"Kant & Aesthetic Excellence" - читать интересную книгу автора (Gerwen Rob van)

We find that our judgements of taste should be universally agreed upon, but this is not a claim to their logical truth. This is illustrated by the fact that we do not think that something like the truth of these judgements could be established, for example, by enumerating natural properties. The only rather uncertain way to establish their 'correctness' is by eliminating those aspects of the involved experience, which might cloud the purity of the judgement.13 Instead, this validity claim is exemplary:14 the beautiful object is supposed to be an outstanding instance of a 'rule' that we cannot describe, but what kind of rule can this be?15 For example, in an herbarium examples of plants are depicted in such a way as to enable us to identify actual plants in nature. Some conventional system is at work here: we must understand the ways in which plants differ in general from their representations to remark their resemblances. We must reconcile differences in dimensionality, dimension, colour, mobility, et cetera. On top of this conventional system we must be aware of the various ways in which representations of distinct plants differ from one another. There are, indeed, rules involved in such herbal identifications, and each time we succeed in identifying a plant we will be able to provide a satisfactory description of the involved rule. Now, it cannot be this way with a concrete beautiful thing being an exemplary case of a 'rule'. Clearly we do not have herbarium-like books which have arranged all exemplary
cases of beautiful things into some hierarchy. Of course we do have books representing the paintings of subsequent ages, periods, styles, and painters, but, firstly, these are not books assembling all and only aesthetically excellent paintings and, secondly, they do not enable one to recognize beautiful artefacts of different kinds, such as aeroplanes, novels, musical works, sculptures, natural beauties, et cetera. To advocate the possibility or desirability of such a rule-governed objectivism would clearly be absurd. Apparently there is no satisfactory route for describing rules that would enable us to recognize beauty whenever we are supposed to be confronted with it, and there exists no system of rules by way of which we could identify a third case of beauty when confronted with two other acclaimed beautiful objects, nor does the notion of an example of beauty have a sense. Now, this might seem to furnish the suggestion that the meaning of 'beauty' resides in some family resemblance. Again, however, since this 'family' would comprise every perceptible object, this would merely beg the question. The idea then that beauty is exemplary of some undescribable rule is metaphorical at best at least if there is a literal sense in the first place to the involvement of rules in more straightforward cases of meaning attribution.16 This idea then of an undescribable rule needs elaboration. An important part of the interpretation of this metaphor is that in claiming universal validity we acknowledge that the free play