
have only perished through a scarcity of men; of which great misfortune
we are not only called to give an account, but even, as men accused of
capital offences, to a certain degree to plead our own cause in
connection with it. For it is owing to our vices, rather than to any
accident, that we have retained the name of republic when we have long
since lost the reality.
II. *В *В * There is no employment so essentially royal as the exposition
of equity, which comprises the true interpretation of all laws. This
justice subjects used generally to expect from their kings. For this
reason, lands, fields, woods, and pastures were reserved as the property
of kings, and cultivated for them, without any labor on their part, in
order that no anxiety on account of their personal interests might
distract their attention from the welfare of the State. Nor was any
private man allowed to be the judge or arbitrator in any suit; but all
disputes were terminated by the royal sentence.
And of all our Roman monarchs, Numa appears to me to have best preserved
this ancient custom of the kings of Greece. For the others, though they
also discharged this 452duty, were for the main part employed in
conducting military enterprises, and in attending to those rights which
belonged to war. But the long peace of Numa’s reign was the mother of
law and religion in this city. And he was himself the author of those
admirable laws which, as you are aware, are still extant. And this
character is precisely what belongs to the man of whom we are speaking.
*В *В *
III. [Scipio. Ought not a farmer] to be acquainted with the nature of
plants and seeds?
Manilius. Certainly, provided he attends to his practical business
also.
Scipio. Do you think that knowledge only fit for a steward?
Manilius. Certainly not, inasmuch as the cultivation of land often
fails for want of agricultural labor.
Scipio. Therefore, as the steward knows the nature of a field, and the
scribe knows penmanship, and as both of them seek, in their respective
sciences, not mere amusement only, but practical utility, so this
statesman of ours should have studied the science of jurisprudence and
legislation; he should have investigated their original sources; but he
should not embarrass himself in debating and arguing, reading and
scribbling. He should rather employ himself in the actual administration
of government, and become a sort of steward of it, being perfectly
conversant with the principles of universal law and equity, without
which no man can be just: not unfamiliar with the civil laws of states;
but he will use them for practical purposes, even as a pilot uses
astronomy, and a physician natural philosophy. For both these men bring
their theoretical science to bear on the practice of their arts; and our
statesman [should do the same with the science of politics, and make it
subservient to the actual interests of philanthropy and patriotism]. *В *В *
IV. *В *В * In states in which good men desire glory and approbation, and
shun disgrace and ignominy. Nor are such men so much alarmed by the
threats and penalties of the law as by that sentiment of shame with
which nature has endowed man, which is nothing else than a certain fear
of deserved censure. The wise director of a government 453strengthens this
natural instinct by the force of public opinion, and perfects it by
education and manners. And thus the citizens are preserved from vice and
corruption rather by honor and shame than by fear of punishment. But
this argument will be better illustrated when we treat of the love of
glory and praise, which we shall discuss on another occasion.
V. As respects the private life and the manners of the citizens, they
are intimately connected with the laws that constitute just marriages
and legitimate offspring, under the protection of the guardian deities
around the domestic hearths. By these laws, all men should be maintained
in their rights of public and private property. It is only under a good
government like this that men can live happily—for nothing can be more
delightful than a well-constituted state.
On which account it appears to me a very strange thing what this *В *В *
VI. I therefore consume all my time in considering what is the
power of that man, whom, as you think, we have described carefully
enough in our books. Do you, then, admit our idea of that governor
of a commonwealth to whom we wish to refer everything? For thus, I
imagine, does Scipio speak in the fifth book: “For as a fair voyage
is the object of the master of a ship, the health of his patient
the aim of a physician, and victory that of a general, so the
happiness of his fellow-citizens is the proper study of the ruler
of a commonwealth; that they may be stable in power, rich in
resources, widely known in reputation, and honorable through their
virtue. For a ruler ought to be one who can perfect this, which is
the best and most important employment among mankind.”
And works in your literature rightly praise that ruler of a country
who consults the welfare of his people more than their
inclinations.
VII. Tully, in those books which he wrote upon the Commonwealth,
could not conceal his opinions, when he speaks of appointing a
chief of the State, who, he says, must be maintained by glory; and
afterward he relates that his ancestors did many admirable and
noble actions from a desire of glory.
Tully, in his treatise on the Commonwealth, wrote that the chief of
a state must be maintained by glory, and that a commonwealth would
last as long as honor was paid by every one to the chief.
INTRODUCTION TO THE SIXTH BOOK.
In this last book of his Commonwealth, Cicero labors to show that
truly pious philanthropical and patriotic statesmen will not only
be rewarded on earth by the approval of conscience and the applause
of all good citizens, but that they may expect hereafter immortal
glory in new forms of being. To illustrate this, he introduces the
“Dream of Scipio,” in which he explains the resplendent doctrines
of Plato respecting the immortality of the soul with inimitable
dignity and elegance. This Somnium Scipionis, for which we are
indebted to the citation of Macrobius, is the most beautiful thing
of the kind ever written. It has been intensely admired by all
European scholars, and will be still more so. There are two
translations of it in our language; one attached to Oliver’s
edition of Cicero’s Thoughts, the other by Mr. Danby, published in
1829. Of these we have freely availed ourselves, and as freely we
express our acknowledgments.
BOOK VI.
SCIPIO’S DREAM.
I.
Therefore you rely upon all the prudence of this rule, which has
derived its very name (
prudentia) from foreseeing (
a
providendo). Wherefore the citizen must so prepare himself as to
be always armed against those things which trouble the constitution
of a state. And that
455dissension of the citizens, when one party
separates from and attacks another, is called sedition.
And in truth in civil dissensions, as the good are of more
importance than the many, I think that we should regard the weight
of the citizens, and not their number.
For the lusts, being severe mistresses of the thoughts, command and
compel many an unbridled action. And as they cannot be satisfied or
appeased by any means, they urge those whom they have inflamed with
their allurements to every kind of atrocity.
II. Which indeed was so much the greater in him because though the
cause of the colleagues was identical, not only was their
unpopularity not equal, but the influence of Gracchus was employed
in mitigating the hatred borne to Claudius.
Who encountered the number of the chiefs and nobles with these
words, and left behind him that mournful and dignified expression
of his gravity and influence.
That, as he writes, a thousand men might every day descend into the
forum with cloaks dyed in purple.
IX. When I had arrived in Africa, where I was, as you are aware,
military tribune of the fourth legion under the consul Manilius, there
was nothing of which I was more earnestly desirous than to see King
Masinissa, who, for very just reasons, had been always the especial
friend of our family. When I was introduced to him, the old man embraced
me, shed tears, and then, looking up to heaven, exclaimed—I thank thee,
O supreme Sun, and ye also, ye other celestial beings, that before I
depart from this life I behold in my kingdom, and in this my palace,
Publius Cornelius Scipio, by whose mere name I seem to be reanimated; so
completely and indelibly is the recollection of that best and most
invincible of men, Africanus, imprinted in my mind.
After this, I inquired of him concerning the affairs of his kingdom. He,
on the other hand, questioned me about the condition of our
Commonwealth, and in this mutual interchange of conversation we passed
the whole of that day.
X. In the evening we were entertained in a manner worthy the
magnificence of a king, and carried on our discourse for a considerable
part of the night. And during all this time the old man spoke of nothing
but Africanus, all whose actions, and even remarkable sayings, he
remembered distinctly. At last, when we retired to bed, I fell into a
more profound sleep than usual, both because I was fatigued with my
journey, and because I had sat up the greatest part of the night.
Here I had the following dream, occasioned, as I verily believe, by our
preceding conversation; for it frequently happens that the thoughts and
discourses which have employed us in the daytime produce in our sleep an
effect somewhat similar to that which Ennius writes happened to him
about Homer, of whom, in his waking hours, he used frequently
458to think
and speak.
Africanus, I thought, appeared to me in that shape, with which I was
better acquainted from his picture than from any personal knowledge of
him. When I perceived it was he, I confess I trembled with
consternation; but he addressed me, saying, Take courage, my Scipio; be
not afraid, and carefully remember what I shall say to you.
XI. Do you see that city Carthage, which, though brought under the Roman
yoke by me, is now renewing former wars, and cannot live in peace? (and
he pointed to Carthage from a lofty spot, full of stars, and brilliant,
and glittering)—to attack which city you are this day arrived in a
station not much superior to that of a private soldier. Before two
years, however, are elapsed, you shall be consul, and complete its
overthrow; and you shall obtain, by your own merit, the surname of
Africanus, which as yet belongs to you no otherwise than as derived from
me. And when you have destroyed Carthage, and received the honor of a
triumph, and been made censor, and, in quality of ambassador, visited
Egypt, Syria, Asia, and Greece, you shall be elected a second time
consul in your absence, and, by utterly destroying Numantia, put an end
to a most dangerous war.
But when you have entered the Capitol in your triumphal car, you shall
find the Roman Commonwealth all in a ferment, through the intrigues of
my grandson Tiberius Gracchus.
XII. It is on this occasion, my dear Africanus, that you show your
country the greatness of your understanding, capacity, and prudence. But
I see that the destiny, however, of that time is, as it were, uncertain;
for when your age shall have accomplished seven times eight revolutions
of the sun, and your fatal hours shall be marked put by the natural
product of these two numbers, each of which is esteemed a perfect one,
but for different reasons, then shall the whole city have recourse to
you alone, and place its hopes in your auspicious name. On you the
senate,
459all good citizens, the allies, the people of Latium, shall cast
their eyes; on you the preservation of the State shall entirely depend.
In a word,
if you escape the impious machinations of your relatives,
you will, in quality of dictator, establish order and tranquillity in
the Commonwealth.
When on this Lælius made an exclamation, and the rest of the company
groaned loudly, Scipio, with a gentle smile, said, I entreat you, do not
wake me out of my dream, but have patience, and hear the rest.
XIII. Now, in order to encourage you, my dear Africanus, continued the
shade of my ancestor, to defend the State with the greater cheerfulness,
be assured that, for all those who have in any way conduced to the
preservation, defence, and enlargement of their native country, there is
a certain place in heaven where they shall enjoy an eternity of
happiness. For nothing on earth is more agreeable to God, the Supreme
Governor of the universe, than the assemblies and societies of men
united together by laws, which are called states. It is from heaven
their rulers and preservers came, and thither they return.
XIV. Though at these words I was extremely troubled, not so much at the
fear of death as at the perfidy of my own relations, yet I recollected
myself enough to inquire whether he himself, my father Paulus, and
others whom we look upon as dead, were really living.
Yes, truly, replied he, they all enjoy life who have escaped from the
chains of the body as from a prison. But as to what you call life on
earth, that is no more than one form of death. But see; here comes your
father Paulus towards you! And as soon as I observed him, my eyes burst
out into a flood of tears; but he took me in his arms, embraced me, and
bade me not weep.
XV. When my first transports subsided, and I regained the liberty of
speech, I addressed my father thus: Thou best and most venerable of
parents, since this, as I am informed by Africanus, is the only
substantial life, why do I linger on earth, and not rather haste to come
hither where you are?
That, replied he, is impossible: unless that God, whose temple is all
that vast expanse you behold, shall free you
460from the fetters of the
body, you can have no admission into this place. Mankind have received
their being on this very condition, that they should labor for the
preservation of that globe which is situated, as you see, in the midst
of this temple, and is called earth.
Men are likewise endowed with a soul, which is a portion of the eternal
fires which you call stars and constellations; and which, being round,
spherical bodies, animated by divine intelligences, perform their cycles
and revolutions with amazing rapidity. It is your duty, therefore, my
Publius, and that of all who have any veneration for the Gods, to
preserve this wonderful union of soul and body; nor without the express
command of Him who gave you a soul should the least thought be
entertained of quitting human life, lest you seem to desert the post
assigned you by God himself.
But rather follow the examples of your grandfather here, and of me, your
father, in paying a strict regard to justice and piety; which is due in
a great degree to parents and relations, but most of all to our country.
Such a life as this is the true way to heaven, and to the company of
those, who, after having lived on earth and escaped from the body,
inhabit the place which you now behold.
XVI. This was the shining circle, or zone, whose remarkable brightness
distinguishes it among the constellations, and which, after the Greeks,
you call the Milky Way.
From thence, as I took a view of the universe, everything appeared
beautiful and admirable; for there those stars are to be seen that are
never visible from our globe, and everything appears of such magnitude
as we could not have imagined. The least of all the stars was that
removed farthest from heaven, and situated next to the earth; I mean our
moon, which shines with a borrowed light. Now, the globes of the stars
far surpass the magnitude of our earth, which at that distance appeared
so exceedingly small that I could not but be sensibly affected on seeing
our whole empire no larger than if we touched the earth, as it were, at
a single point.
XVII. And as I continued to observe the earth with great attention, How
long, I pray you, said Africanus,
461will your mind be fixed on that
object? why don’t you rather take a view of the magnificent temples
among which you have arrived? The universe is composed of nine circles,
or rather spheres, one of which is the heavenly one, and is exterior to
all the rest, which it embraces; being itself the Supreme God, and
bounding and containing the whole. In it are fixed those stars which
revolve with never-varying courses. Below this are seven other spheres,
which revolve in a contrary direction to that of the heavens. One of
these is occupied by the globe which on earth they call Saturn. Next to
that is the star of Jupiter, so benign and salutary to mankind. The
third in order is that fiery and terrible planet called Mars. Below
this, again, almost in the middle region, is the sun—the leader,
governor, and prince of the other luminaries; the soul of the world,
which it regulates and illumines; being of such vast size that it
pervades and gives light to all places. Then follow Venus and Mercury,
which attend, as it were, on the sun. Lastly, the moon, which shines
only in the reflected beams of the sun, moves in the lowest sphere of
all. Below this, if we except that gift of the Gods, the soul, which has
been given by the liberality of the Gods to the human race, everything
is mortal, and tends to dissolution; but above the moon all is eternal.
For the earth, which is the ninth globe, and occupies the centre, is
immovable, and, being the lowest, all others gravitate towards it.
XVIII. When I had recovered myself from the astonishment occasioned by
such a wonderful prospect, I thus addressed Africanus: Pray what is this
sound that strikes my ears in so loud and agreeable a manner? To which
he replied: It is that which is called the
music of the spheres, being
produced by their motion and impulse; and being formed by unequal
intervals, but such as are divided according to the justest proportion,
it produces, by duly tempering acute with grave sounds, various concerts
of harmony. For it is impossible that motions so great should be
performed without any noise; and it is agreeable to nature that the
extremes on one side should produce sharp, and on the other flat sounds.
For which reason the sphere of the fixed stars, being the highest, and
being
462carried with a more rapid velocity, moves with a shrill and acute
sound; whereas that of the moon, being the lowest, moves with a very
flat one. As to the earth, which makes the ninth sphere, it remains
immovably fixed in the middle or lowest part of the universe. But those
eight revolving circles, in which both Mercury and Venus are moved with
the same celerity, give out sounds that are divided by seven distinct
intervals, which is generally the regulating number of all things.
This celestial harmony has been imitated by learned musicians both on
stringed instruments and with the voice, whereby they have opened to
themselves a way to return to the celestial regions, as have likewise
many others who have employed their sublime genius while on earth in
cultivating the divine sciences.
By the amazing noise of this sound the ears of mankind have been in some
degree deafened; and indeed hearing is the dullest of all the human
senses. Thus, the people who dwell near the cataracts of the Nile, which
are called Catadupa
348, are, by the excessive roar which that river
makes in precipitating itself from those lofty mountains, entirely
deprived of the sense of hearing. And so inconceivably great is this
sound which is produced by the rapid motion of the whole universe, that
the human ear is no more capable of receiving it than the eye is able to
look steadfastly and directly on the sun, whose beams easily dazzle the
strongest sight.
While I was busied in admiring the scene of wonders, I could not help
casting my eyes every now and then on the earth.
XIX. On which Africanus said, I perceive that you are still employed in
contemplating the seat and residence of mankind. But if it appears to
you so small, as in fact it really is, despise its vanities, and fix
your attention forever on these heavenly objects. Is it possible that
you should attain any human applause or glory that is worth the
contending for? The earth, you see, is peopled but in a very few places,
and those, too, of small extent; and they appear like so many little
spots of green scattered through vast, uncultivated deserts. And those
who inhabit the
463earth are not only so remote from each other as to be
cut off from all mutual correspondence, but their situation being in
oblique or contrary parts of the globe, or perhaps in those
diametrically opposite to yours, all expectation of universal fame must
fall to the ground.
XX. You may likewise observe that the same globe of the earth is girt
and surrounded with certain zones, whereof those two that are most
remote from each other, and lie under the opposite poles of heaven, are
congealed with frost; but that one in the middle, which is far the
largest, is scorched with the intense heat of the sun. The other two are
habitable, one towards the south, the inhabitants of which are your
antipodes, with whom you have no connection; the other, towards the
north, is that which you inhabit, whereof a very small part, as you may
see, falls to your share. For the whole extent of what you see is, as it
were, but a little island, narrow at both ends and wide in the middle,
which is surrounded by the sea which on earth you call the great
Atlantic Ocean, and which, notwithstanding this magnificent name, you
see is very insignificant. And even in these cultivated and well-known
countries, has yours, or any of our names, ever passed the heights of
the Caucasus or the currents of the Ganges? In what other parts to the
north or the south, or where the sun rises and sets, will your names
ever be heard? And if we leave these out of the question, how small a
space is there left for your glory to spread itself abroad; and how long
will it remain in the memory of those whose minds are now full of it?
XXI. Besides all this, if the progeny of any future generation should
wish to transmit to their posterity the praises of any one of us which
they have heard from their forefathers, yet the deluges and combustions
of the earth, which must necessarily happen at their destined periods,
will prevent our obtaining, not only an eternal, but even a durable
glory. And, after all, what does it signify whether those who shall
hereafter be born talk of you, when those who have lived before you,
whose number was perhaps not less, and whose merit certainly greater,
were not so much as acquainted with your name?
XXII. Especially since not one of those who shall hear
464of us is able to
retain in his memory the transactions of a single year. The bulk of
mankind, indeed, measure their year by the return of the sun, which is
only one star. But when all the stars shall have returned to the place
whence they set out, and after long periods shall again exhibit the same
aspect of the whole heavens, that is what ought properly to be called
the revolution of a year, though I scarcely dare attempt to enumerate
the vast multitude of ages contained in it. For as the sun in old time
was eclipsed, and seemed to be extinguished, at the time when the soul
of Romulus penetrated into these eternal mansions, so, when all the
constellations and stars shall revert to their primary position, and the
sun shall at the same point and time be again eclipsed, then you may
consider that the grand year is completed. Be assured, however, that the
twentieth part of it is not yet elapsed.
XXIII. Wherefore, if you have no hopes of returning to this place where
great and good men enjoy all that their souls can wish for, of what
value, pray, is all that human glory, which can hardly endure for a
small portion of one year?
If, then, you wish to elevate your views to the contemplation of this
eternal seat of splendor, you will not be satisfied with the praises of
your fellow-mortals, nor with any human rewards that your exploits can
obtain; but Virtue herself must point out to you the true and only
object worthy of your pursuit. Leave to others to speak of you as they
may, for speak they will. Their discourses will be confined to the
narrow limits of the countries you see, nor will their duration be very
extensive; for they will perish like those who utter them, and will be
no more remembered by their posterity.
XXIV. When he had ceased to speak in this manner, I said, O Africanus,
if indeed the door of heaven is open to those who have deserved well of
their country, although, indeed, from my childhood I have always
followed yours and my father’s steps, and have not neglected to imitate
your glory, still, I will from henceforth strive to follow them more
closely.
Follow them, then, said he, and consider your body only, not yourself,
as mortal. For it is not your outward form
465which constitutes your
being, but your mind; not that substance which is palpable to the
senses, but your spiritual nature.
Know, then, that you are a God—for
a God it must be, which flourishes, and feels, and recollects, and
foresees, and governs, regulates and moves the body over which it is
set, as the Supreme Ruler does the world which is subject to him. For as
that Eternal Being moves whatever is mortal in this world, so the
immortal mind of man moves the frail body with which it is connected.
XXV. For whatever is always moving must be eternal; but that which
derives its motion from a power which is foreign to itself, when that
motion ceases must itself lose its animation.
That alone, then, which moves itself can never cease to be moved,
because it can never desert itself. Moreover, it must be the source, and
origin, and principle of motion in all the rest. There can be nothing
prior to a principle, for all things must originate from it; and it
cannot itself derive its existence from any other source, for if it did
it would no longer be a principle. And if it had no beginning, it can
have no end; for a beginning that is put an end to will neither be
renewed by any other cause, nor will it produce anything else of itself.
All things, therefore, must originate from one source. Thus it follows
that motion must have its source in something which is moved by itself,
and which can neither have a beginning nor an end. Otherwise all the
heavens and all nature must perish, for it is impossible that they can
of themselves acquire any power of producing motion in themselves.
XXVI. As, therefore, it is plain that what is moved by itself must be
eternal, who will deny that this is the general condition and nature of
minds? For as everything is inanimate which is moved by an impulse
exterior to itself, so what is animated is moved by an interior impulse
of its own; for this is the peculiar nature and power of mind. And if
that alone has the power of self-motion, it can neither have had a
beginning, nor can it have an end.
Do you, therefore, exercise this mind of yours in the best pursuits. And
the best pursuits are those which consist in promoting the good of your
country. Such employments will speed the flight of your mind to this its
466proper abode; and its flight will be still more rapid, if, even while
it is enclosed in the body, it will look abroad, and disengage itself as
much as possible from its bodily dwelling, by the contemplation of
things which are external to itself.
This it should do to the utmost of its power. For the minds of those who
have given themselves up to the pleasures of the body, paying, as it
were, a servile obedience to their lustful impulses, have violated the
laws of God and man; and therefore, when they are separated from their
bodies, flutter continually round the earth on which they lived, and are
not allowed to return to this celestial region till they have been
purified by the revolution of many ages.
Thus saying, he vanished, and I awoke from my dream.
A FRAGMENT.
And although it is most desirable that fortune should remain forever in
the most brilliant possible condition, nevertheless, the equability of
life excites less interest than those changeable conditions wherein
prosperity suddenly revives out of the most desperate and ruinous
circumstances.
THE END.
FOOTNOTES:
1 Archilochus was a native of Paros, and flourished about
714-676
b.c. His poems were chiefly Iambics of bitter satire. Horace
speaks of him as the inventor of Iambics, and calls himself his pupil.
Parios ego primus Iambos
Ostendi Latio, numeros animosque secutus
Archilochi, non res et agentia verba Lycamben.
Epist. I. xix. 25.
And in another place he says,
Archilochum proprio rabies armavit Iambo—A.P. 74.
2 This was Livius Andronicus: he is supposed to have been a
native of Tarentum, and he was made prisoner by the Romans, during their
wars in Southern Italy; owing to which he became the slave of M. Livius
Salinator. He wrote both comedies and tragedies, of which Cicero (Brutus
18) speaks very contemptuously, as “Livianæ fabulæ non satis dignæ quæ
iterum legantur”—not worth reading a second time. He also wrote a Latin
Odyssey, and some hymns, and died probably about 221
b.c.
3 C. Fabius, surnamed Pictor, painted the temple of Salus,
which the dictator C. Junius Brutus Bubulus dedicated 302
b.c. The
temple was destroyed by fire in the reign of Claudius. The painting is
highly praised by Dionysius, xvi. 6.
4 For an account of the ancient Greek philosophers, see the
sketch at the end of the Disputations.
5 Isocrates was born at Athens 436
b.c. He was a pupil of
Gorgias, Prodicus, and Socrates. He opened a school of rhetoric, at
Athens, with great success. He died by his own hand at the age of
ninety-eight.
6 So Horace joins these two classes as inventors of all kinds
of improbable fictions:
Pictoribus atque poetis
Quidlibet audendi semper fuit æqua potestas.—A. P. 9.
Which Roscommon translates:
Painters and poets have been still allow’d
Their pencil and their fancies unconfined.
7 Epicharmus was a native of Cos, but lived at Megara, in
Sicily, and when Megara was destroyed, removed to Syracuse, and lived at
the court of Hiero, where he became the first writer of comedies, so
that Horace ascribes the invention of comedy to him, and so does
Theocritus. He lived to a great age.
8 Pherecydes was a native of Scyros, one of the Cyclades; and
is said to have obtained his knowledge from the secret books of the
PhЕ“nicians. He is said also to have been a pupil of Pittacus, the rival
of Thales, and the master of Pythagoras. His doctrine was that there
were three principles (
О–ОµбЅєП‚, or Г†ther;
О§ОёбЅјОЅ, or Chaos; and
О§ПЃбЅ№ОЅОїП‚, or
Time) and four elements (Fire, Earth, Air, and Water), from which
everything that exists was formed.—
Vide Smith’s Dict. Gr. and Rom.
Biog.
9 Archytas was a native of Tarentum, and is said to have
saved the life of Plato by his influence with the tyrant Dionysius. He
was especially great as a mathematician and geometrician, so that Horace
calls him
Maris et terra numeroque carentis arenæ
Mensorem.
Od. i. 28.1.
Plato is supposed to have learned some of his views from him, and
Aristotle to have borrowed from him every idea of the Categories.
10 This was not Timæus the historian, but a native of Locri,
who is said also in the De Finibus (c. 29) to have been a teacher of
Plato. There is a treatise extant bearing his name, which is, however,
probably spurious, and only an abridgment of Plato’s dialogue Timæus.
11 Dicæarchus was a native of Messana, in Sicily, though he
lived chiefly in Greece. He was one of the later disciples of Aristotle.
He was a great geographer, politician, historian, and philosopher, and
died about 285
b.c.
12 Aristoxenus was a native of Tarentum, and also a pupil of
Aristotle. We know nothing of his opinions except that he held the soul
to be a
harmony of the body; a doctrine which had been already
discussed by Plato in the Phædo, and combated by Aristotle. He was a
great musician, and the chief portions of his works which have come down
to us are fragments of some musical treatises.—Smith’s Dict. Gr. and
Rom. Biog.; to which source I must acknowledge my obligation for nearly
the whole of these biographical notes.
13 The Simonides here meant is the celebrated poet of Ceos,
the perfecter of elegiac poetry among the Greeks. He flourished about
the time of the Persian war. Besides his poetry, he is said to have been
the inventor of some method of aiding the memory. He died at the court
of Hiero, 467
b.c.
14 Theodectes was a native of Phaselis, in Pamphylia, a
distinguished rhetorician and tragic poet, and flourished in the time of
Philip of Macedon. He was a pupil of Isocrates, and lived at Athens, and
died there at the age of forty-one.
15 Cineas was a Thessalian, and (as is said in the text) came
to Rome as ambassador from Pyrrhus after the battle of Heraclea, 280
b.c., and his memory is said to have been so great that on the day after
his arrival he was able to address all the senators and knights by name.
He probably died before Pyrrhus returned to Italy, 276
b.c.
16 Charmadas, called also Charmides, was a fellow-pupil with
Philo, the Larissæan of Clitomachus, the Carthaginian. He is said by
some authors to have founded a fourth academy.
17 Metrodorus was a minister of Mithridates the Great; and
employed by him as supreme judge in Pontus, and afterward as an
ambassador. Cicero speaks of him in other places (De Orat. ii. 88) as a
man of wonderful memory.
18 Quintus Hortensius was eight years older than Cicero; and,
till Cicero’s fame surpassed his, he was accounted the most eloquent of
all the Romans. He was Verres’s counsel in the prosecution conducted
against him by Cicero. Seneca relates that his memory was so great that
he could come out of an auction and repeat the catalogue backward. He
died 50
b.c.
19 This treatise is one which has not come down to us, but
which had been lately composed by Cicero in order to comfort himself for
the loss of his daughter.
20 The epigram is,
О•бјґПЂО±П‚ бјО»О№Оµ П‡О±бї–ПЃОµ, ОљО»ОµбЅ№ОјОІПЃОїП„ОїП‚ бЅОјОІПЃО±ОєО№бЅЅП„О·П‚
ἥλατ’ ἀφ’ ὑψηλοῦ τείχεος εἰς Ἀΐδην,
бј„ОѕО№ОїОЅ ОїбЅђОґбЅІОЅ бј°ОґбЅјОЅ ОёО±ОЅбЅ±П„ОїП… ОєО±ОєбЅёОЅ, бјЂО»О»бЅ° О О»бЅ±П„П‰ОЅОїП‚
ἓν τὸ περὶ ψύχης γράμμ’ ἀναλεξάμενος.
Which may be translated, perhaps,
Farewell, O sun, Cleombrotus exclaim’d,
Then plunged from off a height beneath the sea;
Stung by pain, of no disgrace ashamed,
But moved by Plato’s high philosophy.
21 This is alluded to by Juvenal:
Provida Pompeio dederat Campania febres
Optandas: sed multæ urbes et publica vota
Vicerunt. Igitur Fortuna ipsius et Urbis,
Servatum victo caput abstulit.—Sat. x. 283.
22 Pompey’s second wife was Julia, the daughter of Julius Cæsar,
she died the year before the death of Crassus, in Parthia. Virgil
speaks of Cæsar and Pompey as relations, using the same expression
(socer) as Cicero:
Aggeribus socer Alpinis atque arce Monœci
Descendens, gener adversis instructus Eois.—Æn. vi. 830.
23 This idea is beautifully expanded by Byron:
Yet if, as holiest men have deem’d, there be
A land of souls beyond that sable shore
To shame the doctrine of the Sadducee
And sophist, madly vain or dubious lore,
How sweet it were in concert to adore
With those who made our mortal labors light,
To hear each voice we fear’d to hear no more.
Behold each mighty shade reveal’d to sight,
The Bactrian, Samian sage, and all who taught the right!
Childe Harold, ii.
24 The epitaph in the original is:
Ὦ ξεῖν’ ἀγγεῖλον Λακεδαιμονίοις ὅτι τῇδε
ОєОµбЅ·ОјОµОёО±, П„ОїбїђП‚ ОєОµбЅ·ОЅП‰ОЅ ПЂОµО№ОёбЅ№ОјОµОЅОїО№ ОЅОїОјбЅ·ОјОїО№П‚.
25 This was expressed in the Greek verses,
бј€ПЃП‡бЅґП‚ ОјбЅІОЅ ОјбЅґ П†бї¦ОЅО±О№ бјђПЂО№П‡ОёОїОЅбЅ·ОїО№ПѓО№ОЅ бј„ПЃО№ПѓП„ОїОЅ,
φύντα δ’ ὅπως ὤκιστα πύλας Ἀΐδϋο περῆσαι
which by some authors are attributed to Homer.
26 This is the first fragment of the Cresphontes.—Ed. Var.
vii., p. 594.
бјњОґОµО№ ОібЅ°ПЃ бјЎОјбѕ¶П‚ ПѓбЅ»О»О»ОїОіОїОЅ ПЂОїО№ОїП…ОјбЅіОЅОїП…П‚
Τὸν φύντα θρηνεῖν, εἰς ὅσ’ ἔρχεται κακά.
Τὸν δ’ αὖ θανόντα καὶ πόνων πεπαυμένον
П‡О±бЅ·ПЃОїОЅП„О±П‚ ОµбЅђП†О·ОјОїбї–ОЅП„О±П‚ бјђОєПЂбЅіОјОµО№ОЅ ОґбЅ№ОјП‰ОЅ
27 The Greek verses are quoted by Plutarch:
бј¬ПЂОїП… ОЅбЅµПЂО№Оµ, бј О»бЅ·ОёО№ОїО№ П†ПЃбЅіОЅОµП‚ бјЂОЅОґПЃбї¶ОЅ
О•бЅђОёбЅ»ОЅОїОїП‚ ОєОµбї–П„О±О№ ОјОїО№ПЃО№ОґбЅ·бїі ОёО±ОЅбЅ±П„бїі
ОџбЅђОє бј ОЅ ОібЅ°ПЃ О¶бЅЅОµО№ОЅ ОєО±О»бЅёОЅ О±бЅђП„бї· ОїбЅ”П„Оµ ОіОїОЅОµбї¦ПѓО№.
28 This refers to the story that when Eumolpus, the son of
Neptune, whose assistance the Eleusinians had called in against the
Athenians, had been slain by the Athenians, an oracle demanded the
sacrifice of one of the daughters of Erechtheus, the King of Athens. And
when one was drawn by lot, the others voluntarily accompanied her to
death.
29 MenЕ“ceus was son of Creon, and in the war of the Argives
against Thebes, Teresias declared that the Thebans should conquer if
MenЕ“ceus would sacrifice himself for his country; and accordingly he
killed himself outside the gates of Thebes.
30 The Greek is,
ОјбЅµОґОµ ОјОїО№ бј„ОєО»О±П…ПѓП„ОїП‚ ОёбЅ±ОЅО±П„ОїП‚ ОјбЅ№О»ОїО№, бјЂО»О»бЅ° П†бЅ·О»ОїО№ПѓО№
ПЂОїО№бЅµПѓО±О№ОјО№ ОёО±ОЅбЅјОЅ бј„О»ОіОµО± ОєО±бЅ¶ ПѓП„ОїОЅО±П‡бЅ±П‚.
32 The lines quoted by Cicero here appear to have come from
the Latin play of Prometheus by Accius; the ideas are borrowed, rather
than translated, from the Prometheus of Г†schylus.
34 Each soldier carried a stake, to help form a palisade in
front of the camp.
35 Insania—from
in, a particle of negative force in
composition, and
sanus, healthy, sound.
36 The man who first received this surname was L. Calpurnius
Piso, who was consul, 133
b.c., in the Servile War.
37 The Greek is,
Ἀλλά μοι οἰδάνεται κραδίη χόλῳ ὅπποτ’ ἐκείνου
Μνήσομαι ὅς μ’ ἀσύφηλον ἐν Ἀργείοισιν ἔρεξεν.—Il. ix. 642.
I have given Pope’s translation in the text.
38 This is from the Theseus:
бј�ОібЅј ОґбЅІ П„Оїбї¦П„Ої ПЂО±ПЃбЅ° ПѓОїП†Оїбї¦ П„О№ОЅОїП‚ ОјО±ОёбЅјОЅ
εὶς φροντίδας νοῦν συμφοράς τ’ ἐβαλλόμην
φυγάς τ’ ἐμαυτῷ προστιθεὶς πάτρας ἐμῆς.
θανάτους τ’ ἀώρους, καὶ κακῶν ἄλλας ὁδοὺς
ὡς, εἴ τι πάσχοιμ’ ὠν ἐδόξαζόν ποτε
ОњбЅµ ОјОїО№ ОЅбЅіОїПЃП„ОїОЅ ПЂПЃОїПѓПЂОµПѓбЅёОЅ Ојбѕ¶О»О»ОїОЅ ОґбЅ±ОєОїО№.
39 Ter. Phorm. II. i. 11.
40 This refers to the speech of Agamemnon in Euripides, in
the Iphigenia in Aulis,
О–О·О»бї¶ ПѓОµ, ОібЅіПЃОїОЅ,
ζηλῶ δ’ ἀνδρῶν ὃς ἀκίνδυνον
βίον ἐξεπέρασ’, ἀγνὼς, ἀκλεής.—v. 15.
41 This is a fragment from the Hypsipyle:
О•П†П… ОјбЅІОЅ ОїбЅђОґОµбЅ¶П‚ бЅ…ПѓП„О№П‚ ОїбЅђ ПЂОїОЅОµбї– ОІПЃОїП„бї¶ОЅ
θάπτει τε τέκνα χἄτερ’ αὖ κτᾶται νεὰ,
αὐτός τε θνήσκει. καὶ τάδ’ ἄχθονται βροτοὶ
εἰς γῆν φέροντες γῆν ἀναγκαίως δ’ ἔχει
ОІбЅ·ОїОЅ ОёОµПЃбЅ·О¶ОµО№ОЅ бЅҐПѓП„Оµ ОєбЅ±ПЃПЂО№ОјОїОЅ ПѓП„бЅ±П‡П…ОЅ.
42
Πολλὰς ἐκ κεφαλῆς προθελύμνους ἕλκετο χαίτας.—Il. x. 15.
43
бј¬П„ОїО№ бЅЃ ОєО±ПЂПЂбЅіОґО№ОїОЅ П„бЅё бј€О»О·ОђОїОЅ Оїбј¶ОїП‚ бјЂО»бѕ¶П„Ої
ὅν θυμὸν κατεδὼν, πάτον ἀνθρώπων ἀλεείνων.—Il. vi. 201.
44 This is a translation from Euripides:
бЅПѓОёвЂ™ бјµОјОµПЃОїП‚ μ’ бЅ‘ПЂбї†О»ОёОµ Оібї‡ П„Оµ κ’ ОїбЅђПЃО±ОЅбї·
λέξαι μολούσῃ δεῦρο Μηδείας τύχας.—Med. 57.
45
О›бЅ·О·ОЅ ОібЅ°ПЃ ПЂОїО»О»ОїбЅ¶ ОєО±бЅ¶ бјђПЂбЅµП„ПЃО№ОјОїО№ бј¤ОјО±П„О± ПЂбЅ±ОЅП„О±
ПЂбЅ·ПЂП„ОїП…ПѓО№ОЅ, ПЂбЅ№П„Оµ ОєбЅіОЅ П„О№П‚ бјЂОЅО±ПЂОЅОµбЅ»ПѓОµО№Оµ ПЂбЅ№ОЅОїО№Ої;
бјЂО»О»бЅ° П‡ПЃбЅґ П„бЅёОЅ ОјбЅІОЅ ОєО±П„О±ОёО±ПЂП„бЅіОјОµОЅ, бЅ…П‚ ОєОµ ОёбЅ±ОЅО·ПѓО№,
νηλέα θυμὸν ἔχοντας, ἔπ’ ἤματι δακρυσάντας.—
Hom. Il. xix. 226.
46 This is one of the fragments of Euripides which we are
unable to assign to any play in particular; it occurs Var. Ed. Tr. Inc.
167.
Εἰ μεν τόδ’ ἦμαρ πρῶτον ἦν κακουμένῳ
ОєО±бЅ¶ ОјбЅґ ОјО±ОєПЃбЅ°ОЅ ОґбЅґ ОґО№бЅ° ПЂбЅ№ОЅП‰ОЅ бјђОЅО±П…ПѓП„бЅ№О»ОїП…ОЅ
Оµбј°ОєбЅёП‚ ПѓП†О±ОґбЅ±О¶ОµО№ОЅ бј¦ОЅ бј‚ОЅ, бЅЎП‚ ОЅОµбЅ№О¶П…ОіО±
ПЂбї¶О»ОїОЅ, П‡бЅ±О»О№ОЅОїОЅ бјЂПЃП„бЅ·П‰П‚ ОґОµОґОµОіОјбЅіОЅОїОЅ
νῦν δ’ ἀμβλύς εἰμι, καὶ κατηρτυκὼς κακῶν.
47 This is only a fragment, preserved by Stobæus:
Τοὺς δ’ ἂν μεγίστους καὶ σοφωτάτους φρενὶ
τοιούσδ’ ἴδοις ἂν, οἶός ἐστι νῦν ὅδε,
ОєО±О»бї¶П‚ ОєО±Оєбї¶П‚ ПЂПЃбЅ±ПѓПѓОїОЅП„О№ ПѓП…ОјПЂО±ПЃО±О№ОЅбЅіПѓО±О№
бЅ…П„О±ОЅ ОґбЅІ ОґО±бЅ·ОјП‰ОЅ бјЂОЅОґПЃбЅёП‚ ОµбЅђП„П…П‡Оїбї¦П‚ П„бЅё ПЂПЃбЅ¶ОЅ
μάστιγ’ ἐπίσῃ τοῦ βίου παλίντροπον,
П„бЅ° ПЂОїО»О»бЅ° П†ПЃОїбї¦ОґО± ОєО±бЅ¶ ОєО±Оєбї¶П‚ Оµбј°ПЃО·ОјбЅіОЅО±.
48
О©Оє. ОџбЅђОєОїбї¦ОЅ О ПЃОїОјО·ОёОµбї¦ П„Оїбї¦П„Ої ОіО№ОіОЅбЅЅПѓОєОµО№П‚ бЅ…П„О№
бЅЂПЃОібї†П‚ ОЅОїПѓОїбЅ»ПѓО·П‚ Оµбј°ПѓбЅ¶ОЅ бј°О±П„ПЃОїбЅ¶ О»бЅ№ОіОїО№.
О ПЃ. бјђбЅ±ОЅ П„О№П‚ бјђОЅ ОєО±О№ПЃбї· ОіОµ ОјО±О»ОёбЅ±ПѓПѓбїѓ ОєОµбЅ±ПЃ
καὶ μὴ σφριγῶντα θυμὸν ἰσχναίνη βιᾳ.—
Г†sch. Prom. v. 378.
49 Cicero alludes here to Il. vii. 211, which is thus
translated by Pope:
His massy javelin quivering in his hand,
He stood the bulwark of the Grecian band;
Through every Argive heart new transport ran,
All Troy stood trembling at the mighty man:
E’en Hector paused, and with new doubt oppress’d,
Felt his great heart suspended in his breast;
’Twas vain to seek retreat, and vain to fear,
Himself had challenged, and the foe drew near.
But Melmoth (Note on the Familiar Letters of Cicero, book ii. Let. 23)
rightly accuses Cicero of having misunderstood Homer, who “by no means
represents Hector as being thus totally dismayed at the approach of his
adversary; and, indeed, it would have been inconsistent with the general
character of that hero to have described him under such circumstances of
terror.”
Τὸν δὲ καὶ Ἀργεῖοι μέγ’ ἐγήθεον εἰσορόωντες,
О¤ПЃП‰бЅ°П‚ ОґбЅІ П„ПЃбЅ№ОјОїП‚ О±бј¶ОЅОїП‚ бЅ‘ПЂбЅµО»П…ОёОµ ОіП…бї–О± бј•ОєО±ПѓП„ОїОЅ,
Ἕκτορι δ’ αὐτῷ θυμὸς ἐνὶ στήθεσσι πάτασσεν.
But there is a great difference, as Dr. Clarke remarks, between
ОёП…ОјбЅёП‚ бјђОЅбЅ¶ ПѓП„бЅµОёОµПѓПѓО№ ПЂбЅ±П„О±ПѓПѓОµОЅ and
ОєО±ПЃОґбЅіО· бј”ОѕП‰ ПѓП„О·ОёбЅіП‰ОЅ бј”ОёПЃП‰ПѓОєОµОЅ, or
П„ПЃбЅ№ОјОїП‚ О±бј¶ОЅОїП‚
ὑπήλυθε γυῖα.—
The Trojans, says Homer,
trembled at the sight of
Ajax, and even Hector himself felt some emotion in his breast.
50 Cicero means Scipio Nasica, who, in the riots consequent
on the reelection of Tiberius Gracchus to the tribunate, 133
b.c.,
having called in vain on the consul, Mucius Scævola, to save the
republic, attacked Gracchus himself, who was slain in the tumult.
51 Morosus is evidently derived from
mores—“
Morosus,
mos, stubbornness, self-will, etc.”—Riddle and Arnold, Lat. Dict.
52 In the original they run thus:
Οὔκ ἐστιν οὐδὲν δεινὸν ὧδ’ εἰπεῖν ἔπος,
ОџбЅђОґбЅІ ПЂбЅ±ОёОїП‚, ОїбЅђОґбЅІ ОѕП…ОјП†ОїПЃбЅ° ОёОµбЅµО»О±П„ОїП‚
ἧς οὐκ ἂν ἀροιτ’ ἄχθος ἀνθρώπον φύσις.
53 This passage is from the Eunuch of Terence, act i., sc. 1,
14.
54 These verses are from the Atreus of Accius.
55 This was Marcus Atilius Regulus, the story of whose
treatment by the Carthaginians in the first Punic War is well known to
everybody.
56 This was Quintus Servilius Cæpio, who, 105
b.c., was
destroyed, with his army, by the Cimbri, it was believed as a judgment
for the covetousness which he had displayed in the plunder of Tolosa.
57 This was Marcus Aquilius, who, in the year 88
b.c., was
sent against Mithridates as one of the consular legates; and, being
defeated, was delivered up to the king by the inhabitants of Mitylene.
Mithridates put him to death by pouring molten gold down his throat.
58 This was the elder brother of the triumvir Marcus Crassus,
87
b.c. He was put to death by Fimbria, who was in command of some of
the troops of Marius.
59 Lucius Cæsar and Caius Cæsar were relations (it is
uncertain in what degree) of the great Cæsar, and were killed by Fimbria
on the same occasion as Octavius.
60 M. Antonius was the grandfather of the triumvir; he was
murdered the same year, 87
b.c., by Annius, when Marius and Cinna took
Rome.
61 This story is alluded to by Horace:
Districtus ensis cui super impiГў
Cervice pendet non Siculæ dapes
Dulcem elaborabunt saporem,
Non avium citharæve cantus
Somnum reducent.—iii. 1. 17.
62 Hieronymus was a Rhodian, and a pupil of Aristotle,
flourishing about 300
b.c. He is frequently mentioned by Cicero.
63 We know very little of Dinomachus. Some MSS. have
Clitomachus.
64 Callipho was in all probability a pupil of Epicurus, but
we have no certain information about him.
65 Diodorus was a Syrian, and succeeded Critolaus as the head
of the Peripatetic School at Athens.
66 Aristo was a native of Ceos, and a pupil of Lycon, who
succeeded Straton as the head of the Peripatetic School, 270
b.c. He
afterward himself succeeded Lycon.
67 Pyrrho was a native of Elis, and the originator of the
sceptical theories of some of the ancient philosophers. He was a
contemporary of Alexander.
68 Herillus was a disciple of Zeno of Cittium, and therefore
a Stoic. He did not, however, follow all the opinions of his master: he
held that knowledge was the chief good. Some of the treatises of
Cleanthes were written expressly to confute him.
69 Anacharsis was (Herod., iv., 76) son of Gnurus and brother
of Saulius, King of Thrace. He came to Athens while Solon was occupied
in framing laws for his people; and by the simplicity of his way of
living, and his acute observations on the manners of the Greeks, he
excited such general admiration that he was reckoned by some writers
among the Seven Wise Men of Greece.
70 This was Appius Claudius Cæcus, who was censor 310
b.c.,
and who, according to Livy, was afflicted with blindness by the Gods for
persuading the Potitii to instruct the public servants in the way of
sacrificing to Hercules. He it was who made the Via Appia.
71 The fact of Homer’s blindness rests on a passage in the
Hymn to Apollo, quoted by Thucydides as a genuine work of Homer, and
which is thus spoken of by one of the most accomplished scholars that
this country or this age has ever produced: “They are indeed beautiful
verses; and if none worse had ever been attributed to Homer, the Prince
of Poets would have had little reason to complain.
“He has been describing the Delian festival in honor of Apollo and
Diana, and concludes this part of the poem with an address to the women
of that island, to whom it is to be supposed that he had become
familiarly known by his frequent recitations:
Χαίρετε δ’ ὑμεῖς πᾶσαι, ἐμεῖο δὲ καὶ μετόπισθε
μνήσασθ’, ὅπποτέ κέν τις ἐπιχθονίων ἀνθρώπων
ἐνθάδ’ ἀνείρηται ξεῖνος ταλαπείριος ἐλθὼν
ὦ κοῦραι, τίς δ’ ὕμμιν ἀνὴρ ἥδιστος ἀοιδῶν
бјђОЅОёбЅ±ОґОµ ПЂП‰О»Оµбї–П„О±О№ ОєО±бЅ¶ П„бЅібїі П„бЅіПЃПЂОµПѓОёОµ ОјбЅ±О»О№ПѓП„О±;
ὑμεῖς δ’ εὖ μάλα πᾶσαι ὑποκρίνασθε ἀφ’ ἡμῶν,
О¤П…П†О»бЅёП‚ бјЂОЅбЅґПЃ, Оїбј°ОєОµбї– ОґбЅІ О§бЅ·бїі бјђОЅбЅ¶ ПЂО±О№ПЂО±О»ОїбЅіПѓПѓбїѓ,
П„Оїбї¦ ПЂбѕ¶ПѓО±О№ ОјОµП„бЅ№ПЂО№ПѓОёОµОЅ бјЂПЃО№ПѓП„ОµбЅ»ОїП…ПѓО№ОЅ бјЂОїО№ОґО±бЅ·.
Virgins, farewell—and oh! remember me
Hereafter, when some stranger from the sea,
A hapless wanderer, may your isle explore,
And ask you, �Maids, of all the bards you boast,
Who sings the sweetest, and delights you most?’
Oh! answer all, �A blind old man, and poor,
Sweetest he sings, and dwells on Chios’ rocky shore.’”
Coleridge’s Introduction to the Study of the Greek Classic Poets.
72 Some read
scientiam and some
inscientiam; the latter
of which is preferred by some of the best editors and commentators.
73 For a short account of these ancient Greek philosophers,
see the sketch prefixed to the Academics (
Classical Library).
74 Cicero wrote his philosophical works in the last three
years of his life. When he wrote this piece, he was in the sixty-third
year of his age, in the year of Rome 709.
76 Diodorus and Posidonius were Stoics; Philo and Antiochus
were Academics; but the latter afterward inclined to the doctrine of the
Stoics.
78 Cicero was one of the College of Augurs.
79 The Latinæ Feriæ was originally a festival of the Latins,
altered by Tarquinius Superbus into a Roman one. It was held in the
Alban Mount, in honor of Jupiter Latiaris. This holiday lasted six days:
it was not held at any fixed time; but the consul was never allowed to
take the field till he had held them.—
Vide Smith, Dict. Gr. and Rom.
Ant., p. 414.
80 Exhedra, the word used by Cicero, means a study, or
place where disputes were held.
81 M. Piso was a Peripatetic. The four great sects were the
Stoics, the Peripatetics, the Academics, and the Epicureans.
82 It was a prevailing tenet of the Academics that there is
no certain knowledge.
83 The five forms of Plato are these:
ОїбЅђПѓбЅ·О±, П„О±бЅђП„бЅёОЅ, бј•П„ОµПЃОїОЅ,
ПѓП„бЅ±ПѓО№П‚, ОєбЅ·ОЅО·ПѓО№П‚.
84 The four natures here to be understood are the four
elements—fire, water, air, and earth; which are mentioned as the four
principles of Empedocles by Diogenes Laertius.
85 These five moving stars are Saturn, Jupiter, Mars,
Mercury, and Venus. Their revolutions are considered in the next book.
86 Or, Generation of the Gods.
87 The
ПЂПЃбЅ№О»О·П€О№П‚ of Epicurus, before mentioned, is what he
here means.
88 ОЈП„ОµПЃбЅіОјОЅО№О± is the word which Epicurus used to distinguish
between those objects which are perceptible to sense, and those which
are imperceptible; as the essence of the Divine Being, and the various
operations of the divine power.
89 Zeno here mentioned is not the same that Cotta spoke of
before. This was the founder of the Stoics. The other was an Epicurean
philosopher whom he had heard at Athens.
90 That is, there would be the same uncertainty in heaven as
is among the Academics.
91 Those nations which were neither Greek nor Roman.
92 Sigilla numerantes is the common reading; but P.
Manucius proposes
venerantes, which I choose as the better of the two,
and in which sense I have translated it.
93 Fundamental doctrines.
95 The moon, as well as the sun, is indeed in the zodiac, but
she does not measure the same course in a month. She moves in another
line of the zodiac nearer the earth.
96 According to the doctrines of Epicurus, none of these
bodies themselves are clearly seen, but
simulacra ex corporibus
effluentia.
97 Epicurus taught his disciples in a garden.
98 By the word
Deus, as often used by our author, we are to
understand all the Gods in that theology then treated of, and not a
single personal Deity.
99 The best commentators on this passage agree that Cicero
does not mean that Aristotle affirmed that there was no such person as
Orpheus, but that there was no such poet, and that the verse called
Orphic was said to be the invention of another. The passage of Aristotle
to which Cicero here alludes has, as Dr. Davis observes, been long
lost.
100 A just proportion between the different sorts of beings.
101 Some give
quos non pudeat earum Epicuri vocum; but the
best copies have not
non; nor would it be consistent with Cotta to say
quos non pudeat, for he throughout represents Velleius as a perfect
Epicurean in every article.
102 His country was Abdera, the natives of which were
remarkable for their stupidity.
103 This passage will not admit of a translation answerable
to the sense of the original. Cicero says the word
amicitia
(friendship) is derived from
amor (love or affection).
104 This manner of speaking of Jupiter frequently occurs in
Homer,
——πατὴρ ἀνδρῶν τε θεῶν τε,
and has been used by Virgil and other poets since Ennius.
105 Perses, or Perseus, the last king of Macedonia, was taken
by Cnæus Octavius, the prætor, and brought as prisoner to Paullus
Г†milius, 167
b.c.
106 An exemption from serving in the wars, and from paying
public taxes.
107 Mopsus. There were two soothsayers of this name: the
first was one of the Lapithæ, son of Ampycus and Chloris, called also
the son of Apollo and Hienantis; the other a son of Apollo and Manto,
who is said to have founded Mallus, in Asia Minor, where his oracle
existed as late as the time of Strabo.
108 Tiresias was the great Theban prophet at the time of the
war of the Seven against Thebes.
109 Amphiaraus was King of Argos (he had been one of the
Argonauts also). He was killed after the war of the Seven against
Thebes, which he was compelled to join in by the treachery of his wife
Eriphyle, by the earth opening and swallowing him up as he was fleeing
from Periclymenus.
110 Calchas was the prophet of the Grecian army at the siege
of Troy.
111 Helenus was a son of Priam and Hecuba. He is represented
as a prophet in the Philoctetes of Sophocles. And in the Г†neid he is
also represented as king of part of Epirus, and as predicting to Г†neas
the dangers and fortunes which awaited him.
112 This short passage would be very obscure to the reader
without an explanation from another of Cicero’s treatises. The
expression here,
ad investigandum suem regiones vineæ terminavit,
which is a metaphor too bold, if it was not a sort of augural language,
seems to me to have been the effect of carelessness in our great author;
for Navius did not divide the regions, as he calls them, of the vine to
find his sow, but to find a grape.
113 The Peremnia were a sort of auspices performed just
before the passing a river.
114 The Acumina were a military auspices, and were partly
performed on the point of a spear, from which they were called Acumina.
115 Those were called
testamenta in procinctu, which were
made by soldiers just before an engagement, in the presence of men
called as witnesses.
116 This especially refers to the Decii, one of whom devoted
himself for his country in the war with the Latins, 340
b.c., and his
son imitated the action in the war with the Samnites, 295
b.c. Cicero
(Tusc. i. 37) says that his son did the same thing in the war with
Pyrrhus at the battle of Asculum, though in other places (De Off. iii.
4) he speaks of only two Decii as having signalized themselves in this
manner.
117 The Rogator, who collected the votes, and pronounced who
was the person chosen. There were two sorts of Rogators; one was the
officer here mentioned, and the other was the Rogator, or speaker of the
whole assembly.
118 Which was Sardinia, as appears from one of Cicero’s
epistles to his brother Quintus.
119 Their sacred books of ceremonies.
120 The war between Octavius and Cinna, the consuls.
121 This, in the original, is a fragment of an old Latin
verse,
——Terram fumare calentem.
122 The Latin word is
principatus, which exactly
corresponds with the Greek word here used by Cicero; by which is to be
understood the superior, the most prevailing excellence in every kind
and species of things through the universe.
123 The passage of Aristotle to which Cicero here refers is
lost.
124 He means the Epicureans.
125 Here the Stoic speaks too plain to be misunderstood. His
world, his
mundus, is the universe, and that universe is his great
Deity,
in quo sit totius naturæ principatus, in which the superior
excellence of universal nature consists.
126 Athens, the seat of learning and politeness, of which
Balbus will not allow Epicurus to be worthy.
127 This is Pythagoras’s doctrine, as appears in Diogenes
Laertius.
128 He here alludes to mathematical and geometrical
instruments.
129 Balbus here speaks of the fixed stars, and of the motions
of the orbs of the planets. He here alludes, says M. Bonhier, to the
different and diurnal motions of these stars; one sort from east to
west, the other from one tropic to the other: and this is the
construction which our learned and great geometrician and astronomer,
Dr. Halley, made of this passage.
130 This mensuration of the year into three hundred and
sixty-five days and near six hours (by the odd hours and minutes of
which, in every fifth year, the
dies intercalaris, or leap-year, is
made) could not but be known, Dr. Halley states, by Hipparchus, as
appears from the remains of that great astronomer of the ancients. We
are inclined to think that Julius Cæsar had divided the year, according
to what we call the Julian year, before Cicero wrote this book; for we
see, in the beginning of it, how pathetically he speaks of Cæsar’s
usurpation.
131 The words of Censorinus, on this occasion, are to the
same effect. The opinions of philosophers concerning this great year are
very different; but the institution of it is ascribed to Democritus.
133 Though Mars is said to hold his orbit in the zodiac with
the rest, and to finish his revolution through the same orbit (that is,
the zodiac) with the other two, yet Balbus means in a different line of
the zodiac.
134 According to late observations, it never goes but a sign
and a half from the sun.
135 These, Dr. Davis says, are “aërial fires;” concerning
which he refers to the second book of Pliny.
136 In the Eunuch of Terence.
139 The books of Ceremonies.
140 This Libera is taken for Proserpine, who, with her
brother Liber, was consecrated by the Romans; all which are parts of
nature in prosopopЕ“ias. Cicero, therefore, makes Balbus distinguish
between the person Liber, or Bacchus, and the Liber which is a part of
nature in prosopopЕ“ia.
141 These allegorical fables are largely related by Hesiod in
his Theogony.
Horace says exactly the same thing:
HГўc arte Pollux et vagus Hercules
Enisus arces attigit igneas:
Quos inter Augustus recumbens
Purpureo bibit ore nectar.
Hâc te merentem, Bacche pater, tuæ
Vexere tigres indocili jugum
Collo ferentes: hГўc Quirinus
Martis equis Acheronta fugit.—Hor. iii. 3. 9.
142 Cicero means by
conversis casibus, varying the cases
from the common rule of declension; that is, by departing from the true
grammatical rules of speech; for if we would keep to it, we should
decline the word
Jupiter,
Jupiteris in the second case, etc.
143 Pater divГ»mque hominumque.
144 The common reading is,
planiusque alio loco idem;
which, as Dr. Davis observes, is absurd; therefore, in his note, he
prefers
planius quam alia loco idem, from two copies, in which sense I
have translated it.
145 From the verb
gero, to bear.
146 That is, “mother earth.”
147 Janus is said to be the first who erected temples in
Italy, and instituted religious rites, and from whom the first month in
the Roman calendar is derived.
149 Noctu quasi diem efficeret. Ben Jonson says the same
thing:
Thou that mak’st a day of night,
Goddess excellently bright.—Ode to the Moon.
150 Olympias was the mother of Alexander.
151 Venus is here said to be one of the names of Diana,
because
ad res omnes veniret; but she is not supposed to be the same
as the mother of Cupid.
152 Here is a mistake, as Fulvius Ursinus observes; for the
discourse seems to be continued in one day, as appears from the
beginning of this book. This may be an inadvertency of Cicero.
153 The senate of Athens was so called from the words
бјЊПЃОµО№ОїП‚ О бЅ±ОіОїП‚, the Village, some say the Hill, of Mars.
156 By
nulla cohærendi natura—if it is the right, as it is
the common reading—Cicero must mean the same as by
nulla crescendi
natura, or
coalescendi, either of which Lambinus proposes; for, as the
same learned critic well observes, is there not a cohesion of parts in a
clod, or in a piece of stone? Our learned Walker proposes
sola
cohærendi natura, which mends the sense very much; and I wish he had
the authority of any copy for it.
157 Nasica Scipio, the censor, is said to have been the first
who made a water-clock in Rome.
159 An old Latin poet, commended by Quintilian for the
gravity of his sense and his loftiness of style.
160 The shepherd is here supposed to take the stem or beak of
the ship for the mouth, from which the roaring voices of the sailors
came.
Rostrum is here a lucky word to put in the mouth of one who
never saw a ship before, as it is used for the beak of a bird, the snout
of a beast or fish, and for the stem of a ship.
162 Greek,
бјЂбЅґПЃ; Latin,
aer.
163 The treatise of Aristotle, from whence this is taken, is
lost.
164 To the universe the Stoics certainly annexed the idea of
a limited space, otherwise they could not have talked of a middle; for
there can be no middle but of a limited space: infinite space can have
no middle, there being infinite extension from every part.
165 These two contrary reversions are from the tropics of
Cancer and Capricorn. They are the extreme bounds of the sun’s course.
The reader must observe that the astronomical parts of this book are
introduced by the Stoic as proofs of design and reason in the universe;
and, notwithstanding the errors in his planetary system, his intent is
well answered, because all he means is that the regular motions of the
heavenly bodies, and their dependencies, are demonstrations of a divine
mind. The inference proposed to be drawn from his astronomical
observations is as just as if his system was in every part
unexceptionably right: the same may be said of his anatomical
observations.
168 These verses of Cicero are a translation from a Greek
poem of Aratus, called the Phænomena.
170 The arctic and antarctic poles.
171 The two Arctoi are northern constellations. Cynosura is
what we call the Lesser Bear; Helice, the Greater Bear; in Latin,
Ursa
Minor and
Ursa Major.
172 These stars in the Greater Bear are vulgarly called the
“Seven Stars,” or the “Northern Wain;” by the Latins, “Septentriones.”
175 Exactly agreeable to this and the following description
of the Dragon is the same northern constellation described in the map by
Flamsteed in his Atlas CЕ“lestis; and all the figures here described by
Aratus nearly agree with the maps of the same constellations in the
Atlas CЕ“lestis, though they are not all placed precisely alike.
176 The tail of the Greater Bear.
177 That is, in Macedon, where Aratus lived.
178 The true interpretation of this passage is as follows:
Here in Macedon, says Aratus, the head of the Dragon does not entirely
immerge itself in the ocean, but only touches the superficies of it. By
ortus and
obitus I doubt not but Cicero meant, agreeable to Aratus,
those parts which arise to view, and those which are removed from
sight.
179 These are two northern constellations. Engonasis, in some
catalogues called Hercules, because he is figured kneeling
бјђОЅ ОібЅ№ОЅО±ПѓО№ОЅ
(on his knees).
�νγόνασιν καλέουσ’, as Aratus says, they call
Engonasis.
180 The crown is placed under the feet of Hercules in the
Atlas CЕ“lestis; but Ophiuchus (
бЅ€П†О№Оїбї¦П‡ОїП‚), the Snake-holder, is placed in
the map by Flamsteed as described here by Aratus; and their heads almost
meet.
181 The Scorpion. Ophiuchus, though a northern constellation,
is not far from that part of the zodiac where the Scorpion is, which is
one of the six southern signs.
182 The Wain of seven stars.
183 The Wain-driver. This northern constellation is, in our
present maps, figured with a club in his right hand behind the Greater
Bear.
184 In some modern maps Arcturus, a star of the first
magnitude, is placed in the belt that is round the waist of Boötes.
Cicero says
subter præcordia, which is about the waist; and Aratus
says
бЅ‘ПЂбЅё О¶бЅЅОЅбїѓ, under the belt.
185 Sub caput Arcti, under the head of the Greater Bear.
186 The Crab is, by the ancients and moderns, placed in the
zodiac, as here, between the Twins and the Lion; and they are all three
northern signs.
187 The Twins are placed in the zodiac with the side of one
to the northern hemisphere, and the side of the other to the southern
hemisphere. Auriga, the Charioteer, is placed in the northern hemisphere
near the zodiac, by the Twins; and at the head of the Charioteer is
Helice, the Greater Bear, placed; and the Goat is a bright star of the
first magnitude placed on the left shoulder of this northern
constellation, and called
Capra, the Goat.
HЕ“di, the Kids, are two
more stars of the same constellation.
188 A constellation; one of the northern signs in the zodiac,
in which the Hyades are placed.
189 One of the feet of Cepheus, a northern constellation, is
under the tail of the Lesser Bear.
190 Grotius, and after him Dr. Davis, and other learned men,
read
Cassiepea, after the Greek
ОљО±ПѓПѓбЅ·ОµПЂОµО№О±, and reject the common
reading,
Cassiopea.
191 These northern constellations here mentioned have been
always placed together as one family with Cepheus and Perseus, as they
are in our modern maps.
192 This alludes to the fable of Perseus and Andromeda.
193 Pegasus, who is one of Perseus and Andromeda’s family.
195 Aries, the Ram, is the first northern sign in the
zodiac;
Pisces, the Fishes, the last southern sign; therefore they
must be near one another, as they are in a circle or belt. In
Flamsteed’s Atlas Cœlestis one of the Fishes is near the head of the
Ram, and the other near the Urn of Aquarius.
196 These are called Virgiliæ by Cicero; by Aratus, the
Pleiades,
О О»О·ПЉбЅ±ОґОµП‚; and they are placed at the neck of the Bull; and one
of Perseus’s feet touches the Bull in the Atlas Cœlestis.
197 This northern constellation is called Fides by Cicero;
but it must be the same with Lyra; because Lyra is placed in our maps as
Fides is here.
198 This is called Ales Avis by Cicero; and I doubt not but
the northern constellation Cygnus is here to be understood, for the
description and place of the Swan in the Atlas CЕ“lestis are the same
which Ales Avis has here.
200 The Water-bearer, one of the six southern signs in the
zodiac: he is described in our maps pouring water out of an urn, and
leaning with one hand on the tail of Capricorn, another southern sign.
201 When the sun is in Capricorn, the days are at the
shortest; and when in Cancer, at the longest.
202 One of the six southern signs.
203 Sagittarius, another southern sign.
204 A northern constellation.
205 A northern constellation.
206 A southern constellation.
207 This is Canis Major, a southern constellation. Orion and
the Dog are named together by Hesiod, who flourished many hundred years
before Cicero or Aratus.
208 A southern constellation, placed as here in the Atlas
CЕ“lestis.
209 A southern constellation, so called from the ship Argo,
in which Jason and the rest of the Argonauts sailed on their expedition
to Colchos.
210 The Ram is the first of the northern signs in the zodiac;
and the last southern sign is the Fishes; which two signs, meeting in
the zodiac, cover the constellation called Argo.
211 The river Eridanus, a southern constellation.
212 A southern constellation.
213 This is called the Scorpion in the original of Aratus.
214 A southern constellation.
215 A southern constellation.
216 The Serpent is not mentioned in Cicero’s translation; but
it is in the original of Aratus.
217 A southern constellation.
218 The Goblet, or Cup, a southern constellation.
219 A southern constellation.
220 Antecanis, a southern constellation, is the Little Dog,
and called
Antecanis in Latin, and
О ПЃОїОєбЅ»П‰ОЅ in Greek, because he rises
before the other Dog.
221 Pansætius, a Stoic philosopher.
223 The proboscis of the elephant is frequently called a
hand, because it is as useful to him as one. “They breathe, drink, and
smell, with what may not be improperly called a hand,” says Pliny, bk.
viii. c. 10.—
Davis.
224 The passage of Aristotle’s works to which Cicero here
alludes is entirely lost; but Plutarch gives a similar account.
225 Balbus does not tell us the remedy which the panther
makes use of; but Pliny is not quite so delicate: he says,
excrementis
hominis sibi medetur.
226 Aristotle says they purge themselves with this herb after
they fawn. Pliny says both before and after.
227 The cuttle-fish has a bag at its neck, the black blood of
which the Romans used for ink. It was called
atramentum.
228 The Euphrates is said to carry into Mesopotamia a large
quantity of citrons, with which it covers the fields.
229 Q. Curtius, and some other authors, say the Ganges is the
largest river in India; but Ammianus Marcellinus concurs with Cicero in
calling the river Indus the largest of all rivers.
230 These Etesian winds return periodically once a year, and
blow at certain seasons, and for a certain time.
231 Some read
mollitur, and some
molitur; the latter of
which P. Manucius justly prefers, from the verb
molo,
molis; from
whence, says he,
molares dentes, the grinders.
232 The weasand, or windpipe.
233 The epiglottis, which is a cartilaginous flap in the
shape of a tongue, and therefore called so.
234 Cicero is here giving the opinion of the ancients
concerning the passage of the chyle till it is converted to blood.
235 What Cicero here calls the ventricles of the heart are
likewise called auricles, of which there is the right and left.
236 The Stoics and Peripatetics said that the nerves, veins,
and arteries come directly from the heart. According to the anatomy of
the moderns, they come from the brain.
237 The author means all musical instruments, whether string
or wind instruments, which are hollow and tortuous.
238 The Latin version of Cicero is a translation from the
Greek of Aratus.
239 Chrysippus’s meaning is, that the swine is so inactive
and slothful a beast that life seems to be of no use to it but to keep
it from putrefaction, as salt keeps dead flesh.
240 Ales, in the general signification, is any large bird;
and
oscinis is any singing bird. But they here mean those birds which
are used in augury:
alites are the birds whose flight was observed by
the augurs, and
oscines the birds from whose voices they augured.
241 As the Academics doubted everything, it was indifferent
to them which side of a question they took.
242 The keepers and interpreters of the Sibylline oracles
were the Quindecimviri.
243 The popular name of Jupiter in Rome, being looked upon as
defender of the Capitol (in which he was placed), and stayer of the
State.
244 Some passages of the original are here wanting. Cotta
continues speaking against the doctrine of the Stoics.
245 The word
sortes is often used for the answers of the
oracles, or, rather, for the rolls in which the answers were written.
246 Three of this eminent family sacrificed themselves for
their country; the father in the Latin war, the son in the Tuscan war,
and the grandson in the war with Pyrrhus.
247 The Straits of Gibraltar.
248 The common reading is,
ex quo anima dicitur; but Dr.
Davis and M. Bouhier prefer
animal, though they keep
anima in the
text, because our author says elsewhere,
animum ex anima dictum, Tusc.
I. 1. Cicero is not here to be accused of contradictions, for we are to
consider that he speaks in the characters of other persons; but there
appears to be nothing in these two passages irreconcilable, and probably
anima is the right word here.
249 He is said to have led a colony from Greece into Caria,
in Asia, and to have built a town, and called it after his own name, for
which his countrymen paid him divine honors after his death.
250 Our great author is under a mistake here. Homer does not
say he met Hercules himself, but his
Εἴδωλον, his “visionary likeness;”
and adds that he himself
μετ’ ἀθανάτοισι θεοῖσι
П„бЅіПЃПЂОµП„О±О№ бјђОЅ ОёО±О»бЅ·бїѓП‚, ОєО±бЅ¶ бј”П‡ОµО№ ОєО±О»О»бЅ·ПѓП†П…ПЃОїП… бјОІО·ОЅ,
ПЂО±бї–ОґО± О”О№бЅёП‚ ОјОµОібЅ±О»ОїО№Ої ОєО±бЅ¶ бјПЃО·П‚ П‡ПЃП…ПѓОїПЂОµОґбЅ·О»ОїП….
which Pope translates—
A shadowy form, for high in heaven’s abodes
Himself resides, a God among the Gods;
There, in the bright assemblies of the skies,
He nectar quaffs, and Hebe crowns his joys.
251 They are said to have been the first workers in iron.
They were called Idæi, because they inhabited about Mount Ida in Crete,
and Dactyli, from
ОґбЅ±ОєП„П…О»ОїО№ (the fingers), their number being five.
252 From whom, some say, the city of that name was called.
253 Capedunculæ seem to have been bowls or cups, with handles
on each side, set apart for the use of the altar.—
Davis.
254 See Cicero de Divinatione, and Ovid. Fast.
255 In the consulship of Piso and Gabinius sacrifices to
Serapis and Isis were prohibited in Rome; but the Roman people afterward
placed them again in the number of their gods. See Tertullian’s Apol.
and his first book Ad Nationes, and Arnobius, lib. 2.—
Davis.
256 In some copies Circe, Pasiphae, and Г†a are mentioned
together; but Г†a is rejected by the most judicious editors.
257 They were three, and are said to have averted a plague by
offering themselves a sacrifice.
258 So called from the Greek word
ОёО±П…ОјбЅ±О¶П‰, to wonder.
259 She was first called Geres, from
gero, to bear.
260 The word is
precatione, which means the books or forms
of prayers used by the augurs.
261 Cotta’s intent here, as well as in other places, is to
show how unphilosophical their civil theology was, and with what
confusions it was embarrassed; which design of the Academic the reader
should carefully keep in view, or he will lose the chain of argument.
262 Anactes,
бјЊОЅО±ОєП„ОµП‚, was a general name for all kings, as we
find in the oldest Greek writers, and particularly in Homer.
263 The common reading is Aleo; but we follow Lambinus and
Davis, who had the authority of the best manuscript copies.
264 Some prefer Phthas to Opas (see Dr. Davis’s edition); but
Opas is the generally received reading.
269 So called from the Greek word
ОЅбЅ№ОјОїП‚,
lex, a law.
270 He is called
бЅ®ПЂО№П‚ in some old Greek fragments, and
ОџбЅ–ПЂО№П‚ by Callimachus in his hymn on Diana.
271 ОЈО±ОІбЅ±О¶бЅ·ОїП‚, Sabazius, is one of the names used for
Bacchus.
272 Here is a wide chasm in the original. What is lost
probably may have contained great part of Cotta’s arguments against the
providence of the Stoics.
273 Here is one expression in the quotation from Cæcilius
that is not commonly met with, which is
præstigias præstrinxit;
Lambinus gives
præstinxit, for the sake, I suppose, of playing on
words, because it might then be translated, “He has deluded my
delusions, or stratagems;” but
præstrinxit is certainly the right
reading.
274 The ancient Romans had a judicial as well as a military
prætor; and he sat, with inferior judges attending him, like one of our
chief-justices.
Sessum it prætor, which I doubt not is the right
reading, Lambinus restored from an old copy. The common reading was
sessum ite precor.
275 Picenum was a region of Italy.
276 The
sex primi were general receivers of all taxes and
tributes; and they were obliged to make good, out of their own fortunes,
whatever deficiencies were in the public treasury.
277 The Lætorian Law was a security for those under age
against extortioners, etc. By this law all debts contracted under
twenty-five years of age were void.
278 This is from Ennius—
Utinam ne in nemore Pelio securibus
Cæsa cecidisset abiegna ad terram trabes.
Translated from the beginning of the Medea of Euripides—
Μήδ’ ἐν νάπαισι Πηλίον πεσεῖν ποτε
П„ОјО·ОёОµбї–ПѓО± ПЂОµбЅ»ОєО·.
279 Q. Fabius Maximus, surnamed Cunctator.
280 Diogenes Laertius says he was pounded to death in a stone
mortar by command of Nicocreon, tyrant of Cyprus.
281 Elea, a city of Lucania, in Italy. The manner in which
Zeno was put to death is, according to Diogenes Laertius, uncertain.
282 This great and good man was accused of destroying the
divinity of the Gods of his country. He was condemned, and died by
drinking a glass of poison.
284 The common reading is,
in tympanidis rogum inlatus est.
This passage has been the occasion of as many different opinions
concerning both the reading and the sense as any passage in the whole
treatise.
Tympanum is used for a timbrel or drum,
tympanidia a
diminutive of it. Lambinus says
tympana “were sticks with which the
tyrant used to beat the condemned.” P. Victorius substitutes
tyrannidis for
tympanidis.
285 The original is
de amissa salute; which means the
sentence of banishment among the Romans, in which was contained the loss
of goods and estate, and the privileges of a Roman; and in this sense
L’Abbé d’Olivet translates it.
286 The forty-seventh proposition of the first book of Euclid
is unanimously ascribed to him by the ancients. Dr. Wotton, in his
Reflections upon Ancient and Modern Learning, says, “It is indeed a very
noble proposition, the foundation of trigonometry, of universal and
various use in those curious speculations about incommensurable
numbers.”
287 These votive tables, or pictures, were hung up in the
temples.
288 This passage is a fragment from a tragedy of Attius.
289 Hipponax was a poet at Ephesus, and so deformed that
Bupalus drew a picture of him to provoke laughter; for which Hipponax is
said to have written such keen iambics on the painter that he hanged
himself.
Lycambes had promised Archilochus the poet to marry his daughter to him,
but afterward retracted his promise, and refused her; upon which
Archilochus is said to have published a satire in iambic verse that
provoked him to hang himself.
290 Cicero refers here to an oracle approving of his laws,
and promising Sparta prosperity as long as they were obeyed, which
Lycurgus procured from Delphi.
291 Pro aris et focis is a proverbial expression. The
Romans, when they would say their all was at stake, could not express it
stronger than by saying they contended
pro aris et focis, for religion
and their firesides, or, as we express it, for religion and property.
292 Cicero, who was an Academic, gives his opinion according
to the manner of the Academics, who looked upon probability, and a
resemblance of truth, as the utmost they could arrive at.
295 It is unnecessary to give an account of the other names
here mentioned; but that of Lænas is probably less known. He was Publius
Popillius Lænas, consul 132
b.c., the year after the death of Tiberius
Gracchus, and it became his duty to prosecute the accomplices of
Gracchus, for which he was afterward attacked by Caius Gracchus with
such animosity that he withdrew into voluntary exile. Cicero pays a
tribute to the energy of Opimius in the first Oration against Catiline,
c. iii.
296 This phenomenon of the parhelion, or mock sun, which so
puzzled Cicero’s interlocutors, has been very satisfactorily explained
by modern science. The parhelia are formed by the reflection of the
sunbeams on a cloud properly situated. They usually accompany the
coronæ, or luminous circles, and are placed in the same circumference,
and at the same height. Their colors resemble that of the rainbow; the
red and yellow are towards the side of the sun, and the blue and violet
on the other. There are, however, coronæ sometimes seen without
parhelia, and
vice versГў. Parhelia are double, triple, etc., and in
1629, a parhelion of five suns was seen at Rome, and another of six suns
at Arles, 1666.
297 There is a little uncertainty as to what this age was,
but it was probably about twenty-five.
298 Cicero here gives a very exact and correct account of the
planetarium of Archimedes, which is so often noticed by the ancient
astronomers. It no doubt corresponded in a great measure to our modern
planetarium, or orrery, invented by the earl of that name. This
elaborate machine, whose manufacture requires the most exact and
critical science, is of the greatest service to those who study the
revolutions of the stars, for astronomic, astrologic, or meteorologic
purposes.
299 The end of the fourteenth chapter and the first words of
the fifteenth are lost; but it is plain that in the fifteenth it is
Scipio who is speaking.
300 There is evidently some error in the text here, for
Ennius was born 515
a.u.c., was a personal friend of the elder
Africanus, and died about 575
a.u.c., so that it is plain that we ought
to read in the text 550, not 350.
301 Two pages are lost here. Afterward it is again Scipio who
is speaking.
302 Two pages are lost here.
303 Both Ennius and Nævius wrote tragedies called
“Iphigenia.” Mai thinks the text here corrupt, and expresses some doubt
whether there is a quotation here at all.
304 He means Scipio himself.
305 There is again a hiatus. What follows is spoken by
Lælius.
306 Again two pages are lost.
307 Again two pages are lost. It is evident that Scipio is
speaking again in cap. xxxi.
308 Again two pages are lost.
309 Again two pages are lost.
310 Here four pages are lost.
311 Here four pages are lost.
312 Two pages are missing here.
314 About seven lines are lost here, and there is a great
deal of corruption and imperfection in the next few sentences.
315 Two pages are lost here.
316 The
Lex Curiata de Imperio, so often mentioned here,
was the same as the
Auctoritas Patrum, and was necessary in order to
confer upon the dictator, consuls, and other magistrates the
imperium,
or military command: without this they had only a
potestas, or civil
authority, and could not meddle with military affairs.
317 Two pages are missing here.
318 Here two pages are missing.
319 I have translated this very corrupt passage according to
Niebuhr’s emendation.
320 Assiduus, ab Г¦re dando.
322 Here four pages are missing.
323 Two pages are missing here.
324 Two pages are missing here.
325 Here twelve pages are missing.
326 Sixteen pages are missing here.
327 Here eight pages are missing.
328 A great many pages are missing here.
329 Several pages are lost here; the passage in brackets is
found in Nonius under the word “exulto.”
330 This and other chapters printed in smaller type are
generally presumed to be of doubtful authenticity.
331 The beginning of this book is lost. The two first
paragraphs come, the one from St. Augustine, the other from Lactantius.
332 Eight or nine pages are lost here.
333 Here six pages are lost.
334 Here twelve pages are missing.
335 We have been obliged to insert two or three of these
sentences between brackets, which are not found in the original, for the
sake of showing the drift of the arguments of Philus. He himself was
fully convinced that justice and morality were of eternal and immutable
obligation, and that the best interests of all beings lie in their
perpetual development and application. This eternity of Justice is
beautifully illustrated by Montesquieu. “Long,” says he, “before
positive laws were instituted, the moral relations of justice were
absolute and universal. To say that there were no justice or injustice
but that which depends on the injunctions or prohibitions of positive
laws, is to say that the radii which spring from a centre are not equal
till we have formed a circle to illustrate the proposition. We must,
therefore, acknowledge that the relations of equity were antecedent to
the positive laws which corroborated them.” But though Philus was fully
convinced of this, in order to give his friends Scipio and Lælius an
opportunity of proving it, he frankly brings forward every argument for
injustice that sophistry had ever cast in the teeth of reason.—
By the
original Translator.
336 Here four pages are missing. The following sentence is
preserved in Nonius.
337 Two pages are missing here.
338 Several pages are missing here.
339 He means Alexander the Great.
340 Six or eight pages are lost here.
341 A great many pages are missing here.
342 Six or eight pages are missing here.
343 Several pages are lost here.
344 This and the following chapters are not the actual words
of Cicero, but quotations by Lactantius and Augustine of what they
affirm that he said.
345 Twelve pages are missing here.
346 Eight pages are missing here.
347 Six or eight pages are missing here.
348 Catadupa, from
ОєО±П„бЅ° and
ОґОїбї–ПЂОїП‚, noise.
End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of Cicero's Tusculan Disputations
by Marcus Tullius Cicero
*** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK CICERO'S TUSCULAN DISPUTATIONS ***
***** This file should be named 14988-h.htm or 14988-h.zip *****
This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
http://www.gutenberg.net/1/4/9/8/14988/
Produced by Ted Garvin, Hagen von Eitzen and the PG Online Distributed
Proofreading Team.
Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions
will be renamed.
Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no
one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation
(and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without
permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules,
set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to
copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to
protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark. Project
Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you
charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If you
do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the
rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose
such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and
research. They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do
practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is
subject to the trademark license, especially commercial
redistribution.
*** START: FULL LICENSE ***
THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
(or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project
Gutenberg-tm License (available with this file or online at
http://gutenberg.net/license).
Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy
all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession.
If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the
terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or
entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.
1.B. "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark. It may only be
used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement
and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation"
or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the
collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an
individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are
located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from
copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative
works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg
are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project
Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by
freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with
the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by
keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project
Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others.
1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in
a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check
the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement
before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or
creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project
Gutenberg-tm work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning
the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United
States.
1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate
access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently
whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the
phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project
Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed,
copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.net
1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived
from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is
posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied
and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees
or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work
with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the
work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1
through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the
Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or
1.E.9.
1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional
terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked
to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the
permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work.
1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.
1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg-tm License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any
word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or
distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than
"Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version
posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.net),
you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a
copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other
form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.
1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided
that
- You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is
owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he
has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments
must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you
prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax
returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and
sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the
address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation."
- You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License. You must require such a user to return or
destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium
and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of
Project Gutenberg-tm works.
- You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any
money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days
of receipt of the work.
- You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.
1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael
Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark. Contact the
Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.
1.F.
1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm
collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain
"Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or
corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a
computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by
your equipment.
1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH F3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
DAMAGE.
1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with
your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with
the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a
refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity
providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to
receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy
is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further
opportunities to fix the problem.
1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS' WITH NO OTHER
WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by
the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance
with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production,
promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works,
harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees,
that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm
work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any
Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause.
Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm
Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers
including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists
because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from
people in all walks of life.
Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
assistance they need, is critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations.
To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4
and the Foundation web page at http://www.pglaf.org.
Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Its 501(c)(3) letter is posted at
http://pglaf.org/fundraising. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.
The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S.
Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered
throughout numerous locations. Its business office is located at
809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887, email
[email protected]. Email contact links and up to date contact
information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official
page at http://pglaf.org
For additional contact information:
Dr. Gregory B. Newby
Chief Executive and Director
[email protected]
Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation
Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
status with the IRS.
The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To
SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any
particular state visit http://pglaf.org
While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
approach us with offers to donate.
International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
ways including including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: http://pglaf.org/donate
Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works.
Professor Michael S. Hart is the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm
concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared
with anyone. For thirty years, he produced and distributed Project
Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support.
Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S.
unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily
keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition.
Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:
http://www.gutenberg.net
This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.